Next Article in Journal
Obtaining Expressions for Time-Dependent Functions That Describe the Unsteady Properties of Swirling Jets of Viscous Fluid
Previous Article in Journal
Schistosomiasis Model Incorporating Snail Predator as Biological Control Agent
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

A Logically Formalized Axiomatic Epistemology System Σ + C and Philosophical Grounding Mathematics as a Self-Sufficing System

by
Vladimir Olegovich Lobovikov
Laboratory for Applied System Investigations, Ural Federal University, 620075 Yekaterinburg, Russia
Mathematics 2021, 9(16), 1859; https://doi.org/10.3390/math9161859
Submission received: 2 June 2021 / Revised: 10 July 2021 / Accepted: 19 July 2021 / Published: 5 August 2021

Abstract

:
The subject matter of this research is Kant’s apriorism underlying Hilbert’s formalism in the philosophical grounding of mathematics as a self-sufficing system. The research aim is the invention of such a logically formalized axiomatic epistemology system, in which it is possible to construct formal deductive inferences of formulae—modeling the formalism ideal of Hilbert—from the assumption of Kant’s apriorism in relation to mathematical knowledge. The research method is hypothetical–deductive (axiomatic). The research results and their scientific novelty are based on a logically formalized axiomatic system of epistemology called Σ + C, constructed here for the first time. In comparison with the already published formal epistemology systems Ξ and Σ, some of the axiom schemes here are generalized in Σ + C, and a new symbol is included in the object-language alphabet of Σ + C, namely, the symbol representing the perfection modality, C: “it is consistent that…”. The meaning of this modality is defined by the system of axiom schemes of Σ + C. A deductive proof of the consistency of Σ + C is submitted. For the first time, by means of Σ + C, it is deductively demonstrated that, from the conjunction of Σ + C and either the first or second version of Gödel’s theorem of incompleteness of a formal arithmetic system, the formal arithmetic investigated by Gödel is a representation of an empirical knowledge system. Thus, Kant’s view of mathematics as a self-sufficient, pure, a priori knowledge system is falsified.

1. Introduction

“Before all, be it observed, that proper mathematical propositions are always judgements a priori, and not empirical, because they carry along with them the conception of necessity, which cannot be given by experience”.
I. Kant [1] (p. 18).
“The denial of deflationism leads us to a difference in the concepts of truth and proof. For the strict formalist, truth and proof are of course equivalent concepts: a sentence of mathematics is true if and only if it is provable, and as such truth is a deflationary concept. … the formalist believes that truth and proof are the same concept by definition”.
M. Pantsar [2] (p. 20).
There are infinitely many different modal logics. The quantity of possible combinations of different kinds of modality is immense. Even within the scope of the modal logic of knowledge, we need a set of significantly different modalities called “knowledge”, various combinations of which constitute different multimodal epistemic logics. Given that, in the broadly accepted definitions of “knowledge”, the words “true” and “provable” are exploited necessarily, the modal logic treating truth as modality [3,4] and the modal logic treating provability as modality [5,6,7,8,9,10] are indispensable to epistemology. In content philosophy, the word “knowledge” is naturally connected with many other modal terms (alethic, deontic, axiological, etc.); consequently, while inventing and elaborating a hypothetical multimodal formal axiomatic system of universal philosophical epistemology, one has to utilize not only proper epistemic modalities, but also many other concepts of modal metaphysics. This is the aim of the present article, namely, the invention (construct) of a novel, logically formalized, axiomatic system for a multimodal philosophy of knowledge. However, the concrete theme and the goal of the paper necessitate a restriction to the set of different kinds of modalities involved in the discourse.
The list of various kinds of modality to be addressed in this article is determined by the subject matter and the target of the research. At the present moment, we are equipped with the axiomatic epistemology system Σ, which was previously addressed in [11]. Is Σ sufficient for realizing the goal of the paper? If not, then which new modalities are to be added to Σ to make it an effective instrument of/for realizing the goal? To answer these questions adequately, we begin with a systematic explication of the subject matter of the research, its aim, and the means of/for realizing this aim.
In this article, the logically formalized multimodal axiomatic epistemology system Σ (or an option of its mutation) is used for the logical analysis of a system of philosophical foundations for mathematics, which (system) is made up of the following set of statements, ST1–ST5:
ST1—
Proper mathematical knowledge of ω is a priori. See, for instance, Kant [1] (pp. 16, 18);
ST2—
The truth of ω and the provability of ω are logically equivalent in the rationalistic optimism ideal created by Leibniz [12,13,14] and Hilbert [15,16,17,18,19,20]. For the rationalistic optimism ideal and Gödel’s philosophy, see also [21]. Incidentally, here, it is relevant to note that there is a nontrivial formal-axiological equivalence of “true” and “provable” [22], but the almost unknown “formal-axiological equivalence” and the well-known “formal-logical equivalence” are not identical;
ST3—
The consistency of proper mathematical statement or theory ω and the provability of consistency of ω are logically equivalent in Hilbert’s ideal of self-sufficient (self-dependent) mathematics;
ST4—
The truth of ω and the consistency of ω are logically equivalent (in the ideal);
ST5—
The truth of ω is logically equivalent to ω (in the ideal).
D. Hilbert was not alone; his rationalistic optimism ideal (norm) of mathematical activity was also attractive for Tarski and many other prominent mathematicians. Even while being aware of Gödel’s theorems of incompleteness, Tarski believed and wrote that it is good (desirable) for a mathematician to prove that ST2 is true in relation to a concrete mathematical statement or theory ω, if this proof is possible [23] (pp. 185–189). While being aware of Gödel’s theorems of incompleteness and taking them into account, Tselishchev wrote (in perfect accordance with Tarski) that proving consistency and completeness is a prescribed (obligatory) norm (duty) for a mathematician, if such proof is possible [24,25,26]. Here, the famous bimodal Kantian principle “obligation (duty) implies possibility” ( Op   p ) applies. As, according to the theorems of Gödel, proving the completeness of a formal arithmetic system (under the condition of its consistency) is impossible, there is no violation of the norm (the relevant obligation is abolished by modus tollens).
If Hilbert’s formalism ideal and program of/for the philosophical grounding of mathematics were to be fulfilled (i.e., if the ideal created by him was realized), then the system of mathematical knowledge (as a whole) would be self-sufficient (self-dependent). Unfortunately, there is today a widespread opinion (a statistical norm of thinking and affirming) that Hilbert’s ideal, and the formalism program targeted at realizing this ideal, were totally annihilated by Gödel’s theorems of incompleteness. However, this widespread opinion is not able to explain the philosophical foundation of/for Hilbert’s creation of the ideal and the formalism program in question. Those talking of Gödel’s termination of Hilbert’s formalism program do not recognize the possibility of the existence of a non-empty domain, in which context Hilbert’s ideal and the formalism program targeted at realizing this ideal are perfectly adequate even today (and will remain so forever). As such, the significance of Gödel’s famous work is reduced to the narrow limiting of the abovementioned non-empty domain, i.e., to the significance of establishing precise borders of/for that domain. The present paper aims at recognizing and explicating the reason of/for Hilbert’s creation of the formalism program, and at giving an exact definition of the realm of the program’s soundness, which is missed by the aforementioned papers.
By scrutinizing the above statements ST1–ST5, it is easy to extract a set of modalities that are indispensable for formulating ST1–ST5, as follows: “knows that…”; “a-priori knows that…”; “empirically knows that…”; “it is true that…”; “it is provable in the consistent theory that…”, “it is consistent that…”. The first five modalities are taken into an account by Σ, whereas the last is not. Therefore, to successfully address the research goal, it is necessary to modify Σ by adding the novel modality “Consistency” to it. Let the symbol Cω stand for “it is consistent that ω”. Given that the novel modality “C” (Consistency) is now added to Σ, let the symbol “Σ + C” be the name of/for the result of this addition to Σ. The general concept of this article is as such addressed in its basic form. Now let us move to the next paragraph, giving a precise definition of the multimodal formal axiomatic system Σ + C to be exploited in this paper.

2. Materials and Methods

We applied the abstract concepts and methods of discrete mathematics (especially algebra) and symbolic logic (especially modal and multimodal) to the materials of universal philosophical ontology, epistemology, axiology, history of philosophy, and the philosophical foundations of mathematics. The traditional materials and methods of the history of philosophy have been complemented by the axiomatic (hypothetic–deductive) method of logical reasoning. Not only has content analysis been exploited, but so too has formal theory investigation (formal inference construction).

3. Results

3.1. A Hitherto Never Published Logically Formalized Multimodal Axiomatic Epistemology and Axiology System Σ + C

As a result of adding the modality C (“It is consistent that…”) to the set of perfection modalities of the multimodal system Σ, and significantly generalizing the axiom scheme AX-5 of Σ, a new system (named “Σ + C”) has come into being. The axiomatic system Σ + C is a result of developing the formal axiomatic epistemological theory Ξ [27] and the formal axiomatic epistemological and axiological theory Σ [11]. In order to not repeat key sentences and phrases from my own previously published work, I have not given precise definitions of the notions “alphabet of object-language of Σ + C”, “term of Σ + C”, “formula of Σ + C”, and a few others. Definitions of these notions in the context of Σ + C are similar to corresponding definitions in the context of Σ. The reader can find such definitions in my already published (open access) work [28,29].
The proper logic axioms and inference rules of Σ and Σ + C are the same as those used in the classical logic of propositions. Thus, the proper logical foundations of Σ and Σ + C are identical, but the logically formalized systems constructed on these foundations are different. Although, at first glance, the definitions of Σ and Σ + C seem identical, strictly speaking, they are not. The object-languages of Σ and Σ + C have different alphabets, and the theories contain different sets of expressions, different sets of formulae, different sets of axioms, and different sets of theorems.
The modality symbols exploited in the present article are as follows. K, A, E, S, T, F, P, and D, respectively, stand for the modalities “agent Knows that…”; “agent A-priori knows that…”; “agent Empirically (a-posteriori) knows that…”; “under some conditions in some space-and-time a person (immediately or by means of some tools) Sensually perceives (has Sensual verification) that…”; “it is True that…”; “person has Faith (or believes) that…”; “it is Provable in the consistent theory that…”; and “there is an algorithm (a machine could be constructed) for Deciding that…”.
C, G, W, O, B, U, J, respectively, stand for the modalities “it is Consistent that…”; “it is (morally) Good that…”; “it is (morally) Wicked that…”’; “it is Obligatory that …”; “it is Beautiful that …”; “it is Useful that …”; and “it is Joyful, pleasant that…”.
In this paragraph of the article, the syntactical meanings of the modality symbols are defined precisely (although not manifestly) by the following system of schemes of proper axioms of multimodal philosophy theory Σ + C.
  • Axiom scheme AX-1: A α     ( β     β ) .
  • Axiom scheme AX-2: A α     ( ( α     β )     ( α     β ) ) .
  • Axiom scheme AX-3: A α     ( K α   &   ( ¬ ¬ α   & ¬   S α   &   ( β     Ω β ) ) ) .
  • Axiom scheme AX-4: E α     ( K α   &   ( ¬ α S α ¬ ( β     Ω β ) ) ) .
  • Axiom scheme AX-5: Ω α   α .
  • Axiom scheme AX-6: ( β   &   β )     β .
  • Axiom scheme AX-7: ( t i = + = t k )     ( G [ t i ]     G [ t k ] ) .
  • Axiom scheme AX-8: ( t i = + = g )     G [ t i ] .
  • Axiom scheme AX-9: ( t i = + = b )     W [ t i ] .
  • Axiom scheme AX-10: ( G α     ¬ W α ) .
  • Axiom scheme AX-11: ( W α     ¬ G α ) .
Definition scheme DF-1: γ is a name of/for ¬ ¬ γ (where γ is a formula of Σ + C).
In AX-3 and AX-4, the symbol Ω (belonging to the meta-language) only represents a (any) “perfection-modality”. Not all of the above-mentioned modalities are perfection-modalities. The set Δ of “perfections” (perfection-modalities) is {K, D, F, C, P, J, T, B, G, U, O, ⎕}.
Evidently, Δ is a subset of the set of all modalities under consideration in this article. Incorporating C into the set Δ of perfection-modalities is quite natural as “consistency” is an important perfection of a theoretical system [23] (pp. 185, 186). As a rule, de dicto modalities are attached to a dictum. Usually, the word “dictum is translated from Latin as “proposition (or sentence)”, but, in principle, it is possible to generalize its meaning in such a manner that a theoretical (deductive) system would be a dictum as well.
A justification of AX-10 and AX-11 can be found in the book [30] devoted to the formal logic of evaluations. However, the almost unknown (unhabitual) axiom schemes AX-7, AX-8, and AX-9 represent not the formal logic, but a formal axiology (universal theory of value forms). The notion “formal logic” is not logically equivalent to the notion “formal axiology”; consequently, “formal logic inconsistency” and “formal axiological inconsistency” are not synonyms. The significant logical difference between the notions “formal-axiological contradiction” and “formal logical contradiction” explains the non-intuitive possibility of a deductive proof of the formal-axiological inconsistency of formal arithmetic theory [31,32].

3.2. Defining Semantics of/for the Multimodal Formal Theory Σ + C

In the above section, the definition of Σ + C has been deliberately deprived of its philosophical content (owing to the relevant abstraction). The axiomatic theory Σ + C is a multimodal one, but thus far, the actual contents of modalities have not been addressed sufficiently, and the theory of Σ + C has been considered to be a formal one. In this section, we attempt to relax the formality of Σ + C and address the actual meaning of the modalities under consideration in the multimodal theory Σ + C. On the syntactical level of the artificial language of Σ + C, its modal symbols are defined by the above axiom schemes (AX1–AX11).
In the present article, it is presumed that the semantic meanings of the proper logical symbols of the artificial language of classical symbolic logic are already well defined. As the proper logic symbols are well known, there is no need to define them here. On the contrary, the unusual symbols of the artificial language of Σ + C require systematic definition.
Defining the semantic meanings involves defining the interpretation function. To define the interpretation function, one has to define (1) the set that plays the role of “domain (or field) of interpretation” (let the interpretation domain be denoted by the letter M) and (2) a “valuator (evaluator)”, V. In a standard interpretation of Σ + C, M is a set in which every element has: (1) one and only one axiological value from the set {good, bad}; (2) one and only one ontological value from the set {exists, not-exists}.
The axiological variables (z, x, y, zi, xk, ym) take their values from the set M.
The axiological constants “b” and “g” mean “bad” and “good”, respectively.
Valuating an element of M using a concrete (fixed) interpreter V involves ascribing an axiological value (either good or bad) to that element. The interpreter V may be either collective or individual. A change in V can definitely change some of the relative evaluations, but it cannot change the laws of the two-valued algebra of formal axiology, which are absolute rather than relative evaluations; that is, they are such and only such constant valuation-functions that have the value g (good) under any possible combination of values of their axiological variables. Although V is a variable that takes its value from the set of all possible interpreters, a perfectly defined interpretation of Σ + C necessarily implies that the value of V is fixed. A change in V necessarily implies a change in interpretation.
In the present article, “e” and “n” represent “… exists” and “… not-exists”, respectively. The signs “e” and “n” are “ontological constants”. In a standard interpretation of Σ + C, one and only one element of the set {{g, e}, {g, n}, {b, e}, {b, n}} corresponds to every element of M. The signs “e” and “n” belong to the meta-language. By definition, “e” and “n” do not belong to the alphabet of the object-language of Σ + C. Nevertheless, “e” and “n” are indirectly represented in the object-language of Σ + C by means of square-bracketing: “ t i exists” is represented by [ t i ] ; “ t i does not exist” is represented by ¬ [ t i ] . This means that square-bracketing is intrinsic to the formal-axiological and ontological semantics of Σ + C.
N-placed terms of Σ + C are interpreted as n-placed evaluation-functions, defined on the set M. “One-placed evaluation-functions” are laid out in Table 1. (Here, the upper index 1 immediately after a capital letter means that this letter represents a one-placed evaluation-function).
In Table 1, the one-placed term B11x is interpreted as the one-placed evaluation-function “being (existence) of (what, whom) x”; N11x is the evaluation-function “non-being (nonexistence) of (what, whom) x”. C11x—“consistency of (what, whom) x”; I11x—“inconsistency of (what, whom) x”; Z11x—“formal-axiological inconsistency (or absolute inconsistency) of (what, whom) x”; S11x—“x’s self-contradiction”; U11x—“absolute non-being of (what, whom) x”; A11x—“absolute being of (what, whom) x”; G11x—“absolute goodness of (what, whom) x”, or “absolute good (what, who) x”; P11x—“positive evaluation of (what, whom) x”; H11x—“negative evaluation of (what, whom) x”; R11x—“resistance to (what, whom) x”. Concerning additional examples of one-placed evaluation-functions, see [11,27,33].
Two-placed evaluation-functions are shown in Table 2. (Here, the upper index 2 immediately after a capital letter means that this letter represents a two-placed function).
In Table 2, the two-placed term K2xy is interpreted as the evaluation-function “being of both x and y together”, or “joint being of x with y”. S2xy is interpreted as the “separation, divorcement between x and y”. The term X2xy—the evaluation-function “y’s being without x”, or “joint being of y with nonbeing of x”. T2xy—“termination of x by y”. Z2xy—“y’s contradiction to (with) x”. P2xy—“preservation, conservation, protection of x by y”. C2xy is interpreted as the evaluation-function “y’s existence, presence in x”. E2xy—“equivalence, identity (of values) of x and y”. V2xy—“choosing and realizing such and only such an element of the set {x, y} that is: (1) the best one, if both x and y are good; (2) the least bad one, if both x and y are bad; (3) the good one, if x and y have opposite values”. (Thus, V2xy means an excluding choice and realization of only the optimal between x and y). The term N2xy is interpreted as the evaluation-function “realizing neither x nor y”. Y2xy is interpreted as the evaluation-function “realizing a not-excluding-choice result, i.e., (1) realizing K2xy if both x and y are good, and (2) realizing V2xy otherwise”. Additional exemplifications of two-placed evaluation-functions may be found in [11,27,33].
To prevent possible misunderstandings of the present article, it is relevant to highlight here that in a standard interpretation of Σ + C, the signs B11x, N11x, C11x, K2xy, C2xy, E2xy, and V2xy do not represent predicates, but n-placed evaluation-functions.
If an interpretation of Σ + C is defined, then expressions of the object-language of Σ + C, with the forms ( t i = + = t k ) , ( t i = + = g ) , and ( t i = + = b ) , are representations of predicates in Σ + C. Following the semantics of Σ + C, if t i is a term of Σ + C, then, in a definite interpretation, a formula of Σ + C with the form [ t i ] is either a true or false proposition, “ t i exists”. Thus, in a standard interpretation, formula [ t i ] is true if and only if t i has the ontological value “e (exists)” in that interpretation. Additionally, by definition, the formula [ t i ] is false in a standard interpretation of Σ + C if and only if t i has the ontological value “n (not-exists)” in that interpretation.
Following the semantics of Σ + C, in a standard interpretation of Σ + C, the formula scheme ( t i = + = t k ) is a proposition of the form “ t i is formal-axiologically equivalent to t k ”; this proposition is true if and only if (in that interpretation) the terms t i and t k obtain identical axiological values (from the set {good, bad}) under any possible combination of axiological values of their axiological variables.
Following the semantics of Σ + C, in a standard interpretation, the formula scheme ( t i = + = b ) is a proposition with the form “ t i is a formal-axiological contradiction” (or “ t i is formal-axiologically, or invariantly, or absolutely bad”); this proposition is true if and only if (in that interpretation) the term t i acquires the axiological value “bad” under any possible combination of axiological values of the axiological variables.
Following the semantics of Σ + C, in a standard interpretation, the formula scheme ( t i = + = g ) is a proposition with the form “ t i is a formal-axiological law” (or “ t i is formal-axiologically, or invariantly, or absolutely good”); this proposition is true if and only if (in the interpretation) the term t i acquires the axiological value “good” under any possible combination of axiological values of the axiological variables.
In light of the above-given sematic meaning of ( t i = + = t k ) in Σ + C, we must highlight the homonymy of the words “is”, “means”, “implies”, “entails”, and “equivalence” in natural language. On the one hand, in natural language, these words may possess their well-known formal logical meanings. On the other hand, in natural language, the same words may stand for the above-defined formal-axiological equivalence relation “= + =”. This ambiguity of natural language must be taken into account, and these different meanings must be separated systematically; otherwise, the homonymy can lead to logic-linguistic paradoxes.
Given the above-presented formal-axiological and ontological semantics of Σ + C, it is clear that the two-valued algebraic system of formal axiology contains nothing but an abstract theory of evaluation relativity. In the theory of relativity, the formal-axiological laws (consistently good evaluation-functions) are invariants in relation to all possible transformations of interpreter V.
Thus, although it is an indisputable fact that relativity (and mutability) in empirical valuations does exist, valuation invariants (immutable universal laws of valuation relativity) do exist [34].

3.3. A Deductive Proof of the Logic Consistency of Formal Theory Σ + C

To create the proof, first of all, we must replace the meta-language of Σ + C with its object-language. To do this, we must switch from the above-formulated axiom schemes AX1–AX11 and the definition scheme DF-1 to the following axioms AX1 *–AX11 * and the definition DF-1 *, respectively.
  • Axiom AX-1 *: Ap     ( q     q ) .
  • Axiom AX-2 *: Ap     ( ( p     q )     ( p     q ) ) .
  • Axiom AX-3 *: Ap     ( Kp   &   ( ¬ ¬ p   &   ¬ Sp   &   ( q     q ) ) ) .
  • Axiom AX-4 *: Ep     ( Kp   &   ( ¬ p   Sp   ¬ ( q     q ) ) ) .
  • Axiom AX-5 *: p     p .
  • Axiom AX-6 *: ( q   &   q )     q .
  • Axiom AX-7 *: ( B 1 1 x = + = C 1 1 x )     ( G [ B 1 1 x ]     G [ C 1 1 x ] ) .
  • Axiom AX-8 *: ( B 1 1 x = + = g )     G [ B 1 1 x ] .
  • Axiom AX-9 *: ( B 1 1 x = + = b )     W [ B 1 1 x ] .
  • Axiom AX-10 *: ( Gp     ¬ Wp ) .
  • Axiom AX-11 *: ( Wp     ¬ Gp ) .
Definition DF-1 *: p is a name of/for ¬ ¬ p , i.e., ( p     ¬ ¬ p ) .
Next, we give a precise definition of/for the function £, which is an interpretation of the formal theory Σ + C (it is worth emphasizing that “t” here stands for “true” and “f” stands for “false”). The interpretation function £ is defined by the following items:
(1)
£ ( ω     π ) = ( £ ω     £ π ) for any formulae ω and π, and also for any binary connective ⊕ of classical logic;
(2)
£ ¬ ω = ¬ £ ω for any formula ω;
(3)
£ Ap = f ;
(4)
£ q = f ;
(5)
£ q = t ;
(6)
£ p = t ;
(7)
£ ( p     q ) = f ;
(8)
£ p = f ;
(9)
£ Kp = f ;
(10)
£ ¬ p = t ;
(11)
£ Sp = t ;
(12)
£ ( q     q ) = f ;
(13)
£ Ep = f ;
(14)
£ p = t ;
(15)
£ q = f ;
(16)
£ ( B 1 1 x = + = C 1 1 x ) = t ;
(17)
£ G [ B 1 1 x ] = t ;
(18)
£ G [ C 1 1 x ] = t ;
(19)
£ ( B 1 1 x = + = g ) = f ;
(20)
£ ( B 1 1 x = + = b ) = f ;
(21)
£ G [ B 1 1 x ] = f ;
(22)
£ W [ B 1 1 x ] = f ;
(23)
£ Gp = t ;
(24)
£ Wp = f ;
(25)
¬ p = f .
Following the interpretation  £ of the formal theory Σ + C, all the axioms AX1 *–AX11 * are true, the equivalence DF-1 * is true, and the derivation rules conserve truthfulness; consequently, a model of/for Σ + C exists, and the formal theory Σ + C is thus logically consistent.

4. Discussion

4.1. Some Special Qualities of the Logically Formalized Axiomatic Epistemology System Σ + C

Certainly, Σ + C is not a normal modal logic system following Kripke’s definition of the term [35,36,37]. This is because the formula schemes ( β     β ) and ( ( α     β )     ( α     β ) ) are not provable in Σ + C, and neither is Gödel’s necessitation rule. However, it is possible to easily obtain a normal modal logic system via modus ponens by adding the assumption Aα to Σ + C. Nevertheless, according to Σ + C, a discussion of empirical knowledge and of knowledge in general is beyond the domain of normal modal logic.
Generally speaking, the formula scheme ( α     T α ) is not provable in Σ + C. However, adding the assumption Aα to Σ + C constructs a system (let us call it “Σ + C + Aα”) in which ( α     T α ) is provable.
In the context of epistemic modal logic, it is notable that the well-known formula ( Kq     q ) is not provable in Σ + C. Being accepted as a strictly universal principle, ( Kq     q ) contradicts evolutionary epistemology, wherein belief revision and knowledge revision are addressed. Thus, Σ + C is a more realistic model of reasoning for empirical knowledge and knowledge in general (in comparison with the epistemologies accepting ( Kq     q ) as a necessarily universal principle). Relativity, flexibility, and flow in empirical knowledge do exist. This is a fact of the history of cognition. Consequently, if one accepts that evolutionary epistemology is rational, then accepting the formula ( Kq     q ) as a theorem of epistemic logic is not rational. Evolutionary epistemology necessitates that, in general, the modal logic of knowledge is not normal [27]. According to Σ + C, the normal modal logic of knowledge is rational only in the very rare cases in which the assumption Aα is true. Although ( Kq     q ) is not a theorem in Σ + C, the weaker formula ( Kq     q ) is derivable in Σ + C. One significant difference between Σ and Σ + C is that the formulae ( Oq     q ) ,   ( Gq     q ) ,   ( Tq     q ) and ( Pq     q ) , which are philosophically important, are formally derivable in Σ + C (from the axiom scheme AX-5 via relevant substitutions), but not in Σ. One of the novel benefits of the system Σ + C constructed here is its justification of the nontrivial bimodal “Kant principle”, modeled by the theorem (Op ⊃ ◊p). (Here I shall abstain from discussing the problem of Kant’s authorship of this bimodal principle of ethics and jurisprudence, as it would be a deviation from the main theme and goal of the article). Another important benefit (and significant novelty) of Σ + C is addressed in the following section. This significant benefit (and novelty) is the main concern of this paper.

4.2. Logical Consequences of Applying Σ + C to the Conjunction of Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems and Philosophical Views of Kant and Hilbert for Proper Mathematical Knowledge System as a Whole

Now let us apply the axiomatic system Σ + C to the set of statements ST1–ST5 formulated in the introduction, which model Kant’s and Hilbert’s philosophies of mathematics. Within Σ + C, by means of its artificial language, the statements ST1–ST5 (formulated in the Introduction) are represented as the following formulae ST1 *–ST5 *, respectively. In these formulae, ω means either a proper mathematical statement or a proper mathematical theory, and A, T, P, and C, respectively, represent the modalities “it is A-priori known that …”; “it is True that…”; “it is Provable in the consistent theory that…”; and “it is Consistent that…”.
  • ST1 *: A ω .
  • ST2 *: ( T ω     P ω ) .
  • ST3 *: ( C ω     PC ω ) .
  • ST4 *: ( T ω     C ω ) .
  • ST5 *: ( T ω     ω ) .
Now let us construct formal proofs of/for the following theorems of Σ + C.
Theorem 1. 
( A ω     ( T ω     ω ) ) ; ( A ω     ( T ω     P ω ) ) ; ( A ω     ( T ω     C ω ) ) ; ( A ω     ( T ω     D ω ) ) ; ( A ω     ( P ω     D ω ) ) . The following chain of formula schemes is the formal proof of Theorem 1.
  • A α     ( K α   &   ( ¬ ¬ α   &   ¬ S α   &   ( β     Ω β ) ) : axiom-scheme AX-3.
  • A α     ( K α   &   ( ¬ ¬ α   &   ¬ S α   &   ( β     Ω β ) ) : from 1 by elimination of .
  • A α : assumption.
  • ( K α   &   ( ¬ ¬ α   &   ¬ S α   &   ( β     Ω β ) : from 2 and 3 by modus ponens.
  • ( β     Ω β ) : from 4 by elimination of & .
  • ( β     Ω β ) : from 3 and 5 by the rule (It is formulated as follows: A α ,   β   |   β ) of elimination of ⎕.
  • A α   |   ( β     Ω β ) : by 1–6.
  • A α   |   ( β     Ξ β ) : from 7 by substituting Ξ for Ω.
  • A α   |   ( Ξ β     β ) : from 8 by commutativity of .
  • A α   |   ( Ξ β     Ω β ) : from 9 and 7 by transitivity of .
  • A α   |   ( Ω β     β ) : from 7 by commutativity of .
  • |   ( A α     ( Ω β     β ) ) : from 11 by introduction of .
  • |   ( A ω     ( T ω     ω ) ) : from 12 by substituting (T for Ω) and (ω for α and β).
  • |   ( A α     ( Ξ β     Ω β ) ) : from 10 by introduction of .
  • ( A ω     ( T ω     P ω ) ) : from 14 by substituting: (T for Ξ); (P for Ω); (ω for α and β).
  • ( A ω     ( T ω     C ω ) ) : from 14 by substituting: (T for Ξ); (C for Ω); (ω for α and β).
  • ( A ω     ( T ω     D ω ) ) : from 14 by substituting: (T for Ξ); (D for Ω); (ω for α and β).
  • ( A ω     ( P ω     D ω ) ) : from 14 by substituting: (P for Ξ); (D for Ω); (ω for α and β).
The succession 1–6 is a formal derivation of ( β     Ω β ) from the assumption Aα. The succession 1–10 is a formal derivation of ( Ξ β     Ω β ) from the assumption Aα. The chain 1–13 is a formal inference of ( A ω     ( T ω     ω ) ) . The chain 1–15 is a formal inference of ( A ω     ( T ω     P ω ) ) . The chain 1—16 is a formal derivation of ( A ω     ( T ω     C ω ) ) . The succession 1–17 is a formal inference of ( A ω     ( T ω     D ω ) ) . The chain 1–18 is a formal inference of ( A ω     ( P ω     D ω ) ) .
Corollary: from the conjunction of the above-proven Theorem 1 and Gödel’s first theorem of incompleteness, it follows logically that ¬ A ω .
Theorem 2. 
( A ω     ( C ω     P C ω ) . The formal proof of this is given by the following succession of formulae schemes.
(1)
A α   |   ( β     Ω β ) , proven by succession 1–6 in the above-constructed formal proof of Theorem 1.
(2)
A α   |   ( Ξ β     Ω Ξ β ) , inferred from (1) by substituting (Ξβ for β).
(3)
|   ( A α     ( β     Ω β ) , inferred from (2) by the rule of introduction of .
(4)
|   ( A ω     ( C ω     PC ω ) , inferred from (3) by substituting (C for Ξ); (P for Ω) and (ω for α and β).
Corollary: from the conjunction of the above-proven Theorem 2 and Gödel’s second theorem of incompleteness, it follows logically that ¬ A ω .
Professional mathematicians and logicians are often skeptical of Leibniz’s belief (dream) that developing a modal propositional logic can help in discussing, precisely formulating, and effectively solving some (if not many) proper philosophical questions. Why this concrete, propositional logic? Why not, for instance, first-order predicate logic (or some more general, richer, or stronger logic system)? These questions are natural and nontrivial. My answer is the following. According to the above-proven Theorem 1, within the formal axiomatic epistemology system Sigma + C, it is formally provable that (Aω (Tω ↔ Dω)), (Aω (Pω ↔ Dω)). In the standard epistemological interpretation, the theorem schemes (Aω (Tω ↔ Dω)), (Aω (Pω ↔ Dω)) mean that an a priori knowledge system is decidable. As first-order predicate logic is notoriously not decidable, it cannot be a proper logical part (logical subsystem) of a formalized system of proper a priori knowledge. Consequently, first-order predicate logic cannot offer a proper logical basis of universal epistemology that is common to both the empirical and a priori knowledge subsystems. Many other respected and consistent logic systems (that are more general, rich, and powerful than first-order predicate logic) are either not complete, or are not decidable; consequently, they are not able to provide a proper logical basis of/for a logically formalized universal epistemology that consistently combines both empiricism and a priority in the philosophy of knowledge. It is therefore quite reasonable to use propositional logic for the role in question, because propositional logic is consistent, complete, and decidable, and consequently, it is compatible with the a priority of epistemology (while first-order predicate logic and the a priority of epistemology are not compatible, given the theorem schemes (Aω (Tω ↔ Dω))), (Aω (Pω ↔ Dω)). However, I agree that first-order predicate logic is an adequate—and in some cases may even be the best—proper logical basis for the formalization of many empirical knowledge systems.

5. Conclusions

Kant emphasized that proper mathematical knowledge is purely a priori. This is especially highlighted not only in his Critique of Pure Reason [1], but also in his Prolegomena [38]. At first glance, Kantean philosophy of mathematics looks quite reasonable and veracious; however, from the conjunction of the axiomatic epistemology system Σ + C and the famous incompleteness theorems of Gödel, it follows that Kant’s statement of the a priority of mathematical knowledge is false. Moreover, it is formally provable in Σ + C that ( A ω     ( ω     T ω ) ) ; consequently, those who do not agree with the equivalence ( ω     T ω ) must also disagree with Kant’s assertion (modeled by Aω). Additionally, it is formally provable in Σ + C that ( A ω     ( T ω     C ω ) ) ; consequently, if one negates ( T ω     C ω ) , then one must also negate Aω. This means that mathematical knowledge as a whole is not an a priori system—rather, it is an empirical one, and only some small (but nevertheless very important) aspects are a priori. As such, it is evident and formally demonstrable that, in Σ + C, Hilbert’s ideal and program of philosophical grounding mathematics as a self-sufficient system logically follow from Kant’s presumption that any proper mathematical statements and systems of knowledge are a priori. If Kant’s presumption was correct, then, by means of Σ + C, Hilbert’s ideal and program would be well grounded, convincingly explained, and totally vindicated. However, Kant’s presumption is wrong; hence, the significance of Hilbert’s ideal and program is limited. However, notwithstanding its limitations, it is fairly adequate, and works effectively within its own reduced domain of applicability.
In principle, it seems that the conclusions concerning Kantian a priority, obtained via = the complex formal axiomatic theory Σ + C, may be obtained more easily via natural logic. However, in my opinion, this is only true in the case of some relations. Sometimes, simplicity is too expensive, coming at the cost of significant losses of precision and rigor. Unfortunately, in the humanities, confined to natural language and natural logic, Kant’s a priority is barely addressed, and any conclusions on it are not convincing. The present article does not mainly concern Kant as a representative of the humanities, but rather concerns D. Hilbert as a formally minded mathematician striving to establish mathematics as a self-sufficing system, who exploits Kant’s a priority to do so. In relation to Hilbert’s program, an analogous skepticism can be developed. There are many respectable creative mathematicians (for example, H. Poincaré [39]) who use intuition, construction, and natural logic exclusively; they have a critical attitude towards D. Hilbert’s formalism and B. Russell’s logicism in addressing the philosophical foundations of mathematics and physics. Nevertheless, in my opinion, Hilbert’s formalism is heuristically important—sometimes, it leads to ground-breaking nontrivial scientific discoveries; for instance, in meta-mathematics and mathematical physics.
As such, the above-presented (but not exhaustively addressed) trend of constructing and investigating multimodal, formal, axiomatic philosophical systems from Ξ, Σ, and Σ + C can also promise nontrivial discoveries in philosophical knowledge, for example, in proper philosophical formal ontology, formal epistemology, and formal axiology. Such discoveries may have applications in the philosophies of science, logic, ethics, aesthetics, and jurisprudence, and in philosophical theology. They may also be applicable to physics. At the very end of the 19th century and in the first half of the 20th century, many celebrated mathematicians were interested in addressing the difficult (even paradoxical) situation of mathematical physics. D. Hilbert was among these famous mathematicians. He tried to apply his idea of logically formalized axiomatic theories to the development of mathematical physics by creating a solid basis for it [20,40]. I have attempted to continue this by applying the formal axiomatic theory Σ to a philosophical grounding of classical mechanics [28,29]. The results are as follows. I have constructed “a formal deductive inference of the law of inertia in Σ from the assumption of knowledge a-priori-ness” [28]. I have also constructed “a formal deductive inference of the law of conservation of energy from assuming a-priori-ness of knowledge in Σ” [29]. However, interesting themes for discussion remain, and difficult theoretical problems await solutions. I propose that the research submitted here may be advanced in two ways.
Firstly, in the future, it would be worth attempting to further develop the formal axiomatic epistemology and axiology theory Σ + C by modifying it. However, it is not quite clear whether the above-presented set of axiom schemes of Σ + C is sufficient for adequately mathematically modeling the possible application domains. At present, it is still not possible to exactly formulate some aspects of the problem of completeness of Σ + C. The syntax of Σ + C has been sufficiently elaborated and represented, as have the formal aspects of the semantics of Σ + C. However, the content of the semantics of Σ + C, namely, the relationship between the standard interpretation of Σ + C and the as-yet indefinite (unrestricted) application domain of Σ + C, needs to be investigated further. Some of the content-related intuitions underlying the formal theory probably remain unformulated because they are too vague and not well recognized. I feel that the content aspect of the semantics of Σ + C (its relationship to the external world) has yet to undergo significant development and elaboration. This analysis of the incompletely defined subject matter of the axiomatic epistemology and axiology theory Σ + C may transform Σ + C into a qualitatively new formal theory. In particular, in the future, some qualitatively new nontrivial axiom schemes may be added to Σ + C.
Secondly, in the future, the possibility of applying the two-valued algebra of formal axiology to some other necessarily universal laws of nature should be addressed; for example, to the laws of conservation in physics. Such hypothetical applications would be theoretically interesting, although we should be prepared for the failure of some of these intellectual experiments. Let us try and see. Regardless, I believe that the application of Σ + C and its modifications to philosophically grounding physics is worth discussing and developing further. Further hypothetical modifications of Σ + C and the resulting applications are future vistas.

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Institutional Review Board Statement

Not applicable, as the study did not involve humans or animals.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable, as the study did not involve humans.

Data Availability Statement

Not applicable, as the study did not report any data.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Kant, I. The Critique of Pure Reason. Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals. The Critique of Practical Reason. Preface and Introduction to the Metaphysical Elements of Ethics. General Introduction to the Metaphysics of Morals. The Science of Right. The Critique of Judgement. In Great Books of the Western World. V. 39: Kant; Adler, M.J., Ed.; Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc.: Chicago, IL, USA; London, UK, 1994. [Google Scholar]
  2. Pantsar, M. Truth, Proof and Gödelian Arguments: A Defense of Tarskian Truth in Mathematics. Philosophical Studies from the University of Helsinki 23; Department of Philosophy, Department of Social and Moral Philosophy, Helsinki University: Tampere, Finland, 2009. [Google Scholar]
  3. Linsky, B. Truth at a world is a modality. Philosophia 1991, 20, 387–394. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Woleński, J. Truth as Modality; University of Information, Technology and Management: Rzeszow, Poland, 2016; Available online: http://ojs.philosophy.spbu.ru/index.php/lphs/article/viewFile/370/377 (accessed on 4 August 2021).
  5. Artemov, S.N.; Beklemishev, L.D. Provability logic. In Handbook of Philosophical Logic, 2nd ed.; Gabbay, D., Guenthner, F., Eds.; Kluwer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2004; Volume 13, pp. 229–403. [Google Scholar]
  6. Beklemishev, L.; Visser, A. Problems in the Logic of Provability. In Mathematical Problems from Applied Logic I, International Mathematical Series; Gabbay, D.M., Goncharov, S.S., Zakharyaschev, M., Eds.; Springer: New York, NY, USA, 2006; Volume 4, pp. 77–136. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  7. Boolos, G. The Logic of Provability; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
  8. Boolos, G.; Sambin, G. Provability: The emergence of a mathematical modality. Studia. Logica. 1991, 50, 1–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Ivin, A.A. Logic of Norms [Logika Norm]; Izdatel’stvo Moskovskogo Universiteta: Moscow, Russia, 1973. (In Russian) [Google Scholar]
  10. Kuznetsov, A.V.; Muravitsky, A. Provability as Modality [Dokazuemost’ kak modal’nost’]. In Actual Problems of Logic and Methodology of Science [Aktual’nye Problemy Logiki i Metodologii Nauki]; Popovich, M.V., Ed.; Naukova Dumka: Kyiv, Ukraine, 1980; pp. 193–230. (In Russian) [Google Scholar]
  11. Lobovikov, V.O. Knowledge logic and algebra of formal axiology: A formal axiomatic epistemology theory sigma used for precise defining the exotic condition under which Hume-and-Moore doctrine of logically unbridgeable gap between statements of being and statements of value is falsified. Antinomies 2020, 20, 7–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Leibniz, G.W. General Investigations concerning the Analysis of Concepts and Truths [Generales Inquisitiones de Analysi Notionum et Veritatum]. In Leibniz’ Unpublished Booklets and Fragments from Royal Library of Hannover [Opuscules et Fragments Inédits de Leibniz: Extraits de la Bibliothèque royale de Hanovre]; Couturat, L., Ed.; Alcan: Paris, France, 1903; pp. 356–399. [Google Scholar]
  13. Leibniz, G.W. Philosophical Papers and Letters; D. Reidel: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1969. [Google Scholar]
  14. Leibniz, G.W. New Essays on Human Understanding; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1981. [Google Scholar]
  15. Hilbert, D. On the Infinite. In From Frege to Gödel. A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1897–1931; Van Heijenoort, J., Ed.; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1967; pp. 367–392. [Google Scholar]
  16. Hilbert, D. Foundations of Geometry [Grundlagen der Geometrie], 2nd English ed.; Leo, U., Translator; Open Court Publishing Co.: La Salle, IL, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
  17. Hilbert, D. Axiomatic thought. In From Kant to Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics; Ewald, W.B., Ed.; Oxford University Press Inc.: Oxford, UK, 1996; Volume 2, pp. 1105–1115. [Google Scholar]
  18. Hilbert, D. The new grounding of mathematics: First report. In From Kant to Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics; Ewald, W.B., Ed.; Oxford University Press Inc.: Oxford, UK, 1996; Volume 2, pp. 1115–1134. [Google Scholar]
  19. Hilbert, D. The logical foundations of mathematics. In From Kant to Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics; Ewald, W.B., Ed.; Oxford University Press Inc.: Oxford, UK, 1996; Volume 2, pp. 1134–1147. [Google Scholar]
  20. Hilbert, D. Logic and the knowledge of nature. In From Kant to Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics; Ewald, W.B., Ed.; Oxford University Press Inc.: Oxford, UK, 1996; Volume 2, pp. 1157–1165. [Google Scholar]
  21. Tselishchev, V.V. The Rationalistic Optimism and Kurt Gödel’s Philosophy [Racionalisticheskij optimizm i filosofiya Kurta Gyodelya]. Philos. Quest. 2013, 8, 12–23. (In Russian) [Google Scholar]
  22. Lobovikov, V.O.K. Gödel’s incompleteness theorems and a hitherto unknown non-trivial formal equivalence of “true” and “provable”. In Proceedings of the Abstracts of International Conference “MAL’TSEV MEETING” Dedicated to the 100th Anniversary of Anatolii Ivanovich Mal’tsev, Sobolev Institute of Mathematics, Novosibirsk State University, Novosibirsk, Russia, 24–28 August 2009; S.L. Sobolev Institute of Mathematics: Novosibirsk, Russia, 2019; p. 220. [Google Scholar]
  23. Tarski, A. Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of Deductive Sciences [Vvedenie v Logiku i Metodologiyu Deduktivnyh Nauk]; State Publishing House of Foreign Literature [Gosudarstvennoe Izdatel’stvo Inostrannoj Literatury]: Moscow, Russia, 1948. (In Russian) [Google Scholar]
  24. Tselishchev, V.V. The normative character of deductive theories and the meaning of mathematical terms [Normativnyj harakter deduktivnyh teorij i znachenie matematicheskih terminov]. Philos. Sci. 2004, 1, 71–82. (In Russian) [Google Scholar]
  25. Tselishchev, V.V. Normative-Ness of Deductive Discourse: Phenomenology of Logic Constants [Normativnost’ Deduktivnogo Diskursa: Fenomenologiya Logicheskih Konstant]; Nonparel: Novosibirsk, Russia, 2004. (In Russian) [Google Scholar]
  26. Tselishchev, V.V. Consistency and completeness as the standards of deductive thinking from the standpoint of Gödel’s theorems about incompleteness of arithmetic [Neprotivorechivost’ i polnota kak normy deduktivnogo myshleniya v svete teorem Gyodelya o nepolnote arifmetiki]. Philos. Sci. 2005, 2, 34–52. (In Russian) [Google Scholar]
  27. Lobovikov, V.O. Proofs of Logic Consistency of a Formal Axiomatic Epistemology Theory, and Demonstrations of Improvability of the Formulae (Kq→q) and (□q→q) in It. J. Appl. Math. Comput. 2018, 2, 483–495. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  28. Lobovikov, V.O. A Formal Deductive Inference of the Law of Inertia in a Logically Formalized Axiomatic Epistemology System Sigma from the Assumption of Knowledge A-Priori-Ness. J. Appl. Math. Phys. 2021, 9, 441–467. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  29. Lobovikov, V.O. Formal Inferring the Law of Conservation of Energy from Assuming A-Priori-ness of Knowledge in a Formal Axiomatic Epistemology System Sigma. J. Appl. Math. Phys. 2021, 9, 1011–1040. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  30. Ivin, A.A. Foundations of Evaluation Logic [Osnovanija Logiki Ocenok]; Izdatel’stvo Moskovskogo Universiteta: Moscow, Russia, 1970. (In Russian) [Google Scholar]
  31. Lobovikov, V.O. A proof of a formal-axiological inconsistency of the formal arithmetic investigated by K. Gödel (the proof essentially using own axioms of formal axiology). In Proceedings of the 7th Smirnov Readings in Logic, Moscow, Russia, 22–24 June 2011; Markin, V.I., Ed.; Sovremennye Tetradi: Moscow, Russia, 2011; pp. 92–93. [Google Scholar]
  32. Lobovikov, V.O. A Logical-Philosophical Justification of a Hypothesis of Formal-Ethical Inconsistency of the Formal Arithmetic Investigated by K. Gödel. Proc. Ural. Fed. University. Ser. Soc. Sci. 2011, 88, 14–28. (In Russian) [Google Scholar]
  33. Lobovikov, V.O. An Equivalence of Moore’s Paradox and Gödel’s Incompleteness Sentence in Two-Valued Algebra of Formal Ethics. Philos. Study 2016, 6, 34–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  34. Lobovikov, V. Algebra of Morality and Formal Ethics. In Looking Back to See the Future. Reflections on Sins and Virtues; Bronk, K., Ed.; Inter-Disciplinary Press: Oxford, UK, 2014; pp. 17–41. [Google Scholar]
  35. Kripke, S.A. Semantical Analysis of Modal Logic I. Normal Modal Propositional Calculi. J. Math. Log. Found. Math. 1963, 9, 67–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  36. Kripke, S.A. Semantical Analysis of Modal Logic II: Non-Normal Modal Propositional Calculi. In The Theory of Models: Proceedings of the 1963 International Symposium at Berkley; North-Holland: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1965; pp. 206–220. [Google Scholar]
  37. Bull, R.; Segerberg, K. Basic Modal Logic. In Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol. II: Extensions of Classical Logic; Gabbay, D., Guenthner, F., Eds.; D. Reidel Publishing Company: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1984; pp. 1–88. [Google Scholar]
  38. Kant, I. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics: In Focus; Routledge: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
  39. Poincaré, H. The Foundations of Science: Science and Hypothesis. In The Value of Science, Science and Method; The Science Press: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
  40. Majer, U.; Sauer, T. Intuition and the Axiomatic Method in Hilbert’s Foundation of Physics (Hilbert’s Idea of a Recursive Epistemology in His Third Hamburg Lecture). In Intuition and the Axiomatic Method. The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science. V.70; Carson, E., Huber, R., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2006; pp. 213–233. [Google Scholar]
Table 1. Definition of the functions determined by one evaluation argument.
Table 1. Definition of the functions determined by one evaluation argument.
xB11x N11xC11x I11xZ11xS11xU11xA11xG11xP11xH11xR11x
ggbgbbbbgggbb
bbgbgbbbggbgg
Table 2. Definition of the evaluation-functions determined by two arguments.
Table 2. Definition of the evaluation-functions determined by two arguments.
xyK2xyS2xyX2xyT2xyZ2xyP2xyC2xyE2xyV2xyN2xyY2xy
gggbbbbgggbbg
gbbgbbbgbbgbg
bgbggggbgbgbg
bbbgbbbgggbgb
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Lobovikov, V.O. A Logically Formalized Axiomatic Epistemology System Σ + C and Philosophical Grounding Mathematics as a Self-Sufficing System. Mathematics 2021, 9, 1859. https://doi.org/10.3390/math9161859

AMA Style

Lobovikov VO. A Logically Formalized Axiomatic Epistemology System Σ + C and Philosophical Grounding Mathematics as a Self-Sufficing System. Mathematics. 2021; 9(16):1859. https://doi.org/10.3390/math9161859

Chicago/Turabian Style

Lobovikov, Vladimir Olegovich. 2021. "A Logically Formalized Axiomatic Epistemology System Σ + C and Philosophical Grounding Mathematics as a Self-Sufficing System" Mathematics 9, no. 16: 1859. https://doi.org/10.3390/math9161859

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop