Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T19:37:41.524Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Positive Science and Discoverability

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Thomas Nickles*
Affiliation:
University of Nevada, Reno

Extract

Several 17th- and 18th-century natural philosophers and methodologists aimed to establish a body of positive scientific results which were more than hypothetical or conjectural. They made exaggerated claims for the truth and empirical pedigree of their scientific conclusions. Since the mid-19th century, investigators have been more circumspect; and, increasingly in the 20th century, reflective scientists have become explicit fallibilists. They frequently acknowledge that current results are unlikely to endure.

Seemingly in keeping with the working scientists own attitude, many, perhaps most, contemporary philosophers of science—in the wake of dramatic revolutions in several sciences and philosophical attacks on the quest for certainty—now take for granted the hypothetical, the conjectural nature of all Interesting scientific claims, particularly deep theoretical claims. According to these philosophers, the lesson we have learned from 19th-century methodologists is that 17th-century discovery programs, which aimed to justify theories by “deduction from the phenomena”, were only utopian dreams.

Type
Part I. Discovery and Justification
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1984

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

For discussion and criticism, I am indebted to Larry and Rachel Laudan, Andrew Lugg, James Woodward, John Worrall, and an anonymous referee. They are not responsible!

References

Achinstein, Peter. (1971). Law and Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Debye, Peter (1914). “Zustandgleichung und Quantenhypothese mit einemanhang über Wärmeleitung.” In Vorträge über die Klnetische Theorie der Materie und der Elektrizität. Leipzig: Teubner. Pages 19-60.Google Scholar
Dorling, Jon. (1970). “Maxwell's Attempts to Arrive at Non-speculative Foundations for the Kinetic Theory.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 1: 229-248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorling, Jon. (1971). “Einstein's Introduction of Photons: Argument by Analogy or Deduction from the Phenomena?” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 22: 1-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorling, Jon. (1973). “Demonstrative Induction: Its Significant Role in the History of Physics.” Philosophy of Science 40: 360-372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehrenfest, Paul (1911). “Welche Züge der Lichtquantenhypothese spiel en in der Theorie der Wärmestrahlung eine wesentliche Rolle?” Annalen der Physik 36: 91-118. (As reprinted in Ehrenfest (1959). Pages 185-212.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehrenfest, Paul (1916). “Over adiabatische veranderingen van een stelsel in verband met de theorie der quanta.” Verslag Koninklijke Akademie von Wetenschappen te Amsterdam 25: 412-433. (As translated as “On adiabatic changes of a system in connection with the quantum theory.” In Ehrenfest (1959). Pages 378-399.)Google Scholar
Ehrenfest, Paul (1959). Paul Ehrenfest: Collected Scientific Papers. (ed.) Klein, M.J.. Amsterdam: North-Hoiland.Google Scholar
Glymour, Clark. (1980). Theory and Evidence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C.G. (1945). “Studies in the Logic of Confirmation.” Mind 54: 1-26 and 97-121. (As reprinted in Hempel (1965b). Pages 3-46.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C.G. (1965a). “Aspects of Scientific Explanation.” In Hempel (1965b). Pages 331-496.Google Scholar
Hempel, C.G. (1965b). Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Herschel, J.F.W. (1830). A Preliminary Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy. London: Longman, Brown, Green, and Longmans. (As reprinted New York: Johnson Reprint Corporation, 1966.)Google Scholar
Kuhn, T.S. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T.S. (1974). “Second Thoughts on Paradigms.” In The Structure of Scientific Theories. Edited by F. Suppe. Urbana: University of Illinois Press. Pages 459-482.Google Scholar
Lagrange, J.L. (1788). Méchanioue analitioue. Paris: Desaint.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, Imre. (1968). “Changes in The Problem of Inductive Logic.” In The Problem of Inductive Logic. Edited by Lakatos, I. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company. Pages 315-417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, Imre. and Zahar, Elie. (1975). “Why Did Copernicus's Research Program Supersede Ptolemy's?” In The Copernican Achievement. Edited by Westman, R.. Berkeley: University of California Press. Pages 354-383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, Larry. (1980). “Why Was the Logic of Discovery Abandoned?” In Nickles (1980b). Pages 173-183. (Reprinted with revisions in Science and Hypothesis. (University of Western Ontario Series'ln Philosophy of Science. Volume 19.) Dordrecht: Reidel, 1981. Pages 181-191.)Google Scholar
Newton, Isaac. (1687). Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica. London: Royal Society. (As reprinted as Sir Isaac Newton's Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy and his System of the World. 2 vols. (trans.) A. Motte, revised by Cajori, F.. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1973.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newton, Isaac. (1730). Opticks. 4th ed. London: Bell, G.. (As reprinted New York: Dover, 1952.)Google Scholar
Nickles, Thomas. (1976). “Theory Generalization, Problem Reduction, and the Unity of Science.” In PSA 1974. (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume XXXII.) Edited by Cohen, R.S., Hooker, C.A., Michalos, A.C. and van Evra, J.W.. Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 33-75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, Thomas. (1980a). “Can Scientific Constraints Be Violated Rationally?” In Nickles (1980b). Pages 285-315.Google Scholar
Nickles, Thomas. (ed.). (1980b). Scientific Discovery. Logic, and Rationality. (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Volume 56.) Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, Thomas. (1984a). “Discovery and Scientific Change.” Materiali Filosofici 8: forthcoming (in Italian).Google Scholar
Nickles, Thomas. (1984b). “Justification as Discoverability II.” Philosophia Naturalis 23: forthcoming.Google Scholar
Nickles, Thomas. (1985). “Beyond Divorce: Current Status of the Discovery Debate.” Philosophy of Science 52: forthcoming.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Planck, Max. (1900a). “über eine Verbesserung der Wienschen Spektralgleichung.” Verhandlungen der Deutschen Physikalischen Gesellschaft 2: 202-204. (As translated as “On an Improvement of Wien's Equation for the Spectrum.” In ter Haar (1967). Pages 79-81.)Google Scholar
Planck, Max.(1900b). “Zur Theorie des Gesetzes der Energieverteilung im Normalspektrum.” Verhandlungen der Deutschen Physikalischen Gesellschaft 2: 237-245. (As translated as “On the Theory of the Energy Distribution Law of the Normal Spectrum.” In ter Haar (1967). Pages 82-90.)Google Scholar
Folanyi, Michael. (1958). Personal Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl. (1962). Coniectures and Refutations. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. (1962). “What theories are not.” In Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science. Edited by Nagel, E., Suppes, P. and Tarski, A.. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Pages 240-251. (As reprinted in Mathematics Matter and Method. (Philosophical Papers, Volume 1.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975. Page3 215-227.)Google Scholar
Shapere, Dudley. (1982). “The Concept of Observation in Science and Philosophy.” Philosophy of Science 49: 485-525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
ter Haar, D., (ed.). (1967). The Old Quantum Theory. Oxford: Pergamon.Google Scholar
Wien, W. (1896). über die Energievertheilung im Emissionsspectrum eines schwarzen Körpers.’ Annalen der Physik 58: 662-669. (Translated as “On the Division of Energy in the Emission-Spectrum of a Black Body.” Philosophical Magazine 43 (1897): 214-221.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, John. (1978). “The Ways in which the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes Improves on Popper's Methodology.” In Progress and Rationality in Science. (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume LVII.) Edited by G. Radnitzky and G. Andersson. Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 45-70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, John. (1983). “Hypotheses and Mr. Newton.” Read at the University of Pittsburgh, the Boston Colloquium for Philosophy of Science, and Indiana University (as the N.R. Hanson Memorial Lecture), spring 1983.Google Scholar
Worrall, John. (1984). “Scientific Discovery and Theory-Confirmation.” In Change and Progress in Modern Science. (University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science.) Edited by J.C. Pitt. Dordrecht: Reidel. Forthcoming.Google Scholar
Zahar, Elie. (1973). “Why Did Einstein ‘ s Programme Supersede Lorentz's?” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24: 95-123 and 223-262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahar, Elie. (1983). “Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Invention?” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34: 243-261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar