Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-skm99 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T17:35:58.263Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Developmental Systems Theory Formulated as a Claim about Inherited Representations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Developmental systems theory (DST) is often dismissed on the basis that the causal indispensability of nongenetic factors in evolution and development has long been appreciated. A reformulation makes a more substantive claim: that the special role played by genes is also played by some (but not all) nongenetic resources. That special role can be captured by Shea's ‘inherited representation’. Formulating DST as the claim that there are nongenetic inherited representations turns it into a striking, empirically testable hypothesis. DST's characteristic rejection of a gene versus environment dichotomy is preserved but without dissolving into an interactionist casual soup, as some have alleged.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

For helpful comments and discussion of this material, the author would like to thank Paul Griffiths, Arnon Levy, Russell Powell, Ulrich Stegmann, Tobias Uller, the referees for this journal, and audiences in Oxford and at the symposium on Information and Biological Development at the ISHPSSB meeting in Exeter, July 2007. The research reported here was supported by the Oxford University Press John Fell Research Fund, the James Martin 21st Century School, the Wellcome Centre for Neuroethics, and the Mary Somerville Junior Research Fellowship, Somerville College, University of Oxford.

References

Alberts, B., et al. 2004. Essential Cell Biology. 2nd ed. New York: Garland Science.Google Scholar
Avital, Eytan, and Jablonka, Eva. 2000. Animal Traditions: Behavioural Inheritance in Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergstrom, Carl T., and Rosvall, Martin. Forthcoming. “The Transmission Sense of Information.” Biology and Philosophy.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Freeland, S. J., and Hurst, L. D.. 1998. “The Genetic Code Is One in a Million.” Journal of Molecular Evolution 47:238–48.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Galloway, L. F., and Etterson, J. R.. 2007. “Transgenerational Plasticity Is Adaptive in the Wild.” Science 318:1134–36.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 1999. “Genes and Codes: Lessons from the Philosophy of Mind.” In Where Biology Meets Psychology: Philosophical Essays, ed. Hardcastle, V.. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2000. “On the Theoretical Role of ‘Genetic Coding.’Philosophy of Science 67:2644.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2001. “On the Status and Explanatory Structure of Developmental Systems Theory.” In Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution, ed. Oyama, Susan, Griffiths, Paul E., and Gray, Russell D.. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2006. “Information in Biology.” In The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology, ed. Hull, D.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2007. “Conditions for Evolution by Natural Selection.” Journal of Philosophy 54 (10): 489516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, Russell D. 2001. “Selfish Genes or Developmental Systems?” In Thinking about Evolution: Historical, Philosophical and Political Perspectives, ed. Singh, R. S., Costas, B. K., Paul, D. B., and Beatty, J., 184207. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Griffiths, Paul E. 2001. “Genetic Information: A Metaphor in Search of a Theory.” Philosophy of Science 68:394412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, Paul E.. 2005. “The Fearless Vampire Conservator: Philip Kitcher, Genetic Determinism and the Informational Gene.” In Genes in Development: Re-reading the Molecular Paradigm, ed. Neumann-Held, E. M. and Rehmann-Sutter, C.. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Griffiths, Paul E., and Gray, Russell D.. 1994. “Developmental Systems and Evolutionary Explanations.” Journal of Philosophy 91:277304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, Paul E., and Gray, Russell D.. 1997. “Replicator II: Judgement Day.” Biology and Philosophy 12:471–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, Paul E., and Gray, Russell D.. 2005. “Discussion: Three Ways to Misunderstand Developmental Systems Theory.” Biology and Philosophy 20:417–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, Paul E., and Knight, Robin D.. 1998. “What Is the Developmentalist Challenge?Philosophy of Science 65:253–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haig, D., and Hurst, L. D.. 1991. “A Quantitative Measure of Error Minimization in the Genetic Code.” Journal of Molecular Evolution 33:412–17.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Immelmann, K. 1975. “Ecological Significance of Imprinting and Early Learning.” Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 6:1537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jablonka, Eva. 2002. “Information: Its Interpretation, Its Inheritance, and Its Sharing.” Philosophy of Science 69:578605.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jablonka, Eva, and Lamb, Marion J.. 1995. Epigenetic Inheritance and Evolution: The Lamarckian Dimension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jablonka, Eva, and Lamb, Marion J.. 2005. Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Jablonka, Eva, and Lamb, Marion J.. 2007. “Précis of Evolution in Four Dimensions.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30:353–92.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jablonka, Eva, and Raz, Gal. 2009. “Transgenerational Epigenetic Inheritance: Prevalence, Mechanisms, and Implications for the Study of Heredity and Evolution.” Quarterly Review of Biology 84 (2): 131–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lambourn, W. A. 1930. “The Remarkable Adaptation by which a Dipterous Pupa (Tabanidae) Is Preserved from the Dangers of Fissures in Drying Mud.” Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B 106:8387.Google Scholar
Leimar, O., Hammerstein, P., and Van Dooren, T. J. M.. 2006. “A New Perspective on Developmental Plasticity and the Principles of Adaptive Morph Determination.” American Naturalist 167:367–76.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levy, Arnon. 2010. “Information in Biology: A Fictionalist Account.” Nous, doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0068.2010.00792.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewontin, Richard C. 1974. “The Analysis of Variance and the Analysis of Causes.” American Journal of Human Genetics 26:400411.Google ScholarPubMed
Lewontin, Richard C.. 1982. “Organism and Environment.” In Learning, Development, Culture, ed. Plotkin, H., 151–70. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Lewontin, Richard C.. 1983. “The Organism as the Subject and Object of Evolution.” Scientia 118:6582.Google Scholar
Lorenz, K. 1965. Evolution and Modification of Behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Mameli, Matteo. 2004. “Nongenetic Selection and Nongenetic Inheritance.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55:3571.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, John. 2000. “The Concept of Information in Biology.” Philosophy of Science 67:177–94.Google Scholar
Maynard Smith, John, and Szathmáry, Erös. 1995. The Major Transitions in Evolution. Oxford: Freeman.Google Scholar
Meaney, M. J. 2001. “Maternal Care, Gene Expression, and the Transmission of Individual Differences in Stress Reactivity across Generations.” Annual Review Neuroscience 24:1161–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett. 1984. Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Moss, L. 2001. “Deconstructing the Gene and Reconstructing Molecular Developmental Systems.” In Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution, ed. Oyama, Susan, Griffiths, Paul E., and Gray, Russell D.. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Oyama, Susan. 1985. The Ontogeny of Information: Developmental Systems and Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shannon, C. E. 1949. “The Mathematical Theory of Communication.” In The Mathematical Theory of Communication, ed. Shannon, C. E. and Weaver, W.. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Shea, Nicholas. 2007. “Representation in the Genome, and in Other Inheritance Systems.” Biology and Philosophy 22:313–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shea, Nicholas. 2009. “Imitation as an Inheritance System.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364:2429–43.Google ScholarPubMed
Shea, Nicholas. Forthcoming. “Inherited Representations Are Read in Development.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Shea, Nicholas. Forthcoming. “Two Modes of Transgenerational Information Transmission.” In Signaling, Commitment, and Emotion, ed. Calcott, Brett, Joyce, Richard, and Sterenly, Kim. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stegmann, Ulrich E. 2005. “Genetic Information as Instructional Content.” Philosophy of Science 72 (3): 425–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, Kim. 2001. “Niche Construction, Developmental Systems and the Extended Replicator.” In Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution, ed. Oyama, Susan, Griffiths, Paul E., and Gray, Russell D., 333–50. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sterelny, Kim. 2004. “Sybiosis, Evolvability and Modularity.” In Modularity in Development and Evolution, ed. Schlosser, Gerhard and Wagner, Günter. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sterelny, Kim, and Kitcher, Philip. 1988. “The Return of the Gene.” Journal of Philosophy 85:339–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, Kim, Smith, K. C., and Dickison, M.. 1996. “The Extended Replicator.” Biology and Philosophy 11:377403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sultan, S. E. 2000. “Phenotypic Plasticity for Plant Development, Function and Life History.” Trends in Plant Science 5:537–42.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Weber, M. 2005. Philosophy of Experimental Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Whiten, Andrew, McGuigan, N., Marshall-Pescini, S., and Hopper, L. M.. 2009. “Emulation, Imitation, Overimitation and the Scope of Culture for Child and Chimpanzee.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364:2417–28.Google Scholar