Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ndmmz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-14T16:42:36.626Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

In Pursuit of the Non-Trivial

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 June 2019

Colin R. Caret*
Affiliation:
Yonsei University, Seoul, South Korea
*
*Corresponding author. Email: colin.caret@gmail.com

Abstract

This paper is about the underlying logical principles of scientific theories. In particular, it concerns ex contradictione quodlibet (ECQ) the principle that anything follows from a contradiction. ECQ is valid according to classical logic, but invalid according to paraconsistent logics. Some advocates of paraconsistency claim that there are ‘real’ inconsistent theories that do not erupt with completely indiscriminate, absurd commitments. They take this as evidence in favor of paraconsistency. Michael (2016) calls this the non-triviality strategy (NTS). He argues that this strategy fails in its purpose. I will show that Michael's criticism significantly over-reaches. The fundamental problem is that he places more of a burden on the advocate of paraconsistency than on the advocate of classical logic. The weaknesses in Michael's argument are symptomatic of this preferential treatment of one viewpoint in the debate over another. He does, however, make important observations that allow us to clarify some of the complexities involved in giving a logical reconstruction of a theory. I will argue that there are abductive arguments deserving of further consideration for the claim that paraconsistent logic offers the best explanation of the practice of inconsistent science. In this sense, the debate is still very much open.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alston, W.P. (1986). ‘Epistemic Circularity.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47, 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beall, J.C. (2015). ‘Free of Detachment: Logic, Rationality, and Gluts.’ Noûs 49, 410–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, J.L. (2017). ‘Continuity and Infinitesimals.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/continuity/.Google Scholar
Boghossian, P. (2003). ‘Blind Reasoning, I.’ Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77, 225–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, B. (1992). ‘Old Quantum Theory: A Paraconsistent Approach.’ In PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, vol. 2, 397411. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Brown, B. and Priest, G. (2004). ‘Chunk and Permeate, a Paraconsistent Inference Strategy. Part I: The Infinitesimal Calculus.’ Journal of Philosophical Logic 33, 379–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, B. and Priest, G. (2015). ‘Chunk and Permeate II: Bohr's Hydrogen Atom.’ European Journal for Philosophy of Science 5, 297314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caret, C.R. and Weber, Z. (2015). ‘A Note on Contraction-Free Logic for Validity.’ Topoi 34, 6374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carroll, L. (1893). Sylvie and Bruno Concluded. London: Macmillan and Co.Google Scholar
Colyvan, M. (2008 a). ‘The Ontological Commitments of Inconsistent Theories.’ Philosophical Studies 141, 115–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colyvan, M. (2008 b). ‘Who's Afraid of Inconsistent Mathematics?ProtoSociology 25, 2435.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colyvan, M. (2009). ‘Applying Inconsistent Mathematics.’ In Bueno, O. and Linnebo, Ø. (eds), New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics, pp. 160172. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
da Costa, Newton C.A. and French, S. (2003). Science and Partial Truth: A Unitary Approach to Models and Scientific Reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dogramaci, S. (2013). ‘Intuitions for Inferences.’ Philosophical Studies 165, 371–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ebert, P.A. (2016). ‘A Framework for Implicit Definitions and the A Priori.’ In Ebert, P.A. and Rossberg, M. (eds), Abstractionism: Essays in Philosophy of Mathematics, pp. 133–60. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. (2009). ‘What is the Normative Role of Logic? I.’ Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 83, 251–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghins, M. (2014). ‘Bohr's Theory of the Hydrogen Atom: A Selective Realist Interpretation.’ In Magnani, L. (ed.), Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology, pp. 415–30. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1984). ‘Logic and Reasoning.’ Synthese 60, 107–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1986). Change in View: Principles of Reasoning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. (2009). ‘Field on the Normative Role of Logic.’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109, 333–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hettema, H. (1995). ‘Bohr's Theory of the Atom 1913–1923: A Case Study in the Progress of Scientific Research Programmes.’ Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 26, 307–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hjortland, O.T. (2013). ‘Logical Pluralism, Meaning-Variance, and Verbal Disputes.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91, 355–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Humberstone, L. (2011). The Connectives. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kvanvig, J.L. (2003). The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1970). ‘Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.’ In Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (eds), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pp. 91195. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (2004). ‘Letters to Beall and Priest.’ In Priest, G., Beall, J.C. and Armour-Garb, B. (eds), The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, pp. 176–77. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacFarlane, J. Ms. ‘In What Sense (If Any) Is Logic Normative for Thought?’ Unpublished draft of April 21, 2004, http://johnmacfarlane.net/work.html.Google Scholar
Michael, M. (2013). ‘Facing Inconsistency: Theories and Our Relations to Them.’ Episteme 10, 351–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Michael, M. (2016). ‘On a “Most Telling” Argument for Paraconsistent Logic.’ Synthese 193, 3347–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinder, M. (2017). ‘A Normative Argument Against Explosion.’ Thought 6, 6170.Google Scholar
Priest, G. (2006). In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent, 2nd edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Priest, G., Tanaka, K. and Weber, Z. (2018). ‘Paraconsistent Logic.’ In Zalta, E.N. (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/logic-paraconsistent/.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1969). ‘Is Logic Empirical?’ In Cohen, R.S. and Wartofsky, M.W. (eds), Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. V, pp. 216–41. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W.V. (1986). Philosophy of Logic, 2nd edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Routley, R., Plumwood, V., Meyer, R.K. and Brady, R.T. (eds) (1982). Relevant Logics and Their Rivals, vol. I. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Russell, G. Forthcoming. ‘Logic Isn't Normative.’ Inquiry.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. (2014). Varieties of Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinberger, F. Forthcoming. ‘Consequence and Normative Guidance.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.Google Scholar
Vickers, P. 2013. Understanding Inconsistent Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vickers, P. 2014. ‘Theory Flexibility and Inconsistency in Science.’ Synthese 191, 2891–906.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, Z., Badia, G. and Girard, P. (2015). ‘What Is an Inconsistent Truth Table?Australasian Journal of Philosophy 94, 533–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, L. (2001). ‘Recovering Understanding.’ In Steup, M. (ed.), Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification, Responsibility, and Virtue, pp. 235–52. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar