Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-75dct Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-30T18:22:56.631Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Political Languages In Later Medieval Europe

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 February 2016

Antony Black*
Affiliation:
University of Dundee
Get access

Extract

Certain aspects of both major and minor political writings in later medieval Europe remain intrinsically puzzling. Michael Wilks, in his seminal work on the ‘Problem of Sovereignty’ in this period called the later medieval and early modern epochs an ‘age of confusion’. One problem may be summed up as (1) What difference did Aristotle make? Ullmann argued that Aristotle made it possible to construct a plausible case for ‘the ascending’ (that is, quasi-democratic) view of authority. In that case, as Wilks persistently enquires: Why did defenders of papal monarchy make such free, prolific use of Aristotle?

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Ecclesiastical History Society 1991 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Wilks, Michael, The Problem of Sovereignty in lhe Later Middle Ages (Cambridge, 1963).Google Scholar

2 Ullmann, Walter, Principles of Government and Politics in the Middle Ages, 4th edn (London, 1978)Google Scholar, pt 3, ch. 2.

3 Quillet, Jeannine, La Philosophie politique de Marsile de Padoue (Paris, 1970)Google Scholar; Wilks, Michael, ‘Corporation and Representation in the Defensor Pads’: SGra, 15 (1972), pp. 253–92Google Scholar; Rubinstein, Nicolai, ‘Marsilius of Padua and Italian Political Thought of his Time’ in Hale, J. R, Highfield, R., and Smalley, B., eds, Europe in the Late Middle Ages (London, 1965), pp. 4475Google Scholar; Skinner, Quentin, The Foundations of Modem Political Thought, 1, The Renaissance (Cambridge, 1978). PP. 53ff.Google Scholar

4 Seigel, Jerrold E., ‘“Civic Humanism” or Ciceronian Rhetoric? The culture of Petrarch and Bruni’, PaP, 34 (1966), pp. 348Google Scholar (it was he who first introduced the notion of ‘paradigm’ here); Rubinstein, Nicolai, ‘Florentine constitutionalism and the Medici ascendancy’, in stein, N. Rubin, ed., Florentine Studies (London, 1068), pp. 442–62Google Scholar, at pp. 446—52; Baron, Hans, The Crisis ofthe Early Italian Renaissance, 2nd edn (Princeton, 1966), pp. 245–53CrossRefGoogle Scholar, Ana passim.

5 See esp. Nicholas of Cusa, Opera omnia (Basle, 1565), pp. 825-9 (Epistola ad Rodericum), and Deutsche Reichslagsakten, 16, pp. 421-3. Cf. Sigmund, Paul, Nicholas of Cusa and Medieval Political Thought (Harvard, 1963)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Sigmund, Paul, ‘Cusanus’ Concordantia, a re-interpretation’, Political Studies, 10 (1962), pp. 180–97.Google Scholar

6 Black, Antony, Council and Commune: the Conciliar Movement and the Fifteenth-Century Heritage (London, 1979), p.124Google Scholar, on Segovia’s De magna auctoritate episcoporum in synodogenerali, Basle, Universitätsbibliothek, MS B.V.1 5.

7 See nn. 27-8, 30, 32, 34 below. I am grateful to the seminar of the Department of Political Science and Social Policy at the University of Dundee, especially Paul Spicker, Brian Baxter, and Brian Smith for stimulating my enquiry into this question.

8 Sigmund, P., ‘The influence of Marsilius on fifteenth-century conciliarism’.JHI, 23 (1962), pp. 393402CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Black, Council, p. 12.

9 Burns, J. H., ed., Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought (Cambridge, 1988), p. 422Google Scholar; Oakley, Francis, ‘On the road from Constance to 1688’, JBS, 1 (1962), pp. 132CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Oakley, Francis, ‘Figgis, Constance and the Divines of Paris’, AHR, 75 (1969), pp. 368–86.Google Scholar

10 Pocock, J. G. A., The Machiavellian Moment (Princeton, 1975)Google Scholar, ch. 1.

11 Skinner, Foundations, 1.

12 Skinner, Quentin, ‘Meaning and understanding in the history of ideas’: History and Theory, 8 (1969), pp. 351Google Scholar, and his preface to Foundations, 1; Pocock, J. G. A., Politics, Language, and Time (London, 1972)Google Scholar, chs 1 and 8, and his ‘The Concept of a Language and the métier d’historien’, in Pagden, Anthony, ed., The Languages of Political Theory in Early-Modem Europe (Cambridge, 1987)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, ch. 1. (The title of this article was suggested, presumptuously no doubt, by the title of that book.)

13 ‘Concept’, p.21, Politics, pp.17-18.

14 Pagden, ed.. Languages; Skinner, Foundations, 1.

15 Black, Antony, Guilds and Civil Society in European Political Thoughtfrom the Twelfth Century to the Present (London, 1984).Google Scholar

16 Pagden’s introd. to languages, pp. 3-6.

17 Codex, 5.59.5.2.

18 Tractatus de regimine civitatis, ed. Quaglione, D. : Pensiero Politico, 9 (1976), pp. 7093.Google Scholar But see Skinner, , Foundations, 1, pp. 62–5.Google Scholar

19 Tierney, Brian, ‘Ockham, the conciliar theory and the canonists’, JHI, 15 (1954), pp. 4070.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

20 Tierney, Brian, Foundations of the Conciliar Theory: the Contribution of the Medieval Canonists from Gratian to the Great Schism (Cambridge, 1955).Google Scholar

21 Nicholas of Cusa, Opera Omnia, ed. Kallen, G. (Hamburg, 1959-68), 14Google Scholar (with a host of peculiar readings).

22 Black, Council, pp. 118-93; Krämer, W., Konsens una Reception. Verfassungsprinzipien der Kirclte im Basler Konziliarismus (Münster, 1980).Google Scholar

23 Black, Council, pp. 128ff. It was from this source that the notion of authority as minislerium, of course, derived (Matt. 20.25-8, etc.).

24 Ibid., pp. 132-3.

25 Ibid., pp. 128-9.

26 Juan de Segovia, Traclalus de concitiorum el ecclaiae aucloritate (also known as Decern advisamenta). Codices Vat. Lat. MS 4039, fols 192r-232v, at fols 224J-V (written in 1439); and, with minor verbal alterations, Amplificatici disputationis (written between 1450 and 1454) in his Historia gestorum generaiis synodi Basiliensis, ed. Palacky, F. et al. » Monumenta Conciliorum Generalium Secali XV, 3 (Vienna and Basle, 1935), pp. 720–1Google Scholar. Extracts are in Black, A., Monarchy and Community (Cambridge, 1970), pp. 141–4Google Scholar; tr. in Black, Council, pp. 163-4.

27 The relevant passages to compare with Segovia (see n. 26 above) are Locke, John, The Second Treatise of Government, ed.Laslett, Peter, John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, 2nd edn (Cambridge, 1967Google Scholar; student ed with altered pagination, 1988), ch. 8, esp. paras 95-7; ch. 12, esp. paras 149-53; and Rousseau, Jean Jacques, Du Contrat Social, ed. Grimsley, R. (Oxford, 1972)Google Scholar, book 1, chs 6—8. Compare especially the following: Segovia, , Historia, Monumenta, 3, pp. 720–1Google Scholar: ‘Si contingat totam illam multitudinem in unum congregari, et asserere vel optare aliquid, econtra autem ipse presidens dicat; quia ipsa Veritas prefertur fictioni, ipsa multi tudo merito superabit. Veritas enim est hanc multitudinem esse multas personas, fictio autem quod ipse presidens, qui unicam personam vere, multas autem esse dicitur representative … Cum ipsa multirudo principaliter adest, et iudicat aliquid sibi esse utile, presidens autem econtra dicit, intelligitur manifeste iam cessare causam quare plus sibi [se. presidenti] quam aliis assentiti debebat, vid. quod credebatur iudicium suum esse conforme ad intentionem omnium.’ Locke, Second Treatise, ch. 3, para. 151: ‘But when he (sc. the single person to whom in some commonwealths is entrusted supreme executive power and “a share in the legislative” (by which Locke presumably means to refer to the position of the English monarch), quits this representation, this public will, and acts by his own private will, he degrades himself, and is but a single private person, without power and without will that has any right to obedience; the members owing no obedience but to the public will of society.’ Rousseau, Du contrat social, iii, 14: ‘Á l’instant que le peuple est légitimement assemblée en corps souverain, toute jurisdiction du Gouvernement cesse, la puissance executive est suspendue… parce qu’où se trouve le représenté il n’y a plus de représentant’

28 Locke, Second Treatise, ch. 8, paras 95,97,99; Rousseau, Du contrai social, 1, ch. 6.

29 Historia, Monumenta, 3, pp. 727-8 and also Monumenta, 2, pp. 272-4 (‘ut… idem saperent idemque vellent);Black, Council, pp. 156-9. Cf. Acts 2.4.

30 In particular, that the sovereign people must act in person and not through representatives: Du contrat social, iii, 15; it is when they confer together in assembly that the consciousness of citizens is raised to a ‘general will’.

31 Historia, Monumenta, 3, pp. 802-3: power belongs to the whole community, ‘tamquam propria passio sive innata virtus, ab ea inseparabilis’, and the giving of power to a ruler or consulate consists of ‘potius transfusionis sive extensionis cuiusdam quam novae generationis’; Black, , Council, pp. 172–5.Google Scholar

32 Du contrai social, ii, 1, and esp. ‘le pouvoir peut bien se transmettre, mais non pas la volonté.’

33 Shklar, J. N., Men and Citizens: a Study of Rousseau’s Social Theory (Cambridge, 1969)Google Scholar; Grimsley, R., The Philosophy of Rousseau (Oxford, 1973)Google Scholar; and especially Cobban, Alfred, Rousseau and the Modem State, 2nd edn (London, 1964), pp. 40,49, 59.Google Scholar

34 I wonder whether the same explanation might be given for Locke’s abrupt transition endorsing majority decision-making when speaking of ‘incorporating’ and then abandoning it: for majority decision-making was built into the (juristic) language of corporate action, but Locke had no desire to put it into his constitutional theory. It just, so to speak, slipped in with corporate terms: see Second Treatise, ch. 8, paras 95-9.

35 Black, , Monarchy, pp. 93112.Google Scholar

36 For further development of this argument see my forthcoming Political Thought in Europe, 1250-1450.