Skip to main content

Persons, Artificial Intelligence, and Science Fiction Thought–Experiments

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophy and the 'Dazzling Ideal' of Science
  • 291 Accesses

Abstract

Perhaps our minds are just like computers, even if of interesting kinds (as science fiction illustrates). Then that 'dazzling image' might make particular thoughts seem inevitable, generated exceptionlessly. Hence, Chap. 6 addresses issues most readily raised for artificial intelligence (in a “Strong AI” version) to further elaborate our concept of a person, by first exploring how the so-called Turing Test sets bounds for constructing intelligence. Searle’s "Chinese Room" argument is recruited to expose some limitations of this Test: since computer programmes are syntactic, and syntax cannot determine semantics, passing the Test cannot guarantee understanding. Then, the so-called "Aphrodite Argument", in recognizing constraints on understanding genuine persons, renders problematic the prospect of androids. Some apparent counter-cases, presented from the movie Blade Runner (1982) and the novel The Turing Option (Harrison and Minsky, Penguin Books, 1992), give this contention content and make it vivid. A different version of androidology, from the television series Westworld (2016), reinforces the differential explanatory power of reference to persons and to machines.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Hence Strong AI “is identical with computer functionalism” (Searle, 2008, p. 58).

  2. 2.

    On the homunculus fallacy, see Bennett & Hacker, 2007, pp. 132–133.

  3. 3.

    From Searle in Voices, Channel 4 television (UK), in discussion with Margaret Boden, chaired by Ted Honderich.

  4. 4.

    Contrast Searle, 1992, p. 197: “Marr’s rules of vision (1982: reprinted as his 2000) … are not the sort of phenomena that could become conscious”.

  5. 5.

    See also the suggestion that “expert-systems” (say, for landing an aeroplane) are sometimes just “high-speed data-base searches” (Putnam, 1994, pp. 322–323).

  6. 6.

    From Voices, Channel 4 television (cited note 3).

  7. 7.

    Searle’s own arguments against the possibility of an intelligible Cognitive Science should support this view (Searle, 1984, pp. 42–56; also Searle, 1992).

  8. 8.

    Suggested by Myrene McFee in discussion of this point.

  9. 9.

    It is surprisingly difficult to find examples not based on incompatibility with the biology.

  10. 10.

    Perhaps Searle accepts some version of this argument too, although not explicitly. Certainly, he seems strongly committed to the biological basis here, such that having a “truly substantive of a biological nature … [will] be like digestion or photosynthesis or the secretion of bile” (see Searle, 2008, p. 82); but—contrast with below—Searle (2008, p. 72) also recognizes that “[a]n artificial heart does not merely simulate pumping, it actually pumps”; similarly, for artificial brains in relation to consciousness.

  11. 11.

    See Marr, [1982] 2000. For the relation to rule-following, see Shanker, 1988, pp. 155–255.

  12. 12.

    Consider “the dog knows the cat is up the tree”, a sort of knowledge-attribution uninteresting for students of personhood. See Malcolm, 1977, pp. 40–57.

  13. 13.

    For discussion, see Putnam, 1988, esp. Chaps. 1, 2, and 5.

  14. 14.

    The thought here is that what can be stated without self-contradiction is logically possible. For discussion, see Palmer, 1984; Hacker, 1976, esp. p. 24.

  15. 15.

    Blade Runner , starring Harrison Ford and Rutger Hauer; directed by Ridley Scott from a screenplay by Hampton Fancher and David Peoples. Its inspiration was Philip K. Dick’s novella, Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep? (Grafton Books, 1968), which presents a more complex version. But my comments are typically based on the original 1982 ‘cut’ of the film. For detail, see Coplan & Davies, 2015.

  16. 16.

    By this I mean that these properties result from that physiology, as “higher-order” properties. See also Searle, 1983, pp. 265–271. For discussion, see Dilman, 1988, esp. pp. 95–96.

  17. 17.

    The exception is Rachael, the replicant that Deckard (the hero) falls in love with. But, as her maker implies, she is a special case, not required to engage in the activities usually reserved for replicants. Yet these very differences highlight the intentions vis-à-vis other replicants.

  18. 18.

    As Searle (1984, pp. 35–36) points out, there is an uninteresting sense in which we are machines. But the thought here is clear enough.

  19. 19.

    Is this a genuine act of compassion? Certainly, that point, if conceded, exhibits one of the key personal properties. For discussion, see Midgley, 1979, esp. Chaps. 9 and 10.

  20. 20.

    Reeve (in Coplan & Davies, 2015, p. 84) offers these as “two ways of reading Gaff’s unicorn”; Ridley Scott (reported Coplan & Davies, 2015, p. 25, note 10) seems to think it a closed matter.

  21. 21.

    Of course, any members of homo sapiens not granted full person-status—say, the very young or some advanced dementia cases—are irrelevant here: on exceptions, see Chap. 7; on philosophy without exceptionlessness, see Chap. 8.

  22. 22.

    As above, Searle (1984, p. 86) acknowledges that he cannot easily solve the “free will” problem (see Chap. 2 this volume); and grants that it is a real problem. For discussion, see Dilman, 1988, pp. 130–137.

  23. 23.

    This question returns us to the idea of conceivability: see especially Hacker, 1976, cited note 14.

  24. 24.

    Talking to Jeffrey Hinton, Voices, Channel 4, April 19, 1988; and see Searle, 1992, pp. 66–68.

  25. 25.

    See Shanker, 1987, p. 99 (quoting Wittgenstein, RPP 1, §1096): “Turing’s machine: These machines are in fact human beings who calculate”.

  26. 26.

    HBO television, of ten episodes, first broadcast between 2nd October and December 4th December, 2016: created by Jonathan Nolan and Lisa Joy. A second series aired in 2018; but only the first series (2016) is addressed here.

  27. 27.

    Baker and Morris (1996) is the obvious exception: my debt here, as elsewhere, to their scholarship should also be obvious.

  28. 28.

    Note too that “[p]eople who never philosophize and use only their senses” conceive of the union between body and soul without difficulty: for Descartes, “the ordinary course of life and conversation” teaches us to do this (CSMK III, p. 227); but, in fact, “the mind and the body are incomplete substances when they are referred to a human being which together they make up” (CSM II, p. 157 [4th Set of Replies]), although each is complete relative just to itself.

Bibliography

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). Sense and Sensibilia. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, G., & Morris, K. M. (1996). Descartes’ Dualism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2007). The Conceptual Presuppositions of Cognitive Neuroscience: A Reply to Critics. In D. Robinson (Ed.), Neuroscience and Philosophy: Brain, Mind, and Language (pp. 127–162). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coplan, A., & Davies, D. (Eds.). (2015). Blade Runner. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness Explained. London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1984). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (3 Vols.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [cited as “CSM” (for Vols. I, II) or “CSMK” (for Vol. III) as appropriate].

    Google Scholar 

  • Dilman, I. (1988). Mind, Brain and Behaviour. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunderson, K. (1971). Mentality and Machine. New York: Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P. M. S. (1976). Locke and the Meaning of Colour Words. In G. Vesey (Ed.), Impressions of Empiricism (p. 2S46). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, H., & Minsky, M. (1992). The Turing Option. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, A. (1966). Cartesian Privacy. In G. Pitcher (Ed.), Wittgenstein: The Philosophical Investigations (pp. 352–370). New York: Doubleday.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, A. (1987). Descartes for Beginners. In The Heritage of Wisdom. Oxford: Blackwell. [Reprinted].

    Google Scholar 

  • Malcolm, N. (1977). Thought and Knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (2000). Vision. In R. Cummins & D. D. Cummins (Eds.), Minds, Brains and Computers: The Foundations of Cognitive Science (pp. 69–83). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McFee, G. (1992). Understanding Dance. London: Routledge. [cited as “UD”].

    Google Scholar 

  • Midgley, M. (1979). Beast and Man. London: Harvester.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, A. (1984). The Limits of AI: Thought Experiments and Conceptual Investigations. In S. Torrance (Ed.), The Mind and the Machine (pp. 43–50). Ellis Horwood Ltd..

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1988). Representation and Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1994). Words and Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schank, R., & Abelson, R. (1977). Scripts, Plans, Goals and Understanding. New York: Lawrence Erlbaum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1980). Minds, Brains and Programs. Behavioural and Brain Science, 3, 417–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1984). Minds, Brains and Science. London: BBC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1992). The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (2008). Philosophy in a New Century: Selected Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1963/1991). Science, Perception & Reality. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul; Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing. [cited as “SPR”].

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanker, S. (1987). The Decline and Fall of the Mechanist Metaphor. In R. Born (Ed.), Artificial Intelligence: The Case Against (pp. 72–131). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanker, S. (1988). Wittgenstein’s Remarks on the Significance of Gödel’s Theorum. In S. Shanker (Ed.), Gödel’s Theorum in Focus (pp. 155–256). London: Croom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, G. (2018). The AI Delusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. ([1950] 2005). Computing Machinery and Intelligence. In J. Feinberg & R. Shafer-Landau (Eds.), Reason and Responsibility: Readings in Some Basic Problems in Philosophy (12th edn., pp. 296–305). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth/Thomson. [Reprinted].

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (1980). Sameness and Substance. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953/2001/2009). Philosophical Investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell, [50th Anniversary (3rd edn.); 4th Rev. edn., P. M. S. Hacker & J. Schulte, Eds.]. [cited as “PI”].

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology (Vol. 1, G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell. [cited as “RPP 1”].

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L., & Waismann, F. (2003). The Voices of Wittgenstein (G. Baker, Ed.). London: Routledge. [cited as “VoW”].

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziff, P. (1966). The Feelings of Robots. In Philosophical Turnings (pp. 161–167). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Graham McFee .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

McFee, G. (2019). Persons, Artificial Intelligence, and Science Fiction Thought–Experiments. In: Philosophy and the 'Dazzling Ideal' of Science. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-21675-7_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics