SciELO - Scientific Electronic Library Online

 
 issue97Undo, distill and choreograph: Three notions for the landscape project. Cap de Creus, Cataluna, España. 2005-2010Post-liberal Valparaíso: 272 political postcards author indexsubject indexarticles search
Home Pagealphabetic serial listing  

Services on Demand

Journal

Article

Indicators

Related links

  • On index processCited by Google
  • Have no similar articlesSimilars in SciELO
  • On index processSimilars in Google

Share


ARQ (Santiago)

On-line version ISSN 0717-6996

ARQ (Santiago)  no.97 Santiago Dec. 2017

http://dx.doi.org/10.4067/S0717-69962017000300100 

Readings

On non-value and non-identity. Tafuri’s adventures in Adorno’s Enlightenment

Pedro Correa1 

1 Profesor asistente adjunto, Escuela de Arquitectura, Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile, Santiago, Chile. pcorrea4@gmail.com

Abstract:

By unfolding Tafuri’s intellectual project and its sources, this text shows how the drainage of values produced by the Enlightenment is but one of the crises through which capitalism reinvents itself to survive. In this way, the crisis of values would be nothing else than the logical result of rationalization and, therefore, of modernity as a process.

Keywords: reason; judgment; critical theory; crisis of values; modernity

I.

The reception of critical theory and the Frankfurt School have been in academia and professional practice, until fairly recently, has been inextricably connected to Tafuri’s work. Thus, the fate of such intellectual project has been perhaps too tightly tied to Tafuri, whose influence has been felt widespread around architecture’s circles as disheartening - his allegations to the contrary notwithstanding. And even though Adorno’s fate in philosophical contexts hasn’t been that different, it appears a double bind process has blurred the possibility of establishing concretely the connections between both. On the one hand, Tafuri’s criticism towards Adorno’s cultural model appears to have prevented any possibility for deep analysis,17 even though he has a record for criticizing his influences and distancing himself from them (Cacciari et al., 1977)18. On the other, shallow associations have too hastily equated both critiques, relinquishing the need for proper distinction. While comprehensive works like Andrew Leach’s Choosing History and Carla Keyvanian’s “Manfredo Tafuri’s Notion of History and its Methodological Sources: From Walter Benjamin to Roland Barthes” hardly mention Adorno’s influence, if at all, Fredric Jameson in his 1982 “Architecture and the Critique of Ideology” described Tafuri’s Architecture and Utopia and Adorno’s 1949 Philosophy of Modern Music (along Roland Barthes’ Le degré zéro de l’écriture), both as producing a sense of “the impossibility of the future, which cannot have failed to oppress any reader of this texts” (Jameson, 2000:444). Conversely, Hilde Heynen in her seminal Architecture and Modernity: A Critique, deals within the same work with both intellectual traditions, Critical Theory and the Venice School, providing the grounds for significant analysis - one she briefly outlines at the end of her account on Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory (Heynen, 1999). The substantial distinction Heynen’s work admits is still essential to an evaluation that allows both to limit and contextualize Tafuri’s legacy against a specific historical and intellectual background, and to gauge Adorno’s influence in his “critique of architectural ideology.” At the same time, it renews the possibility of operating with the cultural tools of Critical Theory within architectural discourse detaching them from Tafuri’s well known conclusions. As Tafuri’s legacy has stubbornly endured within architectural academia and practice, and Adorno’s has mostly been archived within discussions on high art against mass culture, the dependency of “negative dialectics” on the Venice School’s disenchanted “negative thought” has to be proven valuable outside those elaborations. By unpacking specific aspects of Architecture and Utopia’s first chapter “Reason’s Adventures” in the light of Adorno and Horkheimer’s Dialectic of Enlightenment, this essay elaborates on the intricate tissue of relations between of both critiques of modernity.

II.

In the first chapter of Architecture and Utopia, Manfredo Tafuri deploys his complete methodological apparatus as well as his political outlook with a succinctness characteristic of the “dense writing” his critics seldom forget to mention.19 Then, outlining the ideological issues determining Enlightenment architecture’s relationship with the emergent approach to the city as an object of design, he writes:

The formation of the architect as an ideologist of society; the individualization of the areas of intervention proper to city planning; the persuasive role of form in regard to the public and the selfcritical role of form in regard to its own problems and development; the interrelationship and opposition - at the level of formal research - between aritectural ‘object’ and urban organization: these are the constantly recurrent themes of the “Enlightenmentdialectic” on architecture (Tafuri, 1975:3).

The quotation marks over “Enlightenment dialectic” might be the only acknowledgment of the concept’s indebtedness to Theodor W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer’s (A&H) Dialektik der Aufklärung. Here, Tafuri’s historical narrative on the gradual disappearance of Baroque urbanism and the emergence of the first theories absorbing the city’s need for organization according to capital’s surplus value extraction, elaborates on Enlightenment as a twofold development: as a rationalizing process, and as ideology.20 While the former would ensure rational organization of production according to the new schemes of land organization, the latter would provide aesthetic cover for such operations, naturalizing the existence of the city by equating its design with picturesque park design and landscape painting’s management of nature as form. That is, by fashioning the city as a “natural,” a-historical phenomenon, enlightened ideologues would design the city as superstructure in order to allow the economic base to function properly, without raising public alarms. In this context, rational understanding of nature’s order as a principle of organization would function as a replacement of the monarchic authoritarianism of Baroque layouts. The dialectic Tafuri mentions is the product of Enlightenment’s rational organization of the city’s double nature and its conflicted andinevitable encounter with architecture’s also rational organization of form, through newly cast concepts such as ‘type’ and ‘typology.’ Facing theories like Laugier’s and Milizia’s which described the design of the city as the organization of “existing material,” architecture abandoned its symbolism in order to provide buildings as ‘material,’ rationally organized through formal principles. This “struggle between architecture and the city” (Tafuri, 1975:16), the clash between the possibility of organizing the city according to “natural principles,” and the rationalization of building through types, reaches its climax in Tafuri’s narrative, with G. B. Piranesi’s prophetic Campo Marzio. “Here,” Tafuri declares, “the ‘Enlightenment dialectic’ on architecture reached an unsurpassed height” (Tafuri, 1975:16). Piranesi’s drawings of a dystopic city assembled by a collection of autonomous pieces, without any logic except the internal to each type, shows the intractable contradictions of a city whose formal organization is no longer possible. Its attempt to individualize building design as an organic portion of the totality of the city condemns its pieces to silence - to the impossibility of a ‘whole’ given meaning through the sum of its ‘parts.’ Tafuri discovers in Piranesi a high level of consciousness regarding the contradictory friction of individuality, the necessary premise of the marketplace, democracy, and enlightened values, against the ensuing impossibility of Ferdinand Tönnies’ Gemeinschaft, of organic community.

III.

Here, as has been noted, Tafuri’s Piranesi acquires quite literally the qualities of A&H´s Sade (Biraghi, 2013:33; A&H, 2002:63-94). Portrayed as the disenchanted watchdog of Enlightenment’s dialectic underside, Piranesi becomes, for Tafuri, Sade’s architectural doppelgänger.21 The empty sexual excesses done against Sade’s Juliette and Justine are perpetrated by Piranesi to the possibility of an enlightened city. Nevertheless, while A&H’s Sade bears witness to the debilitation of Reason, as morality gets stripped down from its core, impeding forever the possibility of a conceptual knowledge within which morals and reason may share space; Tafuri’s Piranesi criticizes illuminist dreams by revealing their excess of reason turned nightmare. And, at the same time, it proposes an intellectual program: stripping the values from the enlightened products of the bourgeoisie will show tragedy as their real content. Tafuri follows closely A&H’s intellectual project: by demonstrating it is Reason, and not its lack, the principle which leads to the contradictions in Piranesi’s “useless machine” (Tafuri, 1975:15), he attempts to open up Reason dialectically, showing the extent to which understanding has been inevitably tied with domination, and the extent to which that domination leads back to the myth Enlightenment was set to overcome.22 “Reason, the author of this destruction,” Tafuri writes, “a destruction felt by Piranesi to be fatal - is transformed into irrationality” (Tafuri, 1975:18). The essential distinction for critical theory’s critique of reason however, between substantial Reason and instrumental reason (Vernunft and Verstand) can’t be found in Tafuri’s dialectic. The whole dialectical process through which Reason proper, whose power to enlighten life and thus alleviate suffering, is stripped of its substance, reduced to mere calculation, to become the amoral instrument of factual ends is eschewed by Tafuri altogether. His “Enlightenment dialectic” is one historically determined by the demystification of Reason by the ‘anti-ideological character of science’ on the one hand, and on the other, by the withering of values as obstacles to a bourgeoisie in constant revolution, which drops them as soon as their ideological worth disappears. Following Max Weber’s notion of modernity as one of constant disenchantment of the world, Tafuri’s Enlightenment is understood as a relentless progress of Reason, whose constant advancement produces an endless of crisis of values, and thus, the endless need for new ones. Piranesi would foretell precisely such a moment of crisis, one that wouldn’t be resolved until the late stages of artistic avant-garde and the advent of modern planning, with Hilberseimer and Le Corbusier. At the same time, the dialectic ‘struggle’ between the city and architecture would make evident the need for architecture to forego its old values in order to adapt to the new mechanisms of production. A&H’s dialectic of Enlightenment, on the other hand, is not determined historically as an accumulation of Reason which at the point of excess produces irrationality.23 They rather elaborate on the extent to which the freeing potential of Reason is always determined dialectically by a form of domination that leads to barbarism. This entails by no means to abandon reason altogether, but rather to condemn a form of reason whose “redemptive qualities” have been stripped down - as Adorno’s mentor Siegfried Kracauer famously put it, it is not that capitalism “rationalizes too much, but rather too little” (Kracauer, 1995:81). Unlike Piranesi’s, Sade’s debauchery is not the product of the excesses of an overburdened Reason, but evidence to its weakening.

IV.

This dialectical conflict, however, is not absent from Tafuri’s account by chance. Elsewhere he declared Adorno’s take on Enlightenment “too simplistic,”24 for his claim for a substantial Reason is to him symptomatic of an unfinished transformation, in other words, nostalgia for a set of values which has already disappeared from the modern world. He rather draws from Massimo Cacciari’s “Dialectic of the Negative and Metropolis,” who describes modern rationality as the result of the permanent tension between the ever increasing proliferation of outer stimuli and the impossibility of the nervous life (Nervenleben) to absorb them through sensible emotions. Intellectualization and rationalization would, in this context, perform as protection from the continuous shocks, draining qualities and values from things in order to deal with them dispassionately. The “flattening of values” described in Georg Simmel’s The Philosophy of Money - as the process by which the continuous need to transform ‘value’ into ‘exchange value’ produces a rational homogenization of the world (Simmel, 2011:465-483) - is put forward by Cacciari as a confirmation of the extent to which Verstand has already permeated the subjectivity of individual life. Vergeistigung, the process of realization of the spirit, is for Cacciari already fully reached in Simmel’s Blasé type (Simmel, 1971:324-339) wherein his cold indifference towards the quality of things is paid for with spleen, the emotional void left by the impossibility of genuine satisfaction - thus closing the nervous life- instrumental reason dialectic (Cacciari, 1993:8-9).25 Tafuri’s whole theory of the avant-garde revolves around this never ending transformation in which an emotional reaction to the anguish followed by the permanent loss of values in modernity is intellectualized into a rational response able to deal and elaborate on that loss.

Figure 1. Minima Moralia was published in 1951 and translated to Italian in 1954, The Philosophy of Modern Music in 1949 and translated in 1959, Dialectic of Enlightenment in 1944 and translated in 1966, and Negative Dialectics in 1966 and translated in 1970. They were published by Einaudi along with the work of Georg Lukács and Walter Benjamin.

V.

Furthermore, the flattening of values would not only be considered the destiny of the individual by Tafuri, but also the tragic fate of the intellectual, who now has to choose between nostalgia for values as ideology, or to face modernity “with the task of acquiring a tragic awareness of the given” (Cacciari, 1993:9).26 It is not by chance Max Weber’s dispassionate objectivity occupies such an important space in Tafuri’s bibliography. The disenchantment Weber declared essential to a science “free from value,” that is, unobstructed by subjective judgement, has been recognized in Tafuri by many readers.27 Against the pervasiveness of operative criticism, and an architectural history he considered “rotten to the core,” (Tafuri and Very, 1995(1976):37) he makes Weber’s freedom from value (Wertfreiheit) a central topic of his methodological discussions in Theories and History of Architecture. This approach is described in Architecture and Utopia as follows:

It should not be overlooked that for Weber Wertfreiheit has a dramatic significance. The intellectual, not allowing himself value judgment, courageously accepts his own obligation to be. This acceptance is in the first place the recognition of the irrational as the negative part of the system, which, since it is inseparable from the positive, is assumed along with the latter (Tafuri, 1975:51; Weber, 2009:47-48).

Tafuri’s disenchanted outlook is founded on the impossibility of approaching intellectual production within capitalism other than with the rational mechanisms made available by Capital itself. Any other attempt would fall into sheer illusion. Dealing with the negative means, as in Weber’s “virile objectivity,” dispelling myths and nostalgia, gazing at the world unshaken by illusory hopes: only by looking into the void can we return a genuine critical gaze to the world that put us in front of it in the first place. Following Cacciari’s elaborations on “negative thought,” disenchantment allows Tafuri to pursue contradictions: the negative is not avoided nor disentangled, it is precisely its irresolvable character what is pursued. In this context, Tafuri and Cacciari’s negative stresses the instability of capitalism, its restlessness, its needs for constant crisis, by refusing to provide it with a stable synthesis and by leaving the “dialectic of the Metropolis” indefinitely open: forcing capitalist civilization to face its own enduring volatility, by means of its own negativity, allowing no soothing ideological covers.28

In Architecture and Utopia Tafuri relies on Walter Benjamin’s “The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproducibility” and “Author as a Producer,” essential to Cacciari’s “negative thought,” to assess architectural production since Enlightenment. By equating Benjamin’s withering of the ‘aura’ to the devaluation of art altogether, Tafuri’s approach intends to do away with the ‘mysticism’ around art’s inherent values as they increasingly become an obstacle to scientific analysis - an obstacle without which the position works of art occupy within the relations of productions of their time become evident (Tafuri, 1980:171-226). Stripping values from judgment allows Tafuri to elaborate on modernism without appealing to the quality of individual works, or even to architecture as a fixed category, but rather to reconstruct their underlying historical tissue. At the same time, it reveals the tragedy of the modern: no architectural production - building, criticism or otherwise - has ever been produced outside, nor against, the dominion of capital. Architecture either finds its place as ideology or as an instrument to update the means of production. In this context, bad conscience appears to be the only mechanism through which modernism may reflect the unconscious trauma of the ideology it puts forward: “to ward off anguish by absorbing and understanding its causes” (Tafuri, 1975:1 ).29 Piranesi’s program proves effective, by removing the mysticism around art, and of course architecture, their conflicts and contradictions spring forth plainly: there’s no such thing as critical art or architecture, only consciousness of the place it occupies within the cycle of renewal of values.

VI.

Nonetheless, it is precisely the confirmation of ‘the given’ what Adorno criticizes of the disenchantment of positivism, which he equates with instrumental reason - he does not see science at all as an alternative to ideology, but rather as ideology itself. The brand of scientific positivism Weber argues for, as an instrument for stripping science from subjective attempts to “give the world meaning,” is interpreted by Adorno as a confirmation of the pervasiveness of reification in a world in which every aspect of life assumes the objective quality of the commodity form.30 The disenchanted outlook, with which Tafuri and Cacciari seek to expose tragedy, by means of a history deprived of ideology, is for Adorno already tragic. There’s already domination in the logical approach modern science adopts to understand the world - as its rigid structures are designed to extract sameness out of every quality, any possibility of difference is done away with. Adorno’s negativity acquires quite different connotations than Tafuri and Cacciari’s in this context. In his Negative Dialectics he deals precisely with the impossibility of what he calls “identical thinking,” namely, the unrecognized fact that there’s always mediation between knowledge and the real (Adorno, 2007). ‘The given’ only ascertains itself by way of recklessly matching the ‘order of things’ with ‘the order of ideas,’ thus solidifying the relation of knowledge with its object matter as ‘self-identical’ (Adorno, 1991:158).31 The objectivity claimed by organized science, Adorno argues, doesn’t acknowledge the ‘untruth’ of identity, i.e. that there is always a ‘remainder’ between the real and the ability of conceptual thinking to grasp it. The residue that is left out of the objective embrace of the object’s specificity by the subject is, for Adorno, a particle of potential difference and evidence of the limits of enlightened thinking to describe reality as such. The unnamable character of the ‘non-identical’ assumes for him the quality of utopia: a concept whose depiction is impossible without the loss of its redemptive potential. Adorno’s aesthetic theory relies on the impossible character of utopia, and at the same time, in art’s ability to render its existence possible: to reflect the world in ‘non-logical’ terms, potentially unlocking the indescribability of the ‘non-identical,’ and thus the hidden untruth of the world. Aesthetic semblance provides the possibility of reflecting the world not by representing it, but through its ‘mimetic faculty.’32 Mimesis is here understood no just as the ‘imitation of the world’ but a way for the image ‘to be nature entire,’ instead of just claiming to know it (A&H, 2002:13). Kafka, Beckett, Klee and Schönberg, all perform Adorno’s negative reflection as they bring about alienation and reification not by representing it, but by enacting it. Mimetic quality, furthermore, without the need for aesthetic semblance, can be attained by critical writing - precisely by rejecting the stark object-subject opposition and dissolving logic sequences in constellations of ideas Adorno calls “force fields.” Negative Dialects is the elucidation of his own writing as a philosophical “anti-system” resisting “identity thinking.” In this context, Adorno’s Enlightenment's dialectical underside does violence not only to humanity, as it reifies relations between people as though they were relations between things, but also to things themselves, as their specificity is done away with by instrumental reason, along with the utopian potential they carry.

VII.

Weber’s dispassionate detachment notwithstanding, Tafuri’s early criticism was not without mimetic qualities. In fact, his relation to Weber is evidence of the extent to which subject matter and critic are embroiled in a relationship hard to disentangle. Tafuri adopted the pressing historical issues of modernism as his own, as Anthony Vidler has suggested, he is as much a historian of disenchantment as a disenchanted historian (Vidler, 2008:9-13). Adorno’s Enlightenment is here precisely operating dialectically: Tafuri’s novalue relationship with his objects of knowledge enacts positivism’s mastery over the world with its ‘pitiless coherence’ (Tafuri, 1980:201) yet at the same time, Enlightenment's dominion is exercised over Tafuri’s himself - mastery of reason over nature, Adorno argued, is at the same time the repression of the ego, for reason inflects violence over nature as much as over inner nature. In repressing values from historical judgment, Tafuri shows us the historical nature of his disenchantment all the more: it is not just a trait of his work as a historian, but also the unmistakable sign his criticism was one of a modernist through and through. To contextualize Tafuri’s critique within the development of high modernism is not rendering it innocuous by bracketing it off historically, but quite the opposite, it means doing justice to his fearless project of reading modernity from within, without ever running away from even its most pressing contradictions. “Manfredo taught that our being vicissitude equals the necessity to mask ourselves,” wrote Massimo Cacciari for Tafuri’s funeral, “to disguise ourselves, to denature everything” (Cacciari, 1995:169). To unmask Tafuri’s intellectual project, to reconstruct the historicity of his “denaturing,” to contextualize his relationship with his subject matters, to clarify the nature of his relation with his influences, to read against the grain of his closing narrative possibilities for architectural and historical production; these are the tasks Tafuri’s still wide open legacy still demands us to assume today.

Referencias:

AAVV. «Il progetto storico di Manfredo Tafuri»/ «The Historical Project of Manfredo Tafuri.» Edited by Vittorio Gregotti. Special Issue. Casabella 619-620 (1995). [ Links ]

AAVV «Being Manfredo Tafuri: Wickedness, Anxiety, Disenchantment.» ANY: Architecture New York 25/26 (2000). [ Links ]

ADORNO, Theodor; HORKHEIMER, Max. Dialectic of Enlightenment. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002. [ Links ]

ADORNO, Theodor. Negative Dialectics. New York, London, New Delhi, Sydney: Bloomsbury, 2007. [ Links ]

ADORNO, Theodor. Aesthetic Theory. Edited by Rolf Tiedemann and Gretel Adorno, translated by Robert Hullot-Kentor. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997. [ Links ]

ADORNO, Theodor. «The Essay as Form.» In: Notes to Literature, Vol. 1, edited by Rolf Tiedemann, translated by Sherry Weber Nicholsen. New York: Columbia University Press, 1991, 151-171. [ Links ]

ADORNO, Theodor; BLOCH, Ernst. «Something’s Missing: A Discussion between Ernst Bloch and Theodor W. Adorno on the Contradictions of Utopian Longing.» In: The Utopian Function of Art and Literature: Selected Essays by Ernst Bloch. Cambridge, London: MIT Press, 1988, 1-18. [ Links ]

ASOR ROSA, Alberto. «Critique of Ideology and Historical Practice.» Casabella 619-20 (January / February, 1995): 27-29. [ Links ]

AURELI, Pier Vittorio. «Recontextualizing Tafuri’s Critique of Ideology.» Log 18 (Winter 2010), 89-100. [ Links ]

BENJAMIN, Walter. Reflections: Essays, Aphorisms, Autobiographic Writings ed. Peter Demetz. New York: Schocken Books, 2007. [ Links ]

BERMAN, Marshall. «Introducción. La Modernidad Hoy, Ayer y Mañana.» In: Todo lo Sólido se Desvanece en el Aire. La Experiencia de la Modernidad (Barcelona: Siglo XXI Editores, 1992), 1-28. [ Links ]

BIRAGHI, Marco. Project of Crisis: Manfredo Tafuri and Contemporary Architecture. Cambridge, New York: MIT Press, 2013. [ Links ]

CACCIARI, Massimo. «Sulla genesi del pensiero negative.» Contropiano 1 (1969): 186-18. [ Links ]

CACCIARI, M.; RELLA, F.; TAFURI, M.; TEYSSOT, G. Il dispositivo Foucault. Venice: CLUVA, Librería Editrice Cooperativa, 1977. [ Links ]

CACCIARI, Massimo. Krisis: Ensayo sobre la crisis de pensamiento negativo de Nietzsche a Wittgenstein. México D.F, Madrid, Bogotá: Siglo XXI Editores, 1982. [ Links ]

CACCIARI, Massimo. Architecture and Nihilism: On the Philosophy of Modern Architecture. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1993. [ Links ]

CACCIARI, Massimo. «Quid Tum» trans. Paul Blanchard. Casabella 619-620 (January / February 1995). [ Links ]

FRISBY, David. «Modernité.» In Fragments of Modernity: Theories of Modernity in the Work of Simmel, Kracauer and Benjamin. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1986. [ Links ]

HEYNEN, Hilde. Architecture and Modernity: A Critique. London, Cambridge: MIT Press , 1999. [ Links ]

HOEKSTRA, Titia Rixt. «Building versus Bildung: Manfredo Tafuri and the Construction of a Historical Discipline.» PhD Diss. University of Groningen, 2005. [ Links ]

JAMESON, Fredric. «Architecture and the Critique of Ideology.» In: Architecture Theory since 1968, edited by Michael K. Hays. Cambridge, London: MIT Press , 2000, 442-461. [ Links ]

JAY, Martin. «Toward a Philosophy of History: The Critique of Enlightenment.» In: The Dialectical Imagination. Berkley, Los Angeles, London: University of California Press, 1973, 253-281. [ Links ]

KEYVANIAN, Carla. «Manfredo Tafuri’s notion of history and its methodological sources: From Walter Benjamin to Roland Barthes.» PhD. Diss. Massachusetts institute of technology, 1992. [ Links ]

LEACH, Andrew. «Choosing History: A Study of Manfredo Tafuri’s Theorisation of Architectural History and Architectural History Research.» PhD. Diss. Ghent University, 2005-2006. [ Links ]

LIERNUR, Francisco. «Vigencia de Tafuri. Consideraciones sobre la crítica contemporánea de arquitectura en América Latina.» In: Arquitectura en Teoría: Escritos 1986-2010. Buenos Aires: Sociedad Central de Arquitectos, 2010, 131-146. [ Links ]

LIERNUR, Francisco; GORELIK, Adrián; AGUILAR, Gonzalo. «‘Mientras el furor domina el mundo’: Tafuri hoy. Entrevista a Francisco Liernur y Adrián Gorelik.» Informe Escaleno (8 Nov, 2015). Retrieved from: Retrieved from: http://www.informeescaleno.com.ar/index.php?s=articulos&id=390 . Accessed, 19 January 2017 [ Links ]

SIMMEL, Georg. The Philosophy of Money. London, New York: Routledge, 2011. [ Links ]

TAFURI, Manfredo. Architecture and Utopia: Design and Capitalist Development. Translated by Barbara Luigia La Penta. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1975. [ Links ]

TAFURI, Manfredo. Theories and History of Architecture. New York: Harpers & Row Publishers, 1980. [ Links ]

TAFURI, Manfredo. «Para una crítica a la ideología arquitectónica.» In: De la vanguardia a la Metrópoli: crítica radical a la arquitectura, Barcelona: Gustavo Gili, 1981. 13-17. [ Links ]

TAFURI, Manfredo; Daguerre, Mercedes; Lupo, Giulio. «Entrevista a Manfredo Tafuri.» Materiales 1 (March 1985). [ Links ]

TAFURI, Manfredo. The Sphere and the Labyrinth: Avant-Gardes and Architecture from Piranesi to the 1970s. Cambridge, London: MIT Press , 1987. [ Links ]

TAFURI, Manfredo; VERY, Françoise. «The Culture Markets: Françoise Very interviews Manfredo Tafuri.» Casabella 619-20 (January / February 1995). [ Links ]

VIDLER, Anthony. «Disenchanted Histories: The Legacies of Manfredo Tafuri.» ANY: Architecture New York 25/26, «Being Manfredo Tafuri: Wickedness, Anxiety, Disenchantment» (2000): 9-13. [ Links ]

VIDLER, Anthony. Histories of the Immediate Present: Inventing Architectural Modernism. Cambridge, New York: MIT Press , 2008. [ Links ]

WEBER, Max. «La Ciencia como Vocación.» In: El político y el científico. Buenos Aires: Prometeo Libros, 2009, 47-48. [ Links ]

*

Pedro Correa Architect, Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile, 2012, M.Sc Critical, Curatorial and Conceptual Practices, Columbia University, USA, 2016. Assistant professor at School of Architecture UC in the area of Theory, History and Criticism, where he teaches subjects associated with aesthetics and politics from the end of the 19th century until the first half of the 20th century. He currently works as a researcher and associate curator at a Fondart project on architectural biennials in Chile, along with Fernando Carvajal, Fernando Portal and Rayna Razmilic.

Creative Commons License Este es un artículo publicado en acceso abierto bajo una licencia Creative Commons