Skip to main content

GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Psychol., 30 August 2013
Sec. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology

Concerns with attempts by neuroeconomics to answer the philosophical question “Is it rational to donate money for charity?”

  • Indian Institute of Technology Gandhinagar, Ahmedabad, Gujarat, India

A commentary on
Neural responses to taxation and voluntary giving reveal motives for charitable donations

by Harbaugh, W. T., Mayr, U., and Burghart, D. R. (2007). Science 316, 1622–1625. doi: 10.1126/science.1140738

Altruism involves acting toward the welfare of others by incurring costs to the self (Batson and Shaw, 1991). The theoretical question is: Why would people help others who are unrelated genetically? This was considered a “large anomaly” from rationality by neo-classical economics (Fehr and Fischbacher, 2003) as humans are assumed to be maximizers of decision utility—a purely selfish “homo-economicus” who should not spend on unrelated others. However, money given to the poor could create a private good for the recipient but at the same time, it creates a non-rival non-excludable benefit (or utility) for all those citizens who value a condition where poor people are also well fed and can live a decent life (Mayr et al., 2009). Thus, there could be a “warm glow” (Andreoni, 1995) by giving to charity (“impure altruism”).

Harbaugh et al. (2007) designed a novel experiment which strikingly showed that both mandatory and voluntary transfers to charity show neural activity in the brain areas associated with reward processing with larger activations following voluntary transfers. These results support both pure and impure forms of altruism. The brain areas implicated were medial orbitofrontal cortex (OFC) and the dorso-lateral prefrontal cortex (DLPFC) along with the ventral striatum, nucleus accumbens (NAcc) and the insulae which form parts of the reward circuitry that codes most real life rewards (like money, drugs and chocolates). The authors later argued that these results show donating to charity is inherently rewarding and rational (Mayr et al., 2009).

The reasoning adopted was: If brain area B is involved in coding rewards which have inherent utility and then we observe area B is involved in donations, then there is utility in donating and hence donating is rational (see Mayr et al., 2009). Is this conclusion warranted from the current data?

This line of reasoning uses reverse inference—a widespread but questionable technique (Poldrack, 2006) in neuroeconomics which infers mental states from brain states. The conclusions could be flawed under the assumptions of functionalism as multiple brain states can map to multiple mental states in a non-exclusive manner (Levin and Aharon, 2011).

In fact, multiple studies highlight the same brain areas implicated by Harbaugh and colleagues for other cognitive processes apart from donations. For example, medial frontal and posterior cingulate are also involved in moral decision making (Greene et al., 2001) while ventral OFC represent outcome values of primary reinforcers and abstract rewards (Peters and Büchel, 2010). Experienced utility and predictive error involved in both monetary and social reward tasks activate the vMPFC and straitum (Lin et al., 2012). It is now commonly accepted that generally the vMPFC is involved in valuation and a modulation of these signals is performed in the DLPFC which is a seat of self-control and emotion regulation (Hare et al., 2008). Thus, even though I do not attempt to provide a comprehensive review, it is obvious that the problem of inferring whether donating is a rational act by observing activations of the reward circuitry is not easy. Note that in an experiment even if a brain area (meso-limbic reward circuit) is active for both monetary rewards and donations (Moll et al., 2006), we cannot conclude that donating is rewarding or rational by itself or that there is a utility in donating.

Part of the theoretical confusion is due to multiple usages of “utility.” If one uses the concept of decision utility based on economical grounds, then charity might seem irrational (Fehr and Fischbacher, 2003). However, if one uses the hedonic form where utility stems from maximizing pleasures for oneself (“experienced utility”; Kahneman et al., 1997) then both pure altruism and warm-glow could have utility, since both maximize pleasures of seeing somebody gain (pure altruism) or of feeling good oneself (warm-glow).

The other important demonstration by Harbaugh et al. (2007) was that neural responses (in the reward circuit including the NAcc) to pure charity gains after subtracting responses to pure personal gains predict the rate of accepting altruistic transfers to some extent (27%). Whether responding to gains to oneself and gains to an organization neutrally code the same process is not clear. Hence, what a subtraction between these two conditions means is likewise not clear. As activations in the NAcc can increase not only for anticipated gains, but also for anticipated losses (Carter et al., 2009), it is possible that activations for charity gains can also be construed as personal losses. Also, note that the prediction is constructed from six different brain regions (averaged together) that in a way supposes that all these areas encode value, but what kind of utility is encoded and what computations are performed? It is of course possible that monetary gains to oneself and a charity are both valuable because both increase experienced utility. Crucially, future studies need to add more clarity about the motivational relevance of monetary transfers, definitions of utility being referred to and associated pre-suppositions.

Further, in general, what is meant by rational is often not explicit. If “rational” is to desire more of “good things,” it can be seen as experienced utility and if we take the normative route, it is confined to decision utility. But, is it epistemic or instrumental rationality? (Kelly, 2003). Even though rationality is taken as a starting point in economic analysis it is often not clear why that should be so (Foley, 2004). In fact, Foley argues that this supposes an imposition of modern capitalist social understanding which is simply one way society functions. Finally, if moral requirements instigate donating to social causes (Kant's categorical imperative; Johnson, 2012) or altruism is rational in itself (Nagel, 1978), then doesn't donating become rational by definition? These questions require more work before making convincing philosophical or theoretical deductions related to the rational basis of altruism.

I do not intend to suggest that the reasoning is wrong; but, conclusions from neuroscientific works are often based on many undisclosed assumptions and incomplete ontology, which requires more criticality to settle philosophical questions.

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the associate editor (Michael L. Anderson) for helpful feedbacks on previous versions of the manuscript.

References

Andreoni, J. (1995). Cooperation in public-goods experiments: kindness or confusion? Am. Econ. Rev. 85, 891–904.

Batson, C. D., and Shaw, L. L. (1991). Evidence for altruism: toward a pluralism of prosocial motives. Psychol. Inq. 2, 107–122. doi: 10.1207/s15327965pli0202_1

CrossRef Full Text

Carter, R. M., MacInnes, J. J., Huettel, S. A., and Adcock, R. A. (2009). Activation in the VTA and nucleus accumbens increases in anticipation of both gains and losses. Front. Behav. Neurosci. 3:21. doi: 10.3389/neuro.08.021.2009

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Fehr, E., and Fischbacher, U. (2003). The nature of human altruism. Nature 425, 785–791. doi: 10.1038/nature02043

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Foley, D. K. (2004). Rationality and ideology in economics. Soc. Res. Int. Q. 71, 329–342.

Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M., and Cohen, J. D. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science 293, 2105–2108. doi: 10.1126/science.1062872

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Harbaugh, W. T., Mayr, U., and Burghart, D. R. (2007). Neural responses to taxation and voluntary giving reveal motives for charitable donations. Science 316, 1622–1625. doi: 10.1126/science.1140738

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Hare, T. A., O'Doherty, J., Camerer, C. F., Schultz, W., and Rangel, A. (2008). Dissociating the role of the orbitofrontal cortex and the striatum in the computation of goal values and prediction errors. J. Neurosci. 28, 5623–5630. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.1309-08.2008

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Johnson, R. (2012). “Kant's moral philosophy,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2012 Edition, ed E. N. Zalta. Available online at: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/kant-moral/.

Kahneman, D., Wakker, P. P., and Sarin, R. (1997). Back to Bentham? Explorations of experienced utility. Q.J. Econ. 112, 375–406. doi: 10.1162/003355397555235

CrossRef Full Text

Kelly, T. (2003). Epistemic rationality as instrumental rationality: a critique. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 66, 612–640.

Levin, Y., and Aharon, I. (2011). What's on your mind? A brain scan won't tell. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 2, 699–722.

Lin, A., Adolphs, R., and Rangel, A. (2012). Social and monetary reward learning engage overlapping neural substrates. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 7, 274–281. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsr006

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Mayr, U., Harbaugh, W. T., and Tankersley, D. (2009). “Neuroeconomics of charitable giving and philanthropy,” in Neuroeconomics: Decision Making and the Brain, eds P. W. Glimcher, C. F. Camerer, E. Fehr, and R. A. Poldrack (London: Elsevier, Academic Press), 303–320.

Moll, J., Krueger, F., Zahn, R., Pardini, M., de Oliveira-Souza, R., and Grafman, J. (2006). Human fronto–mesolimbic networks guide decisions about charitable donation. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 103, 15623–15628. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0604475103

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Nagel, T. (1978). The Possibility of Altruism. New York, NY: Princeton University Press.

Peters, J., and Büchel, C. (2010). Neural representations of subjective reward value. Behav. Brain Res. 213, 135–141. doi: 10.1016/j.bbr.2010.04.031

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Poldrack, R. A. (2006). Can cognitive processes be inferred from neuroimaging data? Trends Cogn. Sci. 10, 59–63. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2005.12.004

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Keywords: donations, altruism, neuroeconomics, rational, brain mapping

Citation: Mukherjee S (2013) Concerns with attempts by neuroeconomics to answer the philosophical question “Is it rational to donate money for charity?” Front. Psychol. 4:585. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00585

Received: 16 July 2013; Accepted: 13 August 2013;
Published online: 30 August 2013.

Edited by:

Michael L. Anderson, Franklin and Marshall College, USA

Copyright © 2013 Mukherjee. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: sumitava.inbox@gmail.com

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.