Skip to content
Publicly Available Published by De Gruyter July 18, 2017

Brauer characters and fields of values

  • Dan Rossi EMAIL logo
From the journal Journal of Group Theory

Abstract

For a prime number p and a finite group G, we consider the set of p-Brauer characters of G taking values in some field 𝔽 (called 𝔽-Brauer characters) and the set of conjugacy classes of p-regular elements of G whose value at every Brauer character lies in 𝔽 (called 𝔽-conjugacy classes). We show that these sets for G and for G/N are closely related, for certain normal subgroups N of G. This is a p-modular version of a result of Isaacs and Navarro in characteristic 0 (see [3]).

1 Introduction

Let G be a finite group and let π”½βŠ†β„‚ be any subfield of the field of complex numbers. If Ο‡ is a complex character of G such that χ⁒(x)βˆˆπ”½ for every element x∈G, then we say Ο‡ is an 𝔽-character and we write Irr𝔽⁑(G) for the set of all irreducible 𝔽-characters. Analogously, if χ⁒(x)βˆˆπ”½ for every complex character Ο‡, then we say x is an 𝔽-element. Since characters are constant on conjugacy classes, we may unambiguously say that the conjugacy class xG is an 𝔽-class; we write Cl𝔽⁑(G) for the set of 𝔽-classes of G. If HβŠ†G is any subset and H contains no non-trivial 𝔽-elements of G, then we say H is 𝔽-free in G. We emphasize that the notion of H being 𝔽-free is always relative to some overgroup G.

In [3] Isaacs and Navarro prove that the sets Irr𝔽⁑(G) and Irr𝔽⁑(G/N), respectively Cl𝔽⁑(G) and Cl𝔽⁑(G/N), are closely related whenever N◁G is an 𝔽-free normal subgroup. More precisely, they show the following.

Theorem 1 ([3, Theorem A]).

Let F be a subfield of the complex numbers and suppose that N is an F-free normal subgroup of the finite group G. Then the canonical homomorphism Gβ†’G/N defines a bijection from ClF⁑(G) to ClF⁑(G/N).

Theorem 2 ([3, Theorem B]).

Let F be a subfield of the complex numbers and let G be a finite group. Then G contains a unique largest F-free normal subgroup N, and N is contained in the kernel of every irreducible F-character of G.

In this paper we prove analogues of these Isaacs–Navarro theorems in the modular setting. Fix a prime number p. We write G∘ for the set of p-regular elements of G, i.e. the elements with order coprime to p. If SβŠ†G is any subset, we define S∘:=S∩G∘. We choose a maximal ideal of the ring of algebraic integers that contains p. We denote by IBrp⁑(G) the set of irreducible p-Brauer characters of G, calculated with respect to this ideal. When the prime p is understood, we will write Brauer character in place of p-Brauer character and IBr⁑(G) in place of IBrp⁑(G).

As in the ordinary character setting, if Ο• is any Brauer character of G, we say Ο• is an 𝔽-Brauer character if ϕ⁒(x)βˆˆπ”½ for every x∈G∘. The set of irreducible 𝔽-Brauer characters of G is denoted IBr𝔽⁑(G), or IBrp,𝔽⁑(G) when it is necessary to emphasize the prime. Similarly, if x∈G∘ and ϕ⁒(x)βˆˆπ”½ for every Brauer character of G, then we say x is an 𝔽-element, xG is an 𝔽-class, and write Clπ”½βˆ˜β‘(G) for the set of 𝔽-classes of p-regular elements in G. At the moment it appears we have defined β€œπ”½-element” in two different ways, once in terms of ordinary characters and once in terms of Brauer characters. There is actually no cause for confusion, as the two notions agree whenever x∈G∘. If Ο‡ is an ordinary character of G, then we write Ο‡βˆ˜ for the restriction of Ο‡ to G∘. Every Brauer character is a β„€-linear combination of {Ο‡βˆ˜:Ο‡βˆˆIrr⁑(G)}; and conversely every Ο‡βˆ˜, for Ο‡βˆˆIrr⁑(G), is a β„€-linear combination of IBr⁑(G) (see e.g. [5, Chapter 2]). Thus, for any x∈G∘, it follows that χ⁒(x)βˆˆπ”½ for every ordinary character Ο‡ if and only if ϕ⁒(x)βˆˆπ”½ for every Brauer character Ο•.

Now we can state our main results.

Theorem A.

Let p be a prime number and F any subfield of the field of complex numbers. Let N◁G and assume that N∘ is F-free in G. Then the canonical homomorphism Gβ†’G/N induces a bijection from ClF∘⁑(G) to ClF∘⁑(G/N).

Theorem B.

Let p be a prime number and F any subfield of the field of complex numbers. Then G has a unique largest normal subgroup N with the property that N∘ is F-free in G; N is contained in the kernel of every Ο•βˆˆIBrF⁑(G).

A word of caution is necessary here: The set IBr⁑(G) is not canonically defined, depending on the choice of a maximal ideal made above. However, we recall that any two choices of IBr⁑(G) are Galois conjugate (see [5, Theorem 2.34]). In particular, fields of values for the entire set of all Brauer characters are canonically defined. Thus Theorems A and B hold true for any choice of IBr⁑(G).

The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 collects some preliminary results. In Section 3 we prove the surjectivity assertion in Theorem A and the first part of Theorem B. We complete the proof of Theorem B in Section 4. Section 5 establishes the injectivity assertion in Theorem A, thereby completing the proof; it constitutes the bulk of the work in the paper.

2 Preliminaries

Assumption 1.

For the remainder of this paper we fix a field π”½βŠ†β„‚ and a prime number p.

We begin with a useful lemma that will help control the structure of subgroups N◁G when N∘ is 𝔽-free in G.

Lemma 2.

Let S be a non-abelian simple group. Then S has a rational element of order 3 or 5 unless S=PSL2⁑(32⁒n+1), nβ‰₯1, which has no non-trivial rational elements of odd order.

Proof.

See [6, Theorems 11.1 and 11.2]. ∎

In the proofs of Theorems A and B later on, the first step will be to reduce to the situation where N is minimal normal in G and N∘ is 𝔽-free in G. In this case N≃S1×…×Sr with each Si≃S, a simple group. It turns out that if N is solvable, then Theorems A and B can be proved in basically the same way as the analogous Isaacs–Navarro results above. Now if N∘ is 𝔽-free in G, then certainly it is β„š-free in G and, since involutions are automatically rational, if p>2, then it follows that |N| is odd and thus N is solvable. When p=2, it is no longer the case that N must be solvable – this is the main obstacle we must overcome in order to prove Theorems A and B. In this situation, Lemma 2 forces that S=PSL2⁑(32⁒n+1) and we shall exploit this observation in Sections 4 and 5.

Before proceeding further we must recall some notions from [3]. For any integer n, β„šn denotes the cyclotomic field obtained by adjoining to β„š a primitive nth root of unity. If ΞΆ is any nth root of unity and ΟƒβˆˆGal⁑(β„šn/β„š), then ΞΆΟƒ=ΞΆk for some integer k coprime to n. If G is a group with exponent dividing n, then Gal⁑(β„šn/β„š) acts on G by xΟƒ=xk, with k as in the previous sentence. This also induces actions on Cl⁑(G) and Cl∘⁑(G) by (xG)Οƒ=(xk)G. If G is abelian, then the action of Gal⁑(β„šn/β„š) on G is by automorphisms. In particular, if C is cyclic of order n, then this action defines a natural map Gal⁑(β„šn/β„š)β†’Aut⁑(C), which is in fact an isomorphism. Now write 𝕂=π”½βˆ©β„šn, so Gal⁑(β„šn/𝕂)≀Gal⁑(β„šn/β„š). Furthermore, we write Aut𝔽⁑(C) for the image of this subgroup under the isomorphism Gal⁑(β„šn/β„š)β†’Aut⁑(C) just described. If C≀G, then we say C is 𝔽-cyclic in G if the subgroup of Aut⁑(C) induced by NG⁒(C) contains Aut𝔽⁑(C). In particular, we see that C is 𝔽-cyclic in G if and only if it is 𝕂-cyclic.

An easy consequence of the definitions is the following.

Lemma 3.

Let x∈G and write X=γ€ˆx〉. If x is an F-element in G, then X is F-cyclic in G. Conversely, if X is F-cyclic in G, then every element of X is an F-element in G.

Proof.

This is [3, Lemma 2.1]. ∎

The next statement is an almost trivial, but useful, observation.

Lemma 4.

Let X=γ€ˆx〉 and Y=γ€ˆy〉 be cyclic groups of order m and n, respectively, and assume that m divides n. If y↦yt is an automorphism in AutF⁑(Y), then x↦xt is an automorphism in AutF⁑(X). Moreover, every element of the group AutF⁑(X) arises in this way.

Proof.

Let 𝕂=π”½βˆ©β„šn and 𝔼=π”½βˆ©β„šm=π•‚βˆ©β„šm. By basic Galois theory, restriction to 𝔼 defines a surjection from Gal⁑(β„šn/𝕂) onto Gal⁑(β„šm/𝔼). Now the lemma follows from the definitions of Aut𝔽⁑(X) and Aut𝔽⁑(Y). ∎

We conclude this section with one more lemma.

Lemma 5.

Let M and N be normal subgroups of the finite group G and assume that N∩M=1. Let G¯=G/M. Then n∈N is an F-element in G if and only if n¯ is an F-element in G¯.

Proof.

Clearly, if n is an 𝔽-element in G, then nΒ― is one in GΒ―.

So assume that nΒ― is an 𝔽-element in GΒ―. Let ψt:n↦nt be any automorphism in Aut𝔽⁑(γ€ˆn〉). Because N∩M=1, we have o⁒(n)=o⁒(nΒ―) and so, by Lemma 4, the map Ο•t:n¯↦nΒ―t is in Aut𝔽⁑(γ€ˆn¯〉). Thus there is some g∈G with nΒ―gΒ―=nΒ―t. Then ng=nt⁒m for some m∈M. But then m=ng⁒n-t∈M∩N=1 and so ng=nt. Thus g induces on γ€ˆn〉 the automorphism ψt and we conclude that n is an 𝔽-element of G. ∎

3 Lifts

We are now ready to begin proving the main results. We start by proving the surjectivity assertion in Theorem A. Interestingly, for this we do not need to separately consider the case p=2 and N non-solvable. All of the proofs in this section follow [3] nearly exactly; we need only check that certain elements are actually p-regular. We include the arguments in full in order to give a sense of just how similar they are. Later on, we will include less detail whenever we mimic the proofs contained in [3].

Theorem 1.

Let N◁G and assume that N∘ is F-free in G. Then the canonical homomorphism Gβ†’G/N induces a surjection ClF∘⁑(G)β†’ClF∘⁑(G/N).

Proof.

Identifying the Brauer characters of G/N with a subset of the Brauer characters of G, it is clear that images of 𝔽-elements of G are 𝔽-elements of G/N. And clearly images of p-regular elements are p-regular. Thus, to prove the theorem we must show that if N⁒x∈G/N is a p-regular 𝔽-element, then the coset Nx contains a p-regular 𝔽-element of G. Assume this is false and let G have minimal order among counterexamples. Also assume that N has minimal order among normal subgroups K such that K∘ is 𝔽-free in G and K gives rise to a counterexample.

Suppose that 1<M<N with M◁G and note that M∘ is 𝔽-free in G. We claim that (N/M)∘ is 𝔽-free in G/M. To see this, let M⁒y∈N/M be p-regular and assume My is an 𝔽-element in G/M. By the minimality of N among counterexamples, My contains a p-regular 𝔽-element x of G. Since M⁒yβŠ†N and N∘ is 𝔽-free in G, it follows that x=1 and My is the identity in G/M, i.e. (N/M)∘ is 𝔽-free in G/M, as claimed.

Now set GΒ―=G/M. Then G/N≃GΒ―/NΒ― and N⁒xΒ― is a p-regular 𝔽-element of GΒ―/NΒ―. By minimality of G among counterexample groups and since N¯∘ is 𝔽-free in GΒ―, it follows that there is a p-regular 𝔽-element of GΒ― contained in N⁒xΒ―, call it yΒ―. Equivalently, My is a p-regular 𝔽-element in G/M. Again by the minimality of N we deduce that My contains a p-regular 𝔽-element z of G. Finally, M⁒yβŠ†N⁒x, so z∈N⁒x is a p-regular 𝔽-element of G. This contradicts our assumption about N and so we must have that N is minimal normal in G.

Next, we argue that N≀Φ⁒(G), the Frattini subgroup. To see this, let H be a maximal subgroup of G and assume, aiming for a contradiction, that Nβ‰°H. Then N⁒H=G and N⁒x=N⁒h for some h∈H. Let D=N∩H and note that the natural isomorphism G/Nβ†’H/D sends Nx to Dh. Since Nx is a p-regular 𝔽-element in G/N, it follows that Dh is a p-regular 𝔽-element in H/D. Also, 𝔽-elements of H are automatically 𝔽-elements of G and so it follows that D∘ is 𝔽-free in H. By the minimality of G we conclude that D⁒hβŠ†N⁒x contains a p-regular 𝔽-element of G, but we are assuming that this is not the case. This contradiction implies that N≀H and so N≀Φ⁒(G). In particular, N is nilpotent and thus, since N is minimal normal in G, N is an elementary abelian β„“-group for some prime β„“.

Let U=Nβ’γ€ˆx〉. We argue that U◁G. Now U/N is 𝔽-cyclic in G/N and thus it is 𝔽-cyclic in L/N, where L/N=NG/N⁒(U/N). Aiming for a contradiction, suppose that L<G. Then by minimality of G, the coset Nx contains a p-regular 𝔽-element of L, which is automatically a p-regular 𝔽-element of G. But we are assuming Nx contains no such element and this contradiction implies that L=G, i.e. U◁G. Also note that U/N is cyclic and N≀Φ⁒(G), whence U is nilpotent (by [2, Lemma 9.19]).

Assume that β„“=p, i.e. N is a p-group. Since U is nilpotent and x is p-regular, it follows that V:=γ€ˆx〉 is the p-complement in U. In particular, V◁G. Since V≃U/N as G-sets (under the conjugation action of G) and U/N is 𝔽-cyclic in G/N, we conclude that V is 𝔽-cyclic in G. By Lemma 3, every element of V is an 𝔽-element. In particular, x is an 𝔽-element in G and x is p-regular.

If instead β„“β‰ p, then every element of N is p-regular and N∘=N is 𝔽-free in G. Thus by the Isaacs–Navarro Theorem 1Nx contains an 𝔽-element y of G. Now N⁒x=N⁒y and, since γ€ˆy〉 is 𝔽-cyclic in G, by Lemma 3 it follows that γ€ˆyγ€‰βˆ©N=1. We conclude that o⁒(y)=o⁒(N⁒y), so y is p-regular. This is our final contradiction, and the proof is complete. ∎

We obtain the following useful corollary. The reductions in Theorems 5 and 6 to the case N is minimal normal in G rely on this statement. It is the p-modular analogue of [3, Corollary 3.4].

Corollary 2.

Let M and N be normal subgroups of the finite group G with M≀N and suppose that N∘ is F-free in G. Then (N/M)∘ is F-free in G/M.

Proof.

Suppose that Mx is a p-regular 𝔽-element of G/M, where M⁒x∈N/M. Then by Theorem 1Mx contains a p-regular 𝔽-element y of G. Since M⁒xβŠ†N and N∘ is 𝔽-free in G, it follows that y=1 and thus Mx is the identity of G/M, as required. ∎

Also, the first part of Theorem B follows easily. We can actually prove something slightly more general.

Corollary 3.

Assume that M and N are normal subgroups of G and that M∘ and N∘ are F-free in G. Then M⁒N◁G and (M⁒N)∘ is F-free in G. In particular, G has a unique largest normal subgroup K such that K∘ is F-free in G.

Proof.

The second statement follows from the first by taking K to be the subgroup of G generated by all normal subgroups N of G such that N∘ is 𝔽-free in G.

For the first statement, obviously M⁒N◁G. Let ψ be the natural G-isomorphism from M⁒N/M to N/(N∩M). We make the following general observation: If C/M is 𝔽-cyclic in G/M, with M≀C≀M⁒N, and if C/M has order coprime to p, then ψ⁒(C/M) is 𝔽-cyclic in G/(M∩N) and so all the elements of ψ⁒(C/M) are p-regular 𝔽-elements of G/(M∩N).

Now let x∈M⁒N be a p-regular 𝔽-element of G. We must show that x=1. Note that Mx is a p-regular 𝔽-element in G/M and we let C/M be the cyclic subgroup of G/M generated by Mx. By the previous paragraph, ψ⁒(C/M) is 𝔽-cyclic in G/(M∩N) and ψ⁒(C/M) has order coprime to p. But ψ⁒(C/M) is contained in N/(M∩N) and (N/(M∩N))∘ is 𝔽-free in G/(M∩N), by Corollary 2. It follows that ψ⁒(C/M) is the identity in G/(M∩N), so C/M is the identity in G/M, i.e. C=M. Thus x∈M and since M∘ is 𝔽-free in G we conclude x=1, as needed. ∎

4 Character kernels

It takes a bit more work to complete the proof of Theorem B. As mentioned earlier, the critical case for us will be when N is a non-abelian minimal normal subgroup of G and N∘ is 𝔽-free in G. By the remarks following Lemma 2, we must have p=2 and N=S1×…×Sr, where Si≃S and S=PSL2⁑(32⁒n+1). As is well known, if Οƒ is a Galois automorphism and Ο• a Brauer character, then in general ϕσ need not be a Brauer character. But it turns out that Gal⁑(β„šΒ―/β„š) does actually act on IBr2⁑(S) (see [7, Proposition 3.2 (ii)]). In fact, as we shall soon see, more is true. The next three results will allow us to adapt an important step in the proof of [3, Theorem 4.1] to work in our critical situation.

We establish some notation to be used in the next lemma: Let S=PSL2⁑(q), where q=32⁒n+1 and nβ‰₯1. Let Nq:=3(q2-1)/8=exp(S)2β€² and let Ο΅ be a primitive Nqth root of unity. Then every Ο•βˆˆIBr⁑(S) has values in β„šβ’(Ο΅).

Lemma 1.

In the above notation, there is a bijection ϕ↦CΟ• between irreducible 2-Brauer characters of the group S=PSL2⁑(32⁒n+1) and conjugacy classes of odd-order elements in S that is compatible with the actions of Aut⁑(S) and Gal⁑(Q⁒(Ο΅)/Q), in the following sense. If CΟ•=xS for Ο•βˆˆIBr2⁑(S) and x∈S, then the following statements hold:

  1. for any Ο„βˆˆAut⁑(S), Cϕτ=(xΟ„)S,

  2. for any ΟƒβˆˆGal⁑(β„šβ’(Ο΅)/β„š), Cϕσ=(xΟƒ)S,

  3. for any Ο„βˆˆAut⁑(S), ΟƒβˆˆGal⁑(β„šβ’(Ο΅)/β„š), and Ο•βˆˆIBr2⁑(S), ϕσ=ϕτ if and only if Cϕσ=Cϕτ.

Proof.

The existence of the bijection and statements (i)–(ii) are [7, Lemma 3.4], and statement (iii) is an immediate consequence of (i) and (ii). ∎

Corollary 2.

Let N be a minimal normal subgroup of G and suppose that N=S1×…×Sr≃Sr, where S=PSL2⁑(32⁒n+1). For Ο•=Ο•1×…×ϕr∈IBr2⁑(N), let x=(x1,…,xr)∈N, where CΟ•i=(xi)Si in the notation of Lemma 1. Set CΟ•:=xN. Then the map ϕ↦CΟ• is a bijection between IBr2⁑(N) and Cl∘⁑(N) that is compatible with the actions of G and Gal⁑(Q⁒(Ο΅)/Q), in the sense of (i)–(iii) in Lemma 1.

Proof.

See [7, Corollary 3.5]. As in Lemma 1, statement (iii) follows at once from (i) and (ii). ∎

In the next statement, we use the following notation. If X is any group, then for any η∈IBr⁑(X) we define β„šβ’(Ξ·) to be the field obtained by adjoining to β„š all of the values η⁒(g) for g∈X. Similarly, if g∈X, then we define β„šβ’(gX) to be the field obtained by adjoining to β„š all of the values η⁒(g) for η∈IBr⁑(X).

Corollary 3.

Let N be a minimal normal subgroup of G and suppose that N=S1×…×Sr≃Sr, where S=PSL2⁑(32⁒n+1). Let Ο•βˆˆIBr2⁑(N) and let CΟ• be as in Corollary 2. Then Q⁒(Ο•)=Q⁒(CΟ•).

Proof.

Let Ο•=Ο•1×…×ϕr, CΟ•=(x1,…,xr)N. Now β„šβ’(Ο•)=β„šβ’(Ο•1,…,Ο•r) (by evaluating ϕ⁒(y) for elements y∈N with all but one component equal to 1∈S) and likewise β„šβ’(CΟ•)=β„šβ’(x1S,…,xrS) (by evaluating η⁒(x) for characters η∈IBr2⁑(N) with all but one component equal to 1S∈IBr2⁑(S)). Thus it suffices to prove the claim for r=1. This follows by inspecting the character table of SL2⁑(32⁒n+1), which can be found e.g. in [1, Chapter 38], and the explicit description of the map ϕ↦CΟ•, as given in [7]. ∎

Proposition 4.

Assume that N=S1×…×Sr≃Sr is a minimal normal subgroup of G, where S=PSL2⁑(32⁒n+1) for some nβ‰₯1. Assume that θ∈IBr2,F⁑(G) and Nβ‰°ker⁑θ. Then N∘ contains a non-trivial F-element of G.

Proof.

Let Ο•βˆˆIBr2⁑(N) be a non-trivial constituent of the restriction ΞΈN. Let N=exp(S)2β€², n=|G|, 𝕂=π”½βˆ©β„šN, and 𝔼=π”½βˆ©β„šn. Then 𝕂=π”Όβˆ©β„šN and so restriction to β„šN defines a surjection from Gal⁑(β„šn/𝔼) onto Gal⁑(β„šN/𝕂). Note that ΞΈ is an 𝔼-character and that x∈N∘ is an 𝔽-element in G if and only if it is a 𝕂-element.

Now let ΟƒβˆˆGal⁑(β„šN/𝕂) and choose Ο„βˆˆGal⁑(β„šn/𝔼) whose restriction to β„šN is Οƒ. Since ΞΈΟ„=ΞΈ, it follows that ϕτ=ϕσ also enters ΞΈN (Ο•ΟƒβˆˆIBr2⁑(N) by [7, Proposition 3.2 (ii)]) and thus there is some g∈G with Ο•g=ϕσ. Let CΟ• be the conjugacy class of N corresponding to Ο• under the bijection of Corollary 2. Then by Corollary 2 we have CΟ•g=Cϕσ and, by Corollary 3, we conclude that any x∈CΟ• is a 𝕂-element in G, whence it is an 𝔽-element. Since Ο•β‰ 1N, CΟ• is non-trivial and so the proof is complete. ∎

We can now prove the assertion in Theorem B about character kernels.

Theorem 5.

Let Ο•βˆˆIBrF⁑(G) and assume that N is a normal subgroup of G and that N∘ is F-free in G. Then N≀ker⁑ϕ.

Proof.

Assume that the theorem is false. Arguing as in [3, Theorem 4.1], we may assume N is minimal normal in G. If N is not solvable, then, by the remarks following Lemma 2, we must have p=2 and N≃Sr, where S=PSL2⁑(32⁒n+1). Applying Proposition 4, we obtain a contradiction.

So N is solvable and thus N is an elementary abelian β„“-group for some prime β„“. We have β„“β‰ p, as otherwise N≀Op⁒(G)≀ker⁑ϕ, e.g. by [5, Lemma 2.32]. Now the remainder of the proof of [3, Theorem 4.1] goes through unchanged (the point is, since N is a pβ€²-group, we can identify IBr⁑(N) with Irr⁑(N)). ∎

5 Conjugacy

Now we work toward proving the injectivity assertion in Theorem A, which is the major part of the paper. As usual, the critical case is N=PSL2(32⁒n+1)r and p=2.

Lemma 1.

Suppose that M,N◁G, M∩N=1, and N∘ is F-free in G. Let x,y∈G∘ be F-elements such that N⁒x=N⁒y∈G/N. If x∈M, then x=y.

Proof.

We have x⁒n-1=y for some n∈N. Also, [M,N]≀M∩N=1 and so [x,n]=1. Thus

1=yo⁒(y)=xo⁒(y)⁒n-o⁒(y)⟹no⁒(y)=xo⁒(y)∈N∩M=1.

It follows that o(n)∣o(y) and thus n∈N∘. Now A:=NG⁒(γ€ˆy〉) induces on γ€ˆy〉 a group of automorphisms containing Aut𝔽⁑(γ€ˆy〉). Let n↦nt be any automorphism in Aut𝔽⁑(γ€ˆn〉). By Lemma 4 we may express t in such a way that some g∈A induces on γ€ˆy〉 the map y↦yt. Then

xg⁒(n-1)g=(x⁒n-1)g=yg=yt=(x⁒n-1)t=xt⁒n-t,

so (n-1)g⁒nt=(x-1)g⁒xt∈N∩M=1. We conclude that ng=nt, so n is an 𝔽-element in G. Thus n=1 and x=y. ∎

Lemma 2.

Fix an integer n and assume that x∈H≀Sym⁑(n) has prime order β„“ and is an F-element in H. Let t=|Qβ„“:F∩Qβ„“|. Then there is some h∈H such that the natural action of γ€ˆh〉 on n points has an orbit of length t.

Proof.

We will identify {0,1,…,(β„“-1)}=𝔽ℓ, the field with β„“ elements.

Since x is an 𝔽-element, there is some g∈H with g⁒x⁒g-1=xa, where a has order t in 𝔽ℓ×. Also, since x has order β„“, the non-trivial orbits of γ€ˆx〉 all have length β„“. Let Ξ©1,…,Ξ©m denote these orbits.

Now g permutes the Ξ©i. We may assume that

g:Ξ©1β†’Ξ©2→…→Ωjβ†’Ξ©1

(possibly j=1). We label the points of Ξ©i by Ξ±i, where Ξ±βˆˆπ”½β„“, and choose the labeling in such a way that x acts on Ξ©i via the cycle (0i,1i,…,(β„“-1)i) and also

g:01↦02↦⋯↦0j↦b1 for someΒ bβˆˆπ”½β„“.

Thus x acts on Ξ©:=⋃i=1jΞ©i via

x=(01,11,…,(β„“-1)1)⁒(02,12,…,(β„“-1)2)⁒…⁒(0j,1j,…,(β„“-1)j).

Now on the one hand we have, on Ξ©,

g⁒x⁒g-1=(b1,g⁒(1j),…,g⁒((β„“-1)j))⁒(02,g⁒(11),…,g⁒((β„“-1)1))…⁒(0j,g⁒(1j-1),…,g⁒((β„“-1)j-1))

and on the other we have

xa=(b1,(b+a)1,(b+2⁒a)1,…,(b+(β„“-1)⁒a)1)⁒(02,a2,…,(β„“-1)⁒a2)…⁒(0j,aj,…,(β„“-1)⁒aj).

Thus we see that for any αi∈Ω,

g⁒(Ξ±i)={(a⁒α)i+1,if ⁒1≀i≀j-1,(b+a⁒α)1,if ⁒i=j.

Note that for any β∈Ω and any integer s, if gs⁒(Ξ²)=Ξ², then j∣s; also, the length of the γ€ˆg〉-orbit of Ξ² is the minimal s such that gs⁒(Ξ²)=Ξ². Thus, every γ€ˆg〉-orbit on Ξ© has length a multiple of j. Finally, observe that to prove the lemma it actually suffices to show that γ€ˆg〉 has an orbit on Ξ© with length a multiple of t (as then, for some power h of g, γ€ˆh〉 has an orbit of exact length t). This is what we now prove.

If aj=1, then t∣j (recall that a has order t in 𝔽ℓ×). By the previous paragraph any γ€ˆg〉-orbit on Ξ© has length a multiple of t, and so we are finished. Thus we may assume that ajβ‰ 1. For any Ξ±βˆˆπ”½β„“ we compute

gj⁒(α1)=(b+aj⁒α)1,

so for any integer i we have

gi⁒j⁒(Ξ±1)=(b⁒(1+aj+…+aj⁒(i-1))+ai⁒j⁒α)1.

Set c=ajβ‰ 1 and choose Ξ±1∈Ω1 with Ξ±β‰ b1-c. Choose i minimal with gi⁒j⁒(Ξ±1)=Ξ±1. The displayed equation implies that

α⁒(1-ci)=b⁒(1-ci)1-c

and thus

(1-ci)⁒(α-b1-c)=0.

Since Ξ±β‰ b1-c, we have ai⁒j=ci=1 and thus t∣ij. Since i was chosen minimally, ij is the γ€ˆg〉-orbit length of Ξ±1 and so again by the previous paragraph we are finished. ∎

Theorem 3.

Let p=2. Let N=S1×…×Sr≃Sr, where S=PSL2⁑(32⁒n+1) for some nβ‰₯1. Assume that N is a minimal normal subgroup of G, CG⁒(N)=1, and N∘ is F-free in G. Let x∈G∘ be an F-element with odd prime order β„“ and assume that |Qβ„“:F∩Qβ„“|=t. Then there is some g∈G such that γ€ˆg〉 has an orbit of length t on the factors {S1,…,Sr}.

Proof.

By the minimality of N, any g∈G permutes the factors {S1,…,Sr} so the claim makes sense. Let x↦xi have order t in Aut⁑(γ€ˆx〉), so that x↦xi is a generator of Aut𝔽⁑(γ€ˆx〉). Since N∘ is 𝔽-free in G, x¯∈GΒ―:=G/N has order β„“ and of course it is still an 𝔽-element. Let g∈G satisfy xg=xi, so also xΒ―gΒ―=xΒ―i.

Since CG⁒(N)=1, we may view

G¯≀Out⁑(N)≃Out⁑(S)≀Sym⁑(r).

Write gΒ―=h⁒π, where h∈Out(S)r and Ο€βˆˆSym⁑(r). Suppose first that x fixes every factor Sm, i.e. that x¯∈Out(S)r, and write xΒ―=(x1,…,xr), where each xi∈Out⁑(Si). Assume, without loss, that o⁒(x1)=β„“. As Out⁑(S) is abelian, we have

(x1i,…,xri)=xΒ―i=xΒ―g=xΒ―h⁒π=xΒ―Ο€=(xΟ€-1⁒(1),…,xΟ€-1⁒(r))

and, for any integer j,

(x1ij,…,xrij)=xΒ―Ο€j=(xΟ€-j⁒(1),…,xΟ€-j⁒(r)).

Since o⁒(x1)=β„“=o⁒(x), the map x1↦x1i has order t. Thus the x1ij are all distinct for 1≀j≀t and we conclude that the γ€ˆg〉-orbit of S1 has length at least t. But since xΒ―gt=xΒ―it=xΒ―, clearly this orbit has length at most t.

Thus we may assume that x moves some factor Sm. So the image of x under the composition of natural maps

Gβ†’G/Nβ†ͺOut⁑(S)≀Sym⁑(r)β†’Sym⁑(r)

is an 𝔽-element of order β„“. Let H denote the image of G under this map, so by Lemma 2 there is some h∈H such that γ€ˆh〉 has an orbit of length t on the factors {S1,…,Sr}; equivalently, for any preimage g∈G of h, γ€ˆg〉 has an orbit of length t on {S1,…,Sr}. This completes the proof. ∎

This next statement is the last major ingredient that we need.

Theorem 4.

Fix a prime β„“. Let N=S1×…×Sr≃Sr, where S=PSL2⁑(32⁒n+1) for some nβ‰₯1. Further, assume that N is a minimal normal subgroup of G with CG⁒(N)=1. Assume that some g∈G permutes the factors {S1,…,Sr} with an orbit of length t, where t=|Qβ„“:F∩Qβ„“|. If β„“ divides |N|, then there is some F-element of G with order β„“ contained in N.

Before giving the proof we establish some notation and conventions. In the situation of Theorem 4, assume that g:S1↦S2↦⋯↦St↦S1. Let ig denote the conjugation-by-g map. Then all of the groups Si may be identified via appropriate powers of ig, e.g. ig⁒(S1)=S2, etc. We extend this to obtain identifications between all of the groups Aut⁑(Si). In order to simplify the notation, we will use these identifications to make sense of products of elements in Aut⁑(Si) and Aut⁑(Sj), and view these products in Aut⁑(Sk), even when none of i,j,k are necessarily equal.

For example, if h1∈Aut⁑(S1) and h2∈Aut⁑(S2), we will make sense of h1⁒h2 as an element of any or all of Aut⁑(S1),Aut⁑(S2), or Aut⁑(S3). Here it is to be understood that by h1⁒h2 we really mean h1⁒(ig-1∘h2) in the first case, (ig∘h1)⁒h2 in the second, or (ig2∘h1)⁒(ig∘h2) in the third. The intended meaning of a product like h1⁒h2 will always be clear from context.

Finally, a bit of notation: if hi∈Aut⁑(Si) for i=1,…,r and if a≀b are integers, we define

ha:b:=∏i=abhi.

Proof of Theorem 4.

We have

N≀G≀Aut⁑(N)≃Aut⁑(S)≀Sym⁑(r).

Write g=h⁒π, where h∈Aut(S)r and Ο€βˆˆSym⁑(r). Reordering the factors, if necessary, we may assume that

g:S1↦S2↦⋯↦St↦S1.

We will show that there is an element v in S1×…×St with order β„“ and such that γ€ˆg〉 induces on γ€ˆv〉 a group of automorphisms containing Aut𝔽⁑(γ€ˆv〉). Thus, there is no loss to assume that r=t. Since Aut⁑(S) is split over S, by [4], we may choose a complement O≀Aut(S)t for N and identify O with Out(S)t. Therefore, by replacing g by ng for some appropriate n∈N, we may assume that h∈O and that h acts on N via (h1,…,ht)∈Out(S)t. Clearly this new choice of g still has an orbit of length t on the factors Si. Recall that Out⁑(S) is abelian.

The cases β„“=2 and β„“=3 are handled differently from the case β„“>3, so we divide the proof into three steps.

Step (1). Assume that β„“=2. Any involution in N is rational, hence an 𝔽-element, and we are done.

Step (2). Assume that β„“=3. Then either β„š3βˆ©π”½=β„š3, every element of order 3 in N is an 𝔽-element, and we are finished; or else β„š3βˆ©π”½=β„š and t=2. Let u∈S be any element of order 3. Recall that uSβ‰ (u-1)S and any h∈Aut⁑(S) either fixes both uS and (u-1)S or else h exchanges these classes. Now g2 fixes both factors S1 and S2 and acts on both via h1⁒h2.

If h1⁒h2 sends uS to (u-1)S, then choosing v=(u,1) we have

(vg2)N=(uh1⁒h2,1)N=(u-1,1)N=(v-1)N

and so v is rational in G. If instead h1⁒h2 fixes both uS and (u-1)S, then either h1 and h2 each fix both classes or else h1 and h2 each send uS to (u-1)S. In the first case we choose v=(u,u-1) and in the second we choose v=(u,u). In either case, (vg)N=(v-1)N. Again, v is rational. This completes the case β„“=3.

Step (3). Finally, assume that β„“>3. Then β„“ divides qΒ±1, where q=32⁒n+1.

We begin by making an explicit choice for O. Recall that Out⁑(S) is generated by field and diagonal automorphisms. We choose Ξ΄ to be the diagonal automorphism of S induced from conjugation by (100-1). When β„“βˆ£q-1, we choose Ο• to be the field automorphism induced from x↦x3 on 𝔽q; when β„“βˆ£q+1, we view S as PSU2⁑(q) and choose Ο• to be the field automorphism induced from x↦x9 on 𝔽q2. We choose

O=(γ€ˆΞ΄γ€‰Γ—γ€ˆΟ•γ€‰)t.

If β„“βˆ£q-1, then view S=PSL2⁑(q) and if β„“βˆ£q+1, view S=PSU2⁑(q). Consider the diagonal torus T of S, which has order q-1 or q+1, according as S=PSL2⁑(q) or PSU2⁑(q). Now choose u∈T to have order β„“. It is clear that u is fixed by Ξ΄ and γ€ˆu〉 is γ€ˆΟ•γ€‰-stable. By our choice of u and assumptions about g, γ€ˆg〉 acts on

U=γ€ˆuγ€‰Γ—β€¦Γ—γ€ˆuγ€‰βŸt⁒ times≀N.

Now gt acts on N via (k,…,k), where k=h1:t – in particular, gt fixes every factor Si. Let u↦ua be the automorphism of γ€ˆu〉 induced by k and let s denote the order of this automorphism. Let d=gcd⁑(s,t) and f=t/d. Since Aut⁑(γ€ˆu〉)≃Cβ„“-1, t and s both divide β„“-1 and so fs∣(β„“-1) as well. Thus we may choose an fth root of u↦ua, say u↦ui, so that k:u↦uif.

We choose an element v=(v1,v2,…,vt)∈U as follows: v1=u=:uf and for 1≀j≀(f-1), we recursively define vj⁒d+1=:uj, where

uj=(uj+1i)h(j⁒d+1):(j+1)⁒d-1.

All other components of v we define to be 1.

We claim that vgd=vi. Note that the map u↦ui has order s⁒f=(s/d)⁒t in Aut⁑(γ€ˆu〉), and thus v↦vi also has order (s/d)⁒t. Since o⁒(v)=β„“, we have Aut𝔽(γ€ˆv〉)β‰€γ€ˆv↦vi〉 and so, given the claim, it follows that v is an 𝔽-element in G. To prove the claim, observe that the component of vgd in position m is given by vm-dh(m-d):(m-1). So from the construction of v it is obvious that vgd=vi, except possibly in the (d+1)st component. In other words, to prove the claim we need only check that

vd+1i=v1h1:d,or equivalently u1i=uh1:d.

By repeated back-substitution using the definition of the uj, we have

u1i=(uif)h(d+1):t-1=(uk)h(d+1):t-1=uh1:d,

as needed. This completes the proof. ∎

We need one more lemma, which is an easy consequence of the well-known Schur–Zassenhaus theorem.

Lemma 5.

Let N◁G and let x,y∈G. Further, suppose that o⁒(x)=o⁒(y), that (|N|,o⁒(x))=1, and that N⁒x=N⁒y∈G/N. Then x and y are N-conjugate.

Proof.

By the Schur–Zassenhaus theorem there is some n∈N with γ€ˆx〉n=γ€ˆy〉. Thus y=(xk)n for some integer k coprime to o⁒(x). We have

N⁒x=N⁒y=N⁒(xk)n=N⁒xk

and thus xk-1∈N. Since o⁒(x) is coprime to |N|, though, we have γ€ˆxγ€‰βˆ©N=1 and thus xk=x. We conclude that xn=y, which completes the proof. ∎

Finally, we complete the proof of Theorem A.

Theorem 6.

Let N◁G and assume that N∘ is F-free in G. Then the canonical homomorphism Gβ†’G/N induces an injection ClF∘⁑(G)β†’ClF∘⁑(G/N).

Proof.

Assume that the theorem is false, let G be a minimal counterexample, and let N be minimal among normal subgroups of G which give rise to a counterexample. This means there are p-regular 𝔽-elements x,y∈G such that xGβ‰ yG but N⁒x=N⁒y. Arguing as in [3, Theorem 5.1], we may assume that N is minimal normal in G.

If N is non-solvable, then, by the remarks following Lemma 2, we have p=2 and N=S1×…×Sr≃Sr, where S=PSL2⁑(32⁒n+1). Let C=CG⁒(N), let Ο€ denote the set of prime divisors of |N|, and write x=xπ⁒xΟ€β€² and y=yπ⁒yΟ€β€².

We claim that xΟ€βˆˆC. Assume that this is not the case. We set GΒ―=G/C and NΒ―=N⁒C/C≃N. Now our assumption is that xΒ―Ο€ is non-trivial and, since powers of 𝔽-elements are 𝔽-elements, there is some β„“βˆˆΟ€ and some power of xΒ―Ο€ that is an 𝔽-element of order β„“. We have that N¯∘ is 𝔽-free in GΒ―, by Lemma 5, and thus by Theorem 3 there is some g¯∈GΒ― permuting the factors Si of NΒ― with an orbit of length t=|β„šβ„“:β„šβ„“βˆ©π”½|. Theorem 4 now guarantees the existence of an 𝔽-element of GΒ― contained in NΒ― and of order β„“. This is a contradiction and we conclude that xΟ€βˆˆC, as claimed. Thus, by Lemma 1, xΟ€=yΟ€.

Note that (N⁒x)Ο€β€²=N⁒xΟ€β€² and similarly (N⁒y)Ο€β€²=N⁒yΟ€β€². By Lemma 3 we have

γ€ˆxΟ€β€²γ€‰βˆ©N=1=γ€ˆyΟ€β€²γ€‰βˆ©N

and thus

o⁒(xΟ€β€²)=o⁒(N⁒xΟ€β€²)=o⁒(N⁒yΟ€β€²)=o⁒(yΟ€β€²).

By Lemma 5, xΟ€β€²n=yΟ€β€² for some n∈N. Since xΟ€=yΟ€βˆˆC, it follows that xn=y, which we assumed is not the case.

The contradiction in the previous paragraph shows that N must be solvable. So N is an elementary abelian β„“-group for some prime β„“. In this case, too, we conclude that xG=yG – if β„“=p, then, since x and y are p-regular, we may apply Lemma 5 as above; and if β„“β‰ p, then N∘=N is 𝔽-free in G, so we may apply the Isaacs–Navarro Theorem 1. ∎


Communicated by Robert M. Guralnick


Award Identifier / Grant number: DMS-1201374

Funding statement: Partially supported by NSF Grant DMS-1201374.

Acknowledgements

This article is based on some of the results of the author’s PhD thesis at the University of Arizona, under the supervision of Pham Huu Tiep. I gratefully acknowledge Professor Tiep’s support and thank him for several helpful conversations.

References

[1] L. Dornhoff, Group Representation Theory. Part A: Ordinary Representation Theory, Pure Appl. Math. 7, Marcel Dekker, New York, 1971. Search in Google Scholar

[2] I. M. Isaacs, Finite Group Theory, Grad. Stud. Math. 92, American Mathematical Society, Providence, 2008. Search in Google Scholar

[3] I. M. Isaacs and G. Navarro, Group elements and fields of character values, J. Group Theory 12 (2009), no. 5, 635–650. 10.1515/JGT.2009.001Search in Google Scholar

[4] A. Lucchini, F. Menegazzo and M. Morigi, On the existence of a complement for a finite simple group in its automorphism group, Illinois J. Math. 47 (2003), no. 1–2, 395–418. 10.1215/ijm/1258488162Search in Google Scholar

[5] G. Navarro, Characters and Blocks of Finite Groups, London Math. Soc. Lecture Note Ser. 250, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1998. 10.1017/CBO9780511526015Search in Google Scholar

[6] G. Navarro and P. H. Tiep, Rational irreducible characters and rational conjugacy classes in finite groups, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 360 (2008), no. 5, 2443–2465. 10.1090/S0002-9947-07-04375-9Search in Google Scholar

[7] G. Navarro and P. H. Tiep, Brauer characters and rationality, Math. Z. 276 (2014), no. 3–4, 1101–1112. 10.1007/s00209-013-1234-xSearch in Google Scholar

Received: 2017-5-26
Revised: 2017-5-31
Published Online: 2017-7-18
Published in Print: 2017-11-1

Β© 2017 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston

Downloaded on 20.4.2024 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/jgth-2017-0023/html
Scroll to top button