Skip to main content

Enriching some recent coincidence theorems for nonlinear contractions in ordered metric spaces

Abstract

In this article, we generalize some frequently used metrical notions such as: completeness, continuity, g-continuity, and compatibility to order-theoretic setting especially in ordered metric spaces besides introducing some new notions such as: the ICC property, DCC property, MCC property etc. and utilize these relatively weaker notions to prove some coincidence theorems for g-increasing Boyd-Wong type contractions which enrich some recent results due to Alam et al. (Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2014:216, 2014).

1 Introduction

In recent years, a multitude of order-theoretic metrical fixed point theorems have been proved for order-preserving contractions. This trend was essentially initiated by Turinici [1, 2]. After over two decades, Ran and Reurings [3] proved a slightly more natural version of the corresponding fixed point theorems of Turinici (cf. [1, 2]) for continuous monotone mappings with some applications to matrix equations. In the same lieu, Nieto and Rodríguez-López [4] proved some variants of the Ran and Reuring fixed point theorem for increasing mappings, which were generalized by many authors (e.g. [5–16]) in recent years. Most recently, Alam et al. [16] extended the foregoing results for generalized φ-contractions due to Boyd and Wong [17].

The aim of this paper is to present some existence and uniqueness results on coincidence points involving a pair of self-mappings f and g defined on ordered metric space X such that f is g-increasing Boyd-Wong type nonlinear contraction (cf. [17]) employing our newly introduced notions such as: O-completeness, O-continuity, \((g,\mathrm{O})\)-continuity, O-compatibility, MCC property, ≺≻-chain etc.

2 Preliminaries

In this section, to make our exposition self-contained, we recall some basic definitions, relevant notions and auxiliary results. Throughout this paper, \(\mathbb{N}\) stands for the set of natural numbers and \(\mathbb{N}_{0}\) for the set of whole numbers (i.e. \(\mathbb {N}_{0}=\mathbb{N}\cup\{0\}\)).

Definition 1

[18]

A set X together with a partial order ⪯ (often denoted by \((X,\preceq)\)) is called an ordered set. As expected, ⪰ denotes the dual order of ⪯ (i.e. \(x\succeq y\) means \(y\preceq x\)).

Definition 2

[18]

Two elements x and y of an ordered set \((X,\preceq)\) are called comparable if either \(x\preceq y\) or \(x\succeq y\). For brevity, we denote it by \(x\prec\succ y\).

Clearly, the relation ≺≻ is reflexive and symmetric, but not transitive in general (cf. [19]).

Definition 3

[18]

A subset E of an ordered set \((X,\preceq)\) is called totally or linearly ordered if every pair of elements of E are comparable, i.e.,

$$x\prec\succ y \quad \forall x,y\in E. $$

Definition 4

[1]

A sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\) in an ordered set \((X,\preceq)\) is said to be

  1. (i)

    increasing or ascending if for any \(m,n\in \mathbb{N}_{0}\),

    $$m\leq n\quad\Rightarrow\quad x_{m}\preceq x_{n}, $$
  2. (ii)

    decreasing or descending if for any \(m,n\in\mathbb{N}_{0}\),

    $$m\leq n\quad\Rightarrow\quad x_{m}\succeq x_{n}, $$
  3. (iii)

    monotone if it is either increasing or decreasing,

  4. (iv)

    bounded above if there is an element \(u\in X\) such that

    $$x_{n}\preceq u \quad \forall n\in\mathbb{N}_{0} $$

    so that u is an upper bound of \(\{x_{n}\}\) and

  5. (v)

    bounded below if there is an element \(l\in X\) such that

    $$x_{n}\succeq l \quad \forall n\in\mathbb{N}_{0} $$

    so that l is a lower bound of \(\{x_{n}\}\).

Definition 5

[7]

Let f and g be two self-mappings defined on an ordered set \((X,\preceq)\). We say that f is g-increasing (resp. g-decreasing) if for any \(x,y\in X\), \(g(x)\preceq g(y)\Rightarrow f(x)\preceq f(y)\) (resp. \(f(x)\succeq f(y)\)). In all, f is called g-monotone if f is either g-increasing or g-decreasing.

Notice that under the restriction \(g=I\), the identity mapping on X, the notions of g-increasing, g-decreasing and g-monotone mappings reduce to increasing, decreasing and monotone mappings, respectively.

Definition 6

[20, 21]

Let f and g be two self-mappings on a nonempty set X. Then

  1. (i)

    an element \(x\in X\) is called a coincidence point of f and g if

    $$g(x)=f(x), $$
  2. (ii)

    an element \(\overline{x}\in X\) with \(\overline {x}=g(x)=f(x)\), for some \(x\in X\), is called a point of coincidence of f and g,

  3. (iii)

    an element \(x\in X\) is called a common fixed point of f and g if \(x=g(x)=f(x)\),

  4. (iv)

    the pair \((f,g)\) is said to be commuting if for all \(x\in X\),

    $$g(fx)=f(gx) \quad\mbox{and} $$
  5. (v)

    the pair \((f,g)\) is said to be weakly compatible (or partially commuting or coincidentally commuting) if the pair \((f,g)\) commutes at their coincidence points, i.e., for any \(x\in X\),

    $$g(x)=f(x)\quad\Rightarrow\quad g(fx)=f(gx). $$

Definition 7

[22, 23]

Let f and g be two self-mappings on a metric space \((X,d)\). Then

  1. (i)

    the pair \((f,g)\) is said to be weakly commuting if for all \(x\in X\),

    $$d(gfx,fgx)\leq d(gx,fx) \quad\mbox{and} $$
  2. (ii)

    the pair \((f,g)\) is said to be compatible if for any sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subset X\) and for any \(z\in X\),

    $$\lim_{n\to\infty}g(x_{n})=\lim_{n\to\infty }f(x_{n})=z \quad\Rightarrow\quad\lim_{n\to\infty}d(gfx_{n},fgx_{n})=0. $$

Definition 8

[24]

Let f and g be two self-mappings on a metric space \((X,d)\) and \(x\in X\). We say that f is g-continuous at x if for any sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subset X\),

$$g(x_{n})\stackrel{d}{\longrightarrow} g(x)\quad\Rightarrow\quad f(x_{n})\stackrel {d}{\longrightarrow} f(x). $$

Moreover, f is called g-continuous if it is g-continuous at each point of X.

Notice that particularly with \(g=I\), the identity mapping on X, Definition 8 reduces to the definition of continuity.

Definition 9

[6]

A triplet \((X,d,\preceq)\) is called an ordered metric space if \((X,d)\) is a metric space and \((X,\preceq)\) is an ordered set.

Let \((X,d,\preceq)\) be an ordered metric space and \(\{x_{n}\}\) a sequence in X. We adopt the following notations.

  1. (i)

    If \(\{x_{n}\}\) is increasing and \(x_{n}\stackrel {d}{\longrightarrow} x\), then we denote it symbolically by \(x_{n}\uparrow x\).

  2. (ii)

    If \(\{x_{n}\}\) is decreasing and \(x_{n}\stackrel {d}{\longrightarrow} x\), then we denote it symbolically by \(x_{n}\downarrow x\).

  3. (iii)

    If \(\{x_{n}\}\) is monotone and \(x_{n}\stackrel {d}{\longrightarrow} x\), then we denote it symbolically by \(x_{n}\uparrow\downarrow x\).

In order to avoid the continuity requirement of underlying mapping, the following notions are formulated using suitable properties of ordered metric spaces utilized by earlier authors especially those contained in [4, 7, 25, 26] besides some other ones.

Definition 10

[16]

Let \((X,d,\preceq)\) be an ordered metric space and g a self-mapping on X. We say that

  1. (i)

    \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the g-ICU (increasing-convergence-upper bound) property if g-image of every increasing convergent sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\) in X is bounded above by g-image of its limit (as an upper bound), i.e.,

    $$x_{n}\uparrow x \quad\Rightarrow \quad g(x_{n})\preceq g(x) \quad \forall n\in\mathbb{N}_{0} , $$
  2. (ii)

    \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the g-DCL (decreasing-convergence-lower bound) property if g-image of every decreasing convergent sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\) in X is bounded below by g-image of its limit (as a lower bound), i.e.,

    $$x_{n}\downarrow x \quad\Rightarrow \quad g(x_{n})\succeq g(x) \quad\forall n\in\mathbb {N}_{0} \quad\mbox{and} $$
  3. (iii)

    \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the g-MCB (monotone-convergence-boundedness) property if it has both the g-ICU and the g-DCL properties.

Notice that under the restriction \(g=I\), the identity mapping on X, the notions of g-ICU property, g-DCL property, and g-MCB property reduce to ICU property, DCL property, and MCB property, respectively.

Inspired by Jleli et al. [12], Alam and Imdad [27] defined the following.

Definition 11

[27]

Let \((X,\preceq)\) be an ordered set and f and g two self-mappings on X. We say that \((X,\preceq)\) is \((f,g)\)-directed if for every pair \(x,y\in X\), \(\exists z\in X\) such that \(f(x)\prec\succ g(z)\) and \(f(y)\prec\succ g(z)\).

In the cases \(g=I\) and \(f=g=I\) (where I denotes the identity mapping on X), \((X,\preceq)\) is called f-directed and directed, respectively.

Inspired by Turinici [19], Alam and Imdad [27] defined the following.

Definition 12

[27]

Let \((X,\preceq)\) be an ordered set, \(E\subseteq X\) and \(a,b\in E\). A finite subset \(\{e_{1},e_{2},\ldots,e_{k}\}\) of E is called a ≺≻-chain between a and b in E if

  1. (i)

    \(k\geq2\),

  2. (ii)

    \(e_{1}=a\) and \(e_{k}=b\),

  3. (iii)

    \(e_{i}\prec\succ e_{i+1}\) for each i (\(1\leq i\leq k-1\)).

We denote by \(\mathrm{C}(a,b,\prec\succ,E)\) the class of all ≺≻-chains between a and b in E. In particular for \(E=X\), we write \(\mathrm{C}(x,y,\prec\succ)\) instead of \(\mathrm{C}(x,y,\prec\succ,X)\).

Definition 13

[17, 28]

We denote by Ω the family of functions \(\varphi: [0,\infty)\to[0,\infty)\) satisfying

  1. (a)

    \(\varphi(t)< t\) for each \(t>0\),

  2. (b)

    \(\limsup_{r\to t^{+}}\varphi(r)< t\) for each \(t>0\).

We need the following well-known results in the proof of our main results.

Lemma 1

[16]

Let f and g be two self-mappings defined on an ordered set \((X,\preceq)\). If f is g-monotone and \(g(x)=g(y)\), then \(f(x)=f(y)\).

Lemma 2

[16]

Let \(\varphi\in\Omega\). If \(\{a_{n}\}\subset(0,\infty)\) is a sequence such that \(a_{n+1}\leq \varphi(a_{n})\) \(\forall n\in\mathbb{N}_{0}\), then \(\lim_{n\to\infty}a_{n}=0\).

Lemma 3

[16]

Let f and g be two self-mappings defined on a nonempty set X. If the pair \((f,g)\) is weakly compatible, then every point of coincidence of f and g is also a coincidence point of f and g.

3 Order-theoretic metrical notions

Firstly, we adopt several well-known metrical notions to order-theoretic metric setting.

Definition 14

An ordered metric space \((X,d,\preceq)\) is called

  1. (i)

    \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-complete if every increasing Cauchy sequence in X converges,

  2. (ii)

    \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-complete if every decreasing Cauchy sequence in X converges, and

  3. (iii)

    O-complete if every monotone Cauchy sequence in X converges.

Here it can be pointed out that the notion of \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-completeness was already defined by Turinici [29] stating that d is \((\preceq)\)-complete.

Remark 1

In an ordered metric space, completeness ⇒ O-completeness ⇒ \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-completeness as well as \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-completeness.

Definition 15

Let \((X,d,\preceq)\) be an ordered metric space, \(f:X\rightarrow X\) a mapping and \(x\in X\). Then f is called:

  1. (i)

    \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous at \(x\in X\) if for any sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subset X\),

    $$x_{n}\uparrow x\quad \Rightarrow\quad f(x_{n})\stackrel{d}{\longrightarrow} f(x), $$
  2. (ii)

    \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous at \(x\in X\) if for any sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subset X\),

    $$x_{n}\downarrow x\quad\Rightarrow\quad f(x_{n}) \stackrel{d}{\longrightarrow} f(x) \quad\mbox{and} $$
  3. (iii)

    O-continuous at \(x\in X\) if for any sequence \(\{x_{n}\} \subset X\),

    $$x_{n} \uparrow\downarrow x\quad\Rightarrow\quad f(x_{n}) \stackrel{d}{\longrightarrow} f(x). $$

Moreover, f is called O-continuous (resp. \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous, \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous) if it is O-continuous (resp. \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous, \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous) at each point of X.

Here it can be pointed out that the notion of \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuity was earlier defined by Turinici [29] wherein he said that f is \((d,\preceq)\)-continuous.

Remark 2

In an ordered metric space, continuity ⇒ O-continuity ⇒ \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuity as well as \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuity.

Definition 16

Let \((X,d,\preceq)\) be an ordered metric space, f and g two self-mappings on X and \(x\in X\). Then f is called:

  1. (i)

    \((g,\overline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous at \(x\in X\) if for any sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subset X\),

    $$g(x_{n})\uparrow g(x)\quad \Rightarrow\quad f(x_{n}) \stackrel{d}{\longrightarrow} f(x), $$
  2. (ii)

    \((g,\underline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous at \(x\in X\) if for any sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subset X\),

    $$g(x_{n})\downarrow g(x)\quad\Rightarrow\quad f(x_{n}) \stackrel{d}{\longrightarrow} f(x) \quad\mbox{and} $$
  3. (iii)

    \((g,{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous at \(x\in X\) if for any sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subset X\),

    $$g(x_{n}) \uparrow\downarrow g(x)\quad\Rightarrow\quad f(x_{n})\stackrel {d}{\longrightarrow} f(x). $$

Moreover, f is called \((g,{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous (resp. \((g,\overline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous, \((g,\underline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous) if it is \((g,{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous (resp. \((g,\overline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous, \((g,\underline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous) at each point of X.

Notice that on setting \(g=I\) (the identity mapping on X), Definition 16 reduces to Definition 15.

Remark 3

In an ordered metric space, g-continuity ⇒ \((g,{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuity ⇒ \((g,\overline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuity as well as \((g,\underline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuity.

Definition 17

Let \((X,d,\preceq)\) be an ordered metric space and f and g two self-mappings on X. We say that the pair \((f,g)\) is

  1. (i)

    \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatible if for any sequence \(\{x_{n}\} \subset X\) and for any \(z\in X\),

    $$g(x_{n})\uparrow z \quad\mbox{and}\quad f(x_{n})\uparrow z \quad\Rightarrow\quad\lim_{n\to\infty}d(gfx_{n},fgx_{n})=0, $$
  2. (ii)

    \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatible if for any sequence \(\{ x_{n}\}\subset X\) and for any \(z\in X\),

    $$g(x_{n})\downarrow z \quad\mbox{and}\quad f(x_{n}) \downarrow z\quad\Rightarrow\quad\lim_{n\to\infty}d(gfx_{n},fgx_{n})=0 \quad\mbox{and} $$
  3. (iii)

    O-compatible if for any sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subset X\) and for any \(z\in X\),

    $$g(x_{n})\uparrow\downarrow z \quad\mbox{and}\quad f(x_{n}) \uparrow\downarrow z\quad\Rightarrow\quad\lim_{n\to\infty}d(gfx_{n},fgx_{n})=0. $$

Here it can be pointed out that the notion of O-compatibility is slightly weaker than the notion of O-compatibility defined by Luong and Thuan [30]. Luong and Thuan [30] assumed that only the sequence \(\{gx_{n}\}\) is monotone but we assume that both \(\{gx_{n}\}\) and \(\{fx_{n}\}\) are monotone.

Remark 4

In an ordered metric space, commutativity ⇒ weak commutativity ⇒ compatibility ⇒ O-compatibility ⇒ \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatibility as well as \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatibility ⇒ weak compatibility.

Now, we define the following notions, which are weaker than those of Definition 10.

Definition 18

Let \((X,d,\preceq)\) be an ordered metric space. We say that:

  1. (i)

    \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the ICC (increasing-convergence-comparable) property if every increasing convergent sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\) in X has a subsequence \(\{x_{n_{k}}\}\) such that every term of \(\{x_{n_{k}}\}\) is comparable with the limit of \(\{x_{n}\}\), i.e.,

    $$x_{n}\uparrow x \quad\Rightarrow\quad\exists \mbox{ a subsequence } \{x_{n_{k}}\}\mbox{ of } \{x_{n}\} \mbox{ with } x_{n_{k}}\prec\succ x \ \forall k\in\mathbb{N}_{0}, $$
  2. (ii)

    \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the DCC (decreasing-convergence-comparable) property if every decreasing convergent sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\) in X has a subsequence \(\{x_{n_{k}}\}\) such that every term of \(\{x_{n_{k}}\}\) is comparable with the limit of \(\{x_{n}\}\), i.e.,

    $$x_{n}\downarrow x \quad\Rightarrow\quad\exists\mbox{ a subsequence } \{x_{n_{k}}\}\mbox{ of } \{x_{n}\} \mbox{ with } x_{n_{k}}\prec\succ x \ \forall k\in\mathbb{N}_{0} \quad\mbox{and} $$
  3. (iii)

    \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the MCC (monotone-convergence-comparable) property if every monotone convergent sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\) in X has a subsequence \(\{x_{n_{k}}\}\) such that every term of \(\{x_{n_{k}}\}\) is comparable with the limit of \(\{x_{n}\}\), i.e.,

    $$x_{n}\uparrow\downarrow x \quad\Rightarrow\quad\exists\mbox{ a subsequence } \{x_{n_{k}}\}\mbox{ of } \{x_{n}\} \mbox{ with } x_{n_{k}}\prec\succ x \ \forall k\in\mathbb{N}_{0}. $$

Remark 5

For an ordered metric space:

  • ICU property ⇒ ICC property.

  • DCL property ⇒ DCC property.

  • MCB property ⇒ MCC property ⇒ ICC property as well as DCC property.

Definition 19

Let \((X,d,\preceq)\) be an ordered metric space and g a self-mapping on X. We say that:

  1. (i)

    \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the g-ICC property if every increasing convergent sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\) in X has a subsequence \(\{x_{n_{k}}\}\) such that every term of \(\{gx_{n_{k}}\}\) is comparable with g-image of the limit of \(\{x_{n}\}\), i.e.,

    $$x_{n}\uparrow x\quad \Rightarrow\quad\exists \mbox{ a subsequence } \{x_{n_{k}}\} \mbox{ of } \{x_{n}\} \mbox{ with } g(x_{n_{k}})\prec\succ g(x) \ \forall k\in\mathbb{N}_{0}, $$
  2. (ii)

    \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the g-DCC property if each decreasing convergent sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\) in X has a subsequence \(\{x_{n_{k}}\}\) such that every term of \(\{gx_{n_{k}}\}\) is comparable with g-image of the limit of \(\{x_{n}\}\), i.e.,

    $$x_{n}\downarrow x \quad\Rightarrow\quad \exists\mbox{ a subsequence } \{x_{n_{k}}\} \mbox{ of } \{x_{n}\} \mbox{ with } g(x_{n_{k}})\prec\succ g(x)\ \forall k\in \mathbb{N}_{0} \quad\mbox{and} $$
  3. (iii)

    \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the g-MCC property if each monotone convergent sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\) in X has a subsequence \(\{x_{n_{k}}\}\) such that every term of \(\{gx_{n_{k}}\}\) is comparable with g-image of the limit of \(\{x_{n}\}\), i.e.,

    $$x_{n}\uparrow\downarrow x \quad\Rightarrow \quad\exists\mbox{ a subsequence } \{x_{n_{k}}\}\mbox{ of } \{x_{n}\} \mbox{ with } g(x_{n_{k}})\prec\succ g(x) \ \forall k\in\mathbb{N}_{0}. $$

Notice that on setting \(g=I\) (the identity mapping on X), Definition 19 reduces to Definition 18.

Remark 6

For an ordered metric space:

  • g-ICU property ⇒ g-ICC property.

  • g-DCL property ⇒ g-DCC property.

  • g-MCB property ⇒ g-MCC property ⇒ g-ICC property as well as g-DCC property.

4 Main results

Firstly, we prove some results which ensure the existence of coincidence points.

Theorem 1

Let \((X,d,\preceq)\) be an ordered metric space and f and g two self-mappings on X. Suppose that the following conditions hold:

(a):

\(f(X)\subseteq g(X)\),

(b):

f is g-increasing,

(c):

there exists \(x_{0}\in X\) such that \(g(x_{0})\preceq f(x_{0})\),

(d):

there exists \(\varphi\in\Omega\) such that

$$d(fx,fy)\leq\varphi\bigl(d(gx,gy)\bigr)\quad \forall x,y\in X\textit{ with }g(x)\prec\succ g(y), $$
(e):
(e1):

\((X,d,\preceq)\) is \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-complete,

(e2):

\((f,g)\) is \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatible pair,

(e3):

g is \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous,

(e4):

either f is \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous or \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the g-ICC property,

or alternately

(e′):
(e′1):

there exists a subset Y of X such that \(f(X)\subseteq Y \subseteq g(X)\) and \((Y,d,\preceq)\) is \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-complete,

(e′2):

either f is \((g,{\overline{\mathrm{O}}})\)-continuous or f and g are continuous or \((Y,d,\preceq)\) has the ICC property.

Then f and g have a coincidence point.

Proof

The proof of this theorem runs along the lines of the proof of Theorem 1 proved in [16]. We define a sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subset X\) (of joint iterates) such that

$$ g(x_{n+1})=f(x_{n}) \quad\forall n \in\mathbb{N}_{0}. $$
(1)

Following the lines of the proof of Theorem 1 of [16], we can show that the sequence \(\{gx_{n}\}\) (and hence \(\{fx_{n}\}\) also) is increasing and Cauchy.

Assume that (e) holds. Then \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-completeness of X implies the existence of \(z\in X\) such that

$$ g(x_{n})\uparrow z \quad\mbox{and}\quad f(x_{n})\uparrow z. $$
(2)

Owing to (2), we use \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuity and \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatibility instead of continuity and O-compatibility. To prove that \(z\in X\) is a coincidence point of f and g, firstly we suppose that f is \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous, then proceeding along the lines of the proof of Theorem 1 of [16], we show that \(f(z)=g(z)\). Otherwise suppose that \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the g-ICC property, then owing to (2), there exists a subsequence \(\{gx_{n_{k}}\}\) of \(\{gx_{n}\}\) such that

$$ g(gx_{n_{k}})\prec\succ g(z) \quad \forall k\in\mathbb{N}_{0}. $$
(3)

As \(g(x_{n_{k}})\uparrow z\), proceeding on the lines of the proof of Theorem 1 of [16] for the g-ICU property, we get \(g(z)=f(z)\).

Next, assume that (e′) holds. Then the assumption \(f(X)\subseteq Y\) and \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-completeness of Y implies the existence of \(y\in Y\) such that \(f(x_{n})\uparrow y\). Again owing to assumption \(Y\subseteq g(X)\), we can find \(u\in X\) such that \(y=g(u)\). Hence, on using (1), we get

$$ g(x_{n})\uparrow g(u). $$
(4)

To prove that \(u\in X\) is a coincidence point of f and g, firstly we suppose that f is \((g,\overline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous, then \(g(x_{n+1})=f(x_{n})\stackrel{d}{\longrightarrow} f(u)\). Using uniqueness of the limit, \(g(u)=f(u)\), and hence we are through. Next, suppose that f and g are continuous, then our proof runs on the lines of Theorem 1 of [16]. Finally, suppose that \((Y,d,\preceq)\) has the ICC property, then due to (4), there exists a subsequence \(\{gx_{n_{k}}\}\) of \(\{gx_{n}\}\) such that

$$ g(x_{n_{k}})\prec\succ g(u) \quad\forall k\in\mathbb{N}_{0}. $$
(5)

As \(g(x_{n_{k}})\uparrow g(u)\), proceeding on the lines of the proof of Theorem 1 of [16] for the ICU property, the desired result can also be proved. □

Theorem 2

Theorem  1 remains true if certain involved terms namely: \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-complete, \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatible pair, \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous, \((g,\overline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous, ICC property, and g-ICC property are, respectively, replaced by \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-complete, \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatible pair, \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous, \((g,\underline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous, DCC property, and g-DCC property provided the assumption (c) is replaced by the following (besides retaining the rest of the hypotheses):

(c)′:

there exists \(x_{0}\in X\) such that \(g(x_{0})\succeq f(x_{0})\).

Proof

The proof is similar to Theorem 2 of [16]. We define a sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subset X\) (of joint iterates) such that

$$ g(x_{n+1})=f(x_{n}) \quad\forall n \in\mathbb{N}_{0}. $$
(6)

Following the lines of the proof of Theorem 2 in [16], we show that the sequence \(\{gx_{n}\}\) (and hence also \(\{fx_{n}\}\)) is decreasing and Cauchy.

Assume that (e) holds. The \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-completeness of X implies the existence of \(z\in X\) such that

$$ g(x_{n})\downarrow z \quad\mbox{and}\quad f(x_{n}) \downarrow z. $$
(7)

In view of (7), we use \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuity and \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatibility instead of continuity and O-compatibility. To prove that \(z\in X\) is a coincidence point of f and g, firstly we suppose that f is \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous, then proceeding on the lines of the proof of Theorem 2 of [16], we show that \(f(z)=g(z)\). Otherwise suppose that \((X,d,\preceq)\) has the g-DCC property, then owing to (7), there exists a subsequence \(\{gx_{n_{k}}\}\) of \(\{gx_{n}\}\) such that

$$ g(gx_{n_{k}})\prec\succ g(z) \quad \forall k\in\mathbb{N}_{0}. $$
(8)

As \(g(x_{n_{k}})\downarrow z\), proceeding on the lines of the proof of Theorem 2 of [16] for the g-DCL property, we get \(g(z)=f(z)\).

On the other hand, assume that (e′) holds. Then due to availability of an analogous to (4), the \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-completeness of Y implies the existence of \(u\in X\) such that

$$ g(x_{n})\downarrow g(u). $$
(9)

To prove that \(u\in X\) is a coincidence point of f and g, firstly we suppose that f is \((g,\underline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous, then \(g(x_{n+1})=f(x_{n})\stackrel{d}{\longrightarrow} f(u)\). Using the uniqueness of the limit, \(g(u)=f(u)\), and hence we are done. Next, suppose that f and g are continuous, then a proof can be completed along the lines of the proof of Theorem 2 of [16]. Finally, suppose that \((Y,d,\preceq)\) has the DCC property, then, due to (9), there exists a subsequence \(\{gx_{n_{k}}\}\) of \(\{gx_{n}\}\) such that

$$ g(x_{n_{k}})\prec\succ g(u) \quad\forall k\in\mathbb{N}_{0}. $$
(10)

As \(g(x_{n_{k}})\downarrow g(u)\), proceeding on the lines of the proof of Theorem 2 of [16] for the DCL property, this result can be proved. □

Now, combining Theorems 1 and 2 and making use of Remarks 1-6, we obtain the following result.

Theorem 3

Theorem  1 remains true if certain involved terms namely: \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-complete, \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatible pair, \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-continuous, \((g,\overline{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous, ICC property, and g-ICC property are, respectively, replaced by O-complete, O-compatible pair, O-continuous, \((g,{\mathrm{O}})\)-continuous, MCC property, and g-MCC property provided the assumption (c) is replaced by the following (besides retaining the rest):

\((\mathrm{c})^{\prime\prime}\) :

there exists \(x_{0}\in X\) such that \(g(x_{0})\prec\succ f(x_{0})\).

Remark 7

In view of Remarks 1-6, it is clear that Theorems 1, 2 and 3 enrich, respectively, Theorems 1, 2, and 3 of Alam et al. [16].

Taking \(\varphi(t)=\alpha t\) with \(\alpha\in[0,1)\), in Theorem 1 (resp. in Theorem 2 or Theorem 3), we get the corresponding results for linear contractions as follows.

Corollary 1

Theorem  1 (resp. Theorem  2 or Theorem  3) remains true if we replace condition (d) by the following condition (besides retaining the rest of the hypotheses):

(d)′:

there exists \(\alpha\in[0,1)\) such that

$$d(fx,fy)\leq\alpha d(gx,gy)\quad \forall x,y\in X \textit{ with }g(x)\prec\succ g(y). $$

Now, we prove certain results ensuring the uniqueness of coincidence point, point of coincidence, and common fixed point corresponding to some earlier results. For a pair f and g of self-mappings on a nonempty set X, we adopt the following notations:

$$\begin{aligned}& \mathrm{C}(f,g)=\{x\in X:gx=fx\}, \quad \textit{i.e.},\mbox{ the set of all coincidence points of } f \mbox{ and }g, \\& \overline{\mathrm{C}}(f,g)=\{\overline{x}\in X: \mbox{there exists an }x\in X \mbox{ such that } \overline{x}=gx=fx\}, \\& \quad \textit{i.e.},\mbox{ the set of all points of coincidence of } f \mbox{ and }g. \end{aligned}$$

Theorem 4

In addition to the hypotheses (a)-(d) along with (e′) of Theorem  1 (resp. Theorem  2 or Theorem  3), suppose that the following condition (see Definition  12) holds:

(u0):

\(\mathrm{C}(fx,fy,\prec\succ,gX)\) is nonempty, for each \(x,y\in X\).

Then f and g have a unique point of coincidence.

Proof

In view of Theorem 1 (resp. Theorem 2 or Theorem 3), \(\overline{\mathrm{C}}(f,g)\neq\emptyset\). Take \(\overline{x},\overline{y}\in\overline{\mathrm{C}}(f,g)\), then \(\exists x,y\in X\) such that

$$ \overline{x}=g(x)=f(x) \quad\mbox{and} \quad \overline{y}=g(y)=f(y). $$
(11)

Now, we show that \(\overline{x}=\overline{y}\). As \(f(x),f(y)\in f(X)\subseteq g(X)\), by (u0), there exists a ≺≻-chain \(\{gz_{1},gz_{2},\ldots,gz_{k}\}\) between \(f(x)\) and \(f(y)\) in \(g(X)\), where \(z_{1},z_{2},\ldots,z_{k}\in X\). Owing to (11), without loss of generality, we can choose \(z_{1}=x\) and \(z_{k}=y\). We have

$$ g(z_{i})\prec\succ g(z_{i+1})\quad \mbox{for each } i\ (1\leq i\leq k-1). $$
(12)

Define the constant sequences \(z_{n}^{1}=z_{1}=x\) and \(z_{n}^{k}=z_{k}=y\), then using (11), we have \(g(z^{1}_{n+1})=f(z^{1}_{n})\) and \(g(z^{k}_{n+1})=f(z^{k}_{n})\) \(\forall n\in\mathbb{N}_{0}\). Put \(z_{0}^{2}=z_{2}, z_{0}^{3}=z_{3},\ldots, z_{0}^{k-1}=z_{k-1}\). Since \(f(X)\subseteq g(X)\), we can define sequences \(\{z_{n}^{2}\}, \{z_{n}^{3}\},\ldots, \{z_{n}^{k-1}\}\) in X such that \(g(z^{2}_{n+1})=f(z^{2}_{n}), g(z^{3}_{n+1})=f(z^{3}_{n}),\ldots, g(z^{k-1}_{n+1})=f(z^{k-1}_{n})\) \(\forall n\in\mathbb{N}_{0}\). Hence, we have

$$ g\bigl(z^{i}_{n+1}\bigr)=f\bigl(z^{i}_{n} \bigr) \quad\forall n\in\mathbb{N}_{0} \mbox{ and for each } i\ (1\leq i\leq k). $$
(13)

Now, we claim that

$$ g\bigl(z_{n}^{i}\bigr)\prec\succ g\bigl(z_{n}^{i+1} \bigr) \quad\forall n\in\mathbb{N}_{0} \mbox{ and for each } i\ (1\leq i\leq k-1). $$
(14)

We prove this fact by induction. It follows from (12) that (14) holds for \(n=0\). Suppose that (14) holds for \(n=r>0\), i.e.,

$$g\bigl(z_{r}^{i}\bigr)\prec\succ g\bigl(z_{r}^{i+1} \bigr) \quad\mbox{for each } i\ (1\leq i\leq k-1). $$

As f is g-increasing, we obtain

$$f\bigl(z_{r}^{i}\bigr)\prec\succ f\bigl(z_{r}^{i+1} \bigr) \quad\mbox{for each } i\ (1\leq i\leq k-1), $$

which on using (13), gives rise to

$$g\bigl(z_{r+1}^{i}\bigr)\prec\succ g\bigl(z_{r+1}^{i+1} \bigr) \quad\mbox{for each } i\ (1\leq i\leq k-1). $$

It follows that (14) holds for \(n=r+1\). Thus, by induction, (14) holds for all \(n \in\mathbb{N}_{0}\). Now, for each \(n \in \mathbb{N}_{0}\) and for each i (\(1\leq i\leq k-1\)), define \(t_{n}^{i}:=d(gz_{n}^{i},gz_{n}^{i+1})\). We claim that

$$ \lim_{n\to\infty}t_{n}^{i}=0 \quad\mbox{for each } i\ (1\leq i\leq k-1). $$
(15)

On fixing i, two cases arise. Firstly, suppose that \(t_{n_{0}}^{i}=d(gz_{n_{0}}^{i},gz_{n_{0}}^{i+1})=0\) for some \(n_{0}\in \mathbb{N}_{0}\), then by Lemma 1, we obtain \(d(fz_{n_{0}}^{i},fz_{n_{0}}^{i+1})=0\). Consequently on using (13), we get \(t_{n_{0}+1}^{i}=d(gz_{n_{0}+1}^{i},gz_{n_{0}+1}^{i+1})=d(fz_{n_{0}}^{i},fz_{n_{0}}^{i+1})=0\). Thus by induction, we get \(t_{n}^{i}=0\) \(\forall n\geq n_{0}\), yielding thereby \(\lim_{n\to\infty}t_{n}^{i}=0\). Secondly, suppose that \(t_{n}>0\) \(\forall n\in\mathbb{N}_{0}\), then on using (13), (14), and assumption (d), we have

$$\begin{aligned} t_{n+1}^{i} =& d\bigl(gz_{n+1}^{i},gz_{n+1}^{i+1} \bigr) \\ =& d\bigl(fz_{n}^{i},fz_{n}^{i+1} \bigr) \\ \leq& \varphi\bigl(d\bigl(gz_{n}^{i},z_{n}^{i+1} \bigr)\bigr) \\ =&\varphi\bigl(t_{n}^{i}\bigr), \end{aligned}$$

so that

$$t_{n+1}^{i}\leq\varphi\bigl(t_{n}^{i} \bigr). $$

Now, on applying Lemma 2, we obtain \(\lim_{n\to\infty}t_{n}^{i}=0\). Thus, in both cases, (15) is proved for each i (\(1\leq i\leq k-1\)). On using the triangular inequality and (15), we obtain

$$d(\overline{x},\overline{y})\leq t_{n}^{1}+t_{n}^{2}+ \cdots+t_{n}^{k-1} \to0 \quad\mbox{as } n\to\infty $$

so that

$$\overline{x}=\overline{y}. $$

 □

Theorem 5

In addition to the hypotheses of Theorem  4, suppose that the following condition holds:

(u1):

one of f and g is one-one.

Then f and g have a unique coincidence point.

Proof

In view of Theorem 1 (or Theorem 2 or Theorem 3), \(\mathrm{C}(f,g)\neq\emptyset\). Take \(x,y\in\mathrm{C}(f,g)\), then using Theorem 4, we can write

$$g(x)=f(x)=f(y)=g(y). $$

As f or g is one-one, we have

$$x=y. $$

 □

Theorem 6

In addition to the hypotheses of Theorem  4, suppose that the following condition holds:

(u2):

\((f,g)\) is weakly compatible pair.

Then f and g have a unique common fixed point.

Proof

Let x be a coincidence point of f and g. Write \(g(x)=f(x)=\overline{x}\). In view of Lemma 3 and (u2), \(\overline{x}\) is also a coincidence point of f and g. It follows from Theorem 4 with \(y=\overline{x}\) that \(g(x)=g(\overline{x})\), i.e., \(\overline{x}=g(\overline{x})\), which shows

$$\overline{x}=g(\overline{x})=f(\overline{x}). $$

Hence, \(\overline{x}\) is a common fixed point of f and g. To prove uniqueness, assume that \(x^{*}\) is another common fixed point of f and g. Then again from Theorem 4, we have

$$x^{*}=g\bigl(x^{*}\bigr)=g(\overline{x})=\overline{x}. $$

This completes the proof. □

Theorem 7

In addition to the hypotheses (a)-(e) of Theorem  1 (resp. Theorem  2 or Theorem  3), suppose that the condition (u0) (of Theorem  4) holds. Then f and g have a unique common fixed point.

Proof

We know that in an ordered metric space, each of an O-compatible pair, an \(\overline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatible pair, and an \(\underline{\mathrm{O}}\)-compatible pair is weakly compatible so that (u2) is trivially satisfied. Hence proceeding along the lines of the proofs of Theorems 4 and 6 our result follows. □

Corollary 2

Theorem  4 (resp. Theorem  7) remains true if we replace the condition (u0) by one of the following conditions (besides retaining rest of the hypotheses):

(\(\mathrm{u}_{0}^{1}\)):

\((fX,\preceq)\) is totally ordered,

(\(\mathrm{u}_{0}^{2}\)):

\((X,\preceq)\) is \((f,g)\)-directed.

Proof

Suppose that (\(\mathrm{u}_{0}^{1}\)) holds, then for each pair \(x,y\in X\), we have

$$f(x)\prec\succ f(y), $$

which implies that \(\{fx,fy\}\) is a ≺≻-chain between \(f(x)\) and \(f(y)\) in \(g(X)\). It follows that \(\mathrm{C}(fx,fy,\prec\succ,gX)\) is nonempty for each \(x,y\in X\), i.e., (u0) holds and hence Theorem 4 (resp. Theorem 7) is applicable.

Next, assume that (\(\mathrm{u}_{0}^{2}\)) holds, then for each pair \(x,y\in X\), \(\exists z\in X\) such that

$$f(x)\prec\succ g(z)\prec\succ f(y), $$

which implies that \(\{fx,gz,fy\}\) is a ≺≻-chain between \(f(x)\) and \(f(y)\) in \(g(X)\). It follows that \(\mathrm{C}(fx,fy,\prec\succ,gX)\) is nonempty for each \(x,y\in X\), i.e., (u0) holds and hence Theorem 4 (resp. Theorem 7) is applicable. □

Remark 8

Notice that Alam et al. [16] used condition (\(\mathrm{u}_{0}^{2}\)) to prove uniqueness results (see Theorem 5 [16] along with comments). Here, we use condition (u0), which is relatively weak in view of Corollary 2.

References

  1. Turinici, M: Abstract comparison principles and multivariable Gronwall-Bellman inequalities. J. Math. Anal. Appl. 117(1), 100-127 (1986)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Turinici, M: Fixed points for monotone iteratively local contractions. Demonstr. Math. 19(1), 171-180 (1986)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Ran, ACM, Reurings, MCB: A fixed point theorem in partially ordered sets and some applications to matrix equations. Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 132(5), 1435-1443 (2004)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. Nieto, JJ, Rodríguez-López, R: Contractive mapping theorems in partially ordered sets and applications to ordinary differential equations. Order 22(3), 223-239 (2005)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Agarwal, RP, El-Gebeily, MA, O’Regan, D: Generalized contractions in partially ordered metric spaces. Appl. Anal. 87(1), 109-116 (2008)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. O’Regan, D, Petruşel, A: Fixed point theorems for generalized contractions in ordered metric spaces. J. Math. Anal. Appl. 341(2), 1241-1252 (2008)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Ćirić, L, Cakic, N, Rajovic, M, Ume, JS: Monotone generalized nonlinear contractions in partially ordered metric spaces. Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2008, 131294 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Harandi, AA, Emami, H: A fixed point theorem for contraction type maps in partially ordered metric spaces and application to ordinary differential equations. Nonlinear Anal. 72(5), 2238-2242 (2010)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Harjani, J, Sadarangani, K: Generalized contractions in partially ordered metric spaces and applications to ordinary differential equations. Nonlinear Anal. 72, 1188-1197 (2010)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Altun, I, Simsek, H: Some fixed point theorems on ordered metric spaces and application. Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2010, 621469 (2010)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  11. Caballero, J, Harjani, J, Sadarangani, K: Contractive-like mapping principles in ordered metric spaces and application to ordinary differential equations. Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2010, 916064 (2010)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  12. Jleli, M, Rajic, VC, Samet, B, Vetro, C: Fixed point theorems on ordered metric spaces and applications to nonlinear elastic beam equations. J. Fixed Point Theory Appl. 12, 175-192 (2012)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Hadj Amor, S, Karapınar, E, Kumam, P: A new class of generalized contraction using \(\mathcal{P}\)-functions in ordered metric spaces. An. Ştiinţ. Univ. ‘Ovidius’ Constanţa. 23(2), 93-106 (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Karapınar, E, Sadarangani, K: Berinde mappings in ordered metric spaces. Rev. R. Acad. Cienc. Exactas Fís. Nat., Ser. A Mat. (2014). doi:10.1007/s13398-014-0186-2

    Google Scholar 

  15. Karapınar, E, Erhan, IM, Aksoy, U: Weak ψ-contractions on partially ordered metric spaces and applications to boundary value problems. Bound. Value Probl. 2014, 149 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Alam, A, Khan, AR, Imdad, M: Some coincidence theorems for generalized nonlinear contractions in ordered metric spaces with applications. Fixed Point Theory Appl. 2014, 216 (2014)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  17. Boyd, DW, Wong, JSW: On nonlinear contractions. Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 20, 458-464 (1969)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Lipschutz, S: Schaum’s Outlines of Theory and Problems of Set Theory and Related Topics. McGraw-Hill, New York (1964)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Turinici, M: Ran-Reurings fixed point results in ordered metric spaces. Libertas Math. 31, 49-55 (2011)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. Jungck, G: Commuting maps and fixed points. Am. Math. Mon. 83(4), 261-263 (1976)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Jungck, G: Common fixed points for noncontinuous nonself maps on non-metric spaces. Far East J. Math. Sci. 4, 199-215 (1996)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Sessa, S: On a weak commutativity condition of mappings in fixed point considerations. Publ. Inst. Math. (Belgr.) 32, 149-153 (1982)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  23. Jungck, G: Compatible mappings and common fixed points. Int. J. Math. Math. Sci. 9(4), 771-779 (1986)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. Sastry, KPR, Krishna Murthy, ISR: Common fixed points of two partially commuting tangential selfmaps on a metric space. J. Math. Anal. Appl. 250(2), 731-734 (2000)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Gnana Bhaskar, T, Lakshmikantham, V: Fixed point theorems in partially ordered metric spaces and applications. Nonlinear Anal. 65(7), 1379-1393 (2006)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Lakshmikantham, V, Ćirić, L: Coupled fixed point theorems for nonlinear contractions in partially ordered metric spaces. Nonlinear Anal. 70, 4341-4349 (2009)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Alam, A, Imdad, M: Comparable linear contractions in ordered metric spaces. Fixed Point Theory (2015, accepted)

  28. Jotic, N: Some fixed point theorems in metric spaces. Indian J. Pure Appl. Math. 26, 947-952 (1995)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Turinici, M: Linear contractions in product ordered metric spaces. Ann. Univ. Ferrara 59, 187-198 (2013)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  30. Luong, NV, Thuan, NX: Coupled points in ordered generalized metric spaces and application to integro differential equations. An. Ştiinţ. Univ. ‘Ovidius’ Constanţa 21(3), 155-180 (2013)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

All the authors are grateful to two learned referees for their critical readings and pertinent comments on the earlier version of the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mohammad Imdad.

Additional information

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Authors’ contributions

All the authors contributed equally. Thus formally, all the authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Alam, A., Khan, Q.H. & Imdad, M. Enriching some recent coincidence theorems for nonlinear contractions in ordered metric spaces. Fixed Point Theory Appl 2015, 141 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1186/s13663-015-0382-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/s13663-015-0382-6

MSC

Keywords