Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x24gv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-04T22:15:22.829Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Fundamentality and Time’s Arrow

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

The distribution of matter in our universe is strikingly time asymmetric. Most famously, the Second Law of Thermodynamics says that entropy tends to increase toward the future but not toward the past. But what explains this time-asymmetric distribution of matter? In this article, I explore the idea that time itself has a direction by drawing from recent work on grounding and metaphysical fundamentality. I will argue that positing such a direction of time, in addition to time-asymmetric boundary conditions (such as the so-called past hypothesis), enables a better explanation of the thermodynamic asymmetry than is available otherwise.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

†.

I am grateful to Eddy Keming Chen, Florian Fischer, Roman Frigg, Richard Healey, Andreas Hüttemann, David Glick, Marc Lange, Tim Maudlin, Carlo Rovelli, and two anonymous referees for this journal for their helpful comments and suggestions. Special thanks to Siegfried Jaag for helpful discussion and for comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

References

Albert, David Z. 2000. Time and Chance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Albert, David Z. 2015. After Physics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David M. 1983. What Is a Law of Nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2007. Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boltzmann, Ludwig. 1964. Lectures on Gas Theory, 1896–1899. Trans. Brush, S. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Callender, Craig. 2004. “Measures, Explanations, and the Past: Should ‘Special’ Initial Conditions Be Explained?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55:195217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callender, Craig 2011a. “The Past History of Molecules.” In Probabilities in Physics, ed. Beisbart, Claus and Hartmann, Stephan, 83113. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartmann, Stephan 2011b. “Thermodynamic Asymmetry in Time.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2011 ed., ed. E. N. Zalta. Stanford, CA: Stanford University. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/time-thermo/.Google Scholar
Carroll, Sean M. 2010. From Eternity to Here. New York: Dutton.Google Scholar
Carroll, Sean M., and Chen, Jennifer. 2004. “Spontaneous Inflation and the Origin of the Arrow of Time.” arXiv:hep-th/0410270.Google Scholar
Dowe, Phil. 2000. Physical Causation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Earman, John. 2006. “The Past Hypothesis: Not Even False.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37:399430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Emery, Nina. Forthcoming. “Laws and Their Instances.” Philosophical Studies.Google Scholar
Feynman, Richard. 1967. The Character of Physical Law. Boston: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit. 2012. “Guide to Ground.” In Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality, ed. Correia, Fabrice and Schnieder, Benjamin, 3780. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frigg, Roman. 2009. “Typicality and the Approach to Equilibrium in Boltzmannian Statistical Mechanics.” Philosophy of Science 76:9971008.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frigg, Roman, and Werndl, Charlotte. 2012. “Demystifying Typicality.” Philosophy of Science 79:917–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frisch, Mathias. 2014. Causal Reasoning in Physics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greene, Brian. 2004. The Fabric of the Cosmos. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Hicks, Michael T., and van Elswyk, Peter. 2015. “Humean Laws and Circular Explanation.” Philosophical Studies 172:433–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hitchcock, Christopher R. 1999. “Contrastive Explanation and the Demons of Determinism.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50:585612.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, Paul. 1987. Asymmetries in Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lange, Marc. 2009. Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lange, Marc 2013. “Grounding, Scientific Explanation, and Humean Laws.” Philosophical Studies 164:255–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewer, Barry. 2007. “Counterfactuals and the Second Law.” In Causation, Physics and the Constitution of Reality, ed. Price, Huw and Corry, Richard, 293326. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Corry, Richard 2012. “Two Accounts of Laws and Time.” Philosophical Studies 160:115–37.Google Scholar
Maudlin, Tim. 2007a. The Metaphysics within Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maudlin, Tim 2007b. “What Could Be Objective about Probabilities?Studies in History and Philosophy of Science B 38:275–91.Google Scholar
Ney, Alyssa. 2011. “Tim Maudlin: The Metaphysics within Physics.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62:683–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, Jill. 2008. “Two Views on Time-Reversal.” Philosophy of Science 75:201–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, Jill 2011. “Time in Thermodynamics.” In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Time, ed. Callender, Craig, 312–50. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Penrose, Roger. 1989. The Emperor’s New Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, Huw. 1996. Time’s Arrow and Archimedes’ Point. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Price, Huw 2004. “On the Origins of the Arrow of Time: Why There Is Still a Puzzle about the Low-Entropy Past.” In Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Science, ed. Hitchcock, Christopher, 219–39. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, Christopher 2011. “The Flow of Time.” In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Time, ed. Callender, Craig, 276311. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raven, Michael J. 2015. “Ground.” Philosophy Compass 10:322–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, Gideon. 2010. “Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction.” In Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology, ed. Hale, Bob and Hoffmann, Aviv, 109–36. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sachs, Robert G. 1987. The Physics of Time Reversal. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2009. “On What Grounds What.” In Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, ed. Chalmers, David, Manley, David, and Wasserman, Ryan, 347–83. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David, Manley, David, and Wasserman, Ryan 2016. “Grounding in the Image of Causation.” Philosophical Studies 173:49100.Google Scholar
Sklar, Lawrence. 1993. Physics and Chance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace, David. 2010. “Gravity, Entropy, and Cosmology: In Search of Clarity.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61:513–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace, David 2013. “The Arrow of Time in Physics.” In A Companion to the Philosophy of Time, ed. Bardon, Adrian and Dyke, Heather, 262–81. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Winsberg, Eric. 2004. “Can Conditioning on the ‘Past Hypothesis’ Militate Against the Reversibility Objections?Philosophy of Science 71:489504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar