Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-02T07:14:30.424Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Discussion: How Not to Reduce a Functional Psychology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Robert C. Richardson*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy University of Cincinnati

Abstract

There is often substantial disparity between philosophical ideals and scientific practice. Philosophical reductionism is motivated by a drive for ontological austerity. The vehicle is conceptual parsimony: the fewer our conceptual primitives, the less are our ontological commitments. A general moral to be drawn from my “Functionalism and Reductionism” (1979) is that scientific reduction does not, and should not be expected to, facilitate conceptual economy; yet reduction it still is, and in the classical mold. Those who press for the irreducibility of a functional psychology have been seduced by an inadequate account of scientific reduction. Patricia Kitcher (1980) is unhappy with my argument because it fails to live up to her philosophical ideals. “The claim that psychology is irreducible to neurophysiology,” she suggests, “rests to a large extent on the fact that, even in principle, neurophysiology is not capable of carrying out the explanatory work of a functional psychology” (1980, p. 140).

Type
Discussion
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Patricia Kitcher commented on an abbreviated version of my (1979) at the Eastern Division Meetings of the APA in December of 1978. Some of my comments are derived from that session. All of them benefited from it and from Patricia Kitcher. I am especially thankful for the incisive comments from two reviewers for this journal.

This work was completed under a grant from the National Endowment for the Humanities; revisions were undertaken with the support of the Taft Committee at the University of Cincinnati. For their support I am also thankful.

References

REFERENCES

Block, N. (1978), “Troubles With Functionalism”, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. IX, edited by Savage, Wade. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. pp. 261325.Google Scholar
Block, N. (1980), “Are Absent Qualia Impossible?The Philosophical Review, Vol. 89, No. 2: pp. 257274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandt, R. and Kim, J. (1967), “The Logic of The Identity Theory”, The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 64, No. 9: pp. 515537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1980), “Is Thinker a Natural Kind?”, in preparation.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. S. (1980), “A Perspective on Mind-Brain Research”, The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 77, No. 4: pp. 185207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crow, James F. and Kimura, M. (1970), An Introduction to Population Genetics Theory. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Dobzhansky, T., Ayala, F. J., Stebbins, G. L. and Valentine, J. W. (1977), Evolution. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman and Company.Google Scholar
Feigl, H. (1958), “The ‘Mental’ and the ‘Physical'”, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II, edited by Feigl, H., Scriven, M., and Maxwell, G. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. pp. 370497.Google Scholar
Fisher, R. A. (1930), The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection. New York: Dover Publications.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1975), The Language of Thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell Co.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1980), “Methodological Solipsism Considered As a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology”, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: pp. 6373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fridovich, I. (1978), “The Biology of Oxygen Radicals”, Science, Vol. 201, No. 4359: pp. 875880.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gunderson, K. (1971), Mentality and Machines. New York: Doubleday & Co.Google Scholar
Kemeny, J. G. and Oppenheim, P. (1967), “On Reduction”, Philosophical Studies, Vol. 19; as reprinted in Readings in the Philosophy of Science, edited by Brody, B. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall. pp. 307318.Google Scholar
Kimbrough, S. O. (1979), “On The Reduction of Genetics to Molecular Biology”, Philosophy of Science, Vol. 46, No. 3: pp. 389406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1980), “How To Reduce a Functional Psychology?Philosophy of Science, Vol. 47, No. 1: pp. 134140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewontin, R. C. (1974), The Genetic Basis of Evolutionary Change: New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, E. (1961), The Structure of Science. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. (1980), “Computation and Cognition: Issues In the Foundations of Cognitive Science”, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, vol. 3: pp. 111169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1964), “Ontological Reduction and the World of Numbers”, Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 61; as reprinted in The Ways of Paradox. New York: Random House, 1966. pp. 199207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richardson, R. C. (1979), “Functionalism and Reductionism”, Philosophy of Science, Vol. 46, No. 4: pp. 533558.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richardson, R. C. (1980a), “Intentional Realism or Intentional Instrumentalism?Cognition and Brain Theory, Vol. 3, No. 4: pp. 125135.Google Scholar
Richardson, R. C. (1980b), “Reductionist Research Programmes in Psychology”, in Asquith, P. D. and Giere, R. N., (eds.), PSA 1980, vol. 1. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association. pp. 171183.Google Scholar
Richardson, R. C. (1981a), “Internal Representation: Prologue to a Theory of Intentionality”, Philosophical Topics, Vol. 1, pp. 171211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richardson, R. C. (1981b), “The Use and Abuse of ‘In Principle’ Arguments”, in preparation.Google Scholar
Richardson, R. C. (forthcoming), “Review of Wade Savage (ed.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. IX” in NoÛs.Google Scholar
Roughgarden, J. (1979), Theory of Population Genetics and Evolutionary Ecology: An Introduction. New York: MacMillan Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Ruse, M. (1974), “Reduction in Genetics”, in R. S. Cohen, et. al. (eds.), PSA 1974. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Co. pp. 633651.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (1971), “Statistical Explanation”, in Salmon, Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (1975), “Theoretical Explanation”, in Korner, S. (ed.), Explanation. New Haven: Yale University Press. pp. 118145.Google Scholar
Schaffner, K. (1974), “Reduction in Biology”, in R. S. Cohen, et. al. (eds.), PSA 1974. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Stahl, F. W. (1964), The Mechanics of Inheritance. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Williams, M. B. (1970), “Deducing the Consequences of Evolution: A Mathematical Model”, Journal of Theoretical Biology, vol. 29: pp. 343385.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wimsatt, W. C. (1974), “Reductive Explanation: A Functional Account”, in R. S. Cohen, et. al. (eds.), PSA 1974. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Co. pp. 671710.Google Scholar