Skip to main content
  • 236 Accesses

Abstract

According to the interpretation I described in the previous chapter, the distinctive feature of law is its capacity to use physical force or the threat of physical force to compel subjects to obey. This, however, assumes that Hobbes’ account of law conflates the causal and normative aspects of legal guidance or, simply, that his political and legal philosophy lack the concept of authority altogether. Fortunately, this assumption is too quick.1 As I will argue in this chapter, the notion of authority occupies a prominent role in Hobbes’ political theory. I will show that the directives issued by the sovereign authoritatively regulate the subjects’ actions; the causal power to usu physical force or the threat to use physical force normally included in legal systems is merely a back-up mechanism to further motivate subjects to comply with the law.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. The assumption made by the standard interpretation would be unfortunate because the idea that the law is authoritative is really a commonplace, so that any reasonable analysis of the concept of law must account for this feature. See M. C. Murphy, Philosophy of Law: The Fundamentals ( Oxford: Blackwell, 2006 ), pp. 6–9

    Google Scholar 

  2. S. J. Shapiro, Legality ( Cambridge and London: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2011 ), p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  3. The classic example is John Austin’s theory of law. See J. Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, W. E. Rumble (ed.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), I, 21–5, 29–30.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Despite some points in common, Hobbes’ and Austin’s accounts of law are fundamentally different. See M. C. Murphy, ‘Hobbes (and Austin, and Aquinas) on Law as Command of a Sovereign’, in A. P. Martinich and K. Hoekstra (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Hobbes ( Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015 ).

    Google Scholar 

  5. H. L. A. Hart, Essays on Bentham: Studies in Jurisprudence and Political Theory ( Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982 ), pp. 254–5.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  6. J. Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 44, 47–8, 78–9

    Google Scholar 

  7. J. Raz, Between Authority and Interpretation: On the Theory of Law and Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), p. 145. However, some mistakes may be so important that authoritative directives may stop being binding. See Raz, The Morality of Freedom , p. 62.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  8. G. S. Kavka, ‘Why even morally perfect people would need government’, Social Philosophy & Policy, 12(1) (1995), pp. 2–3. It should be borne in mind that this is not the way Hobbes understands angels. See Leviathan, XXXIV, 622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. S. J. Shapiro, ‘Authority’, in J. L. Coleman and S. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law ( New York: Oxford University Press, 2002 ), p. 383.

    Google Scholar 

  10. A. Hamilton, J. Jay, and J. Madison, The Federalist (New York: Modern Library, 1937), p. 337, quoted in Kavka, ‘Why even morally perfect people would need government’, p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  11. H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law , 3rd edn (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2012), p. 40; Shapiro, Legality , pp. 69–71.

    Google Scholar 

  12. L. Green, The Authority of the State (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), pp. 71, 75, 151–2.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See also D. Dyzenhaus, ‘Law and Public Reason’, McGill Law Journal/Revue de droit de McGill , 38(2) (1993), pp. 373, 381

    Google Scholar 

  14. E. R. Ewin, Virtues and Rights: The Moral Philosophy of Thomas Hobbes (Boulder: Westview Press, 1991 ), pp. 44, 53

    Google Scholar 

  15. L. Foisneau, ‘Hobbes y la autoridad de la ley’, Derechos y libertades, 17 (2007), pp. 60–1

    Google Scholar 

  16. Green, The Authority of the State , p. 37; L. Green, ‘Law and Obligations’, in J. L. Coleman and S. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), p. 518, n. 13; Hart, Essays on Bentham , pp. 253–4

    Google Scholar 

  17. A. P. Martinich, The Two Gods of Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes on Religion and Politics ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992 ), pp. 128–32

    Book  Google Scholar 

  18. C. W. Morris, An Essay on the Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998 ), pp. 175–6, 214, n. 101

    Book  Google Scholar 

  19. C. W. Morris, ‘The Very Idea of Popular Sovereignty: “We the People” Reconsidered’, Social Philosophy & Policy, 17 (1) (2000), p. 3

    Google Scholar 

  20. C. W. Morris, ‘State Legitimacy and Social Order’, in J. Kühnelt (ed.), Political Legitimization without Morality? (Heidelberg: Springer, 2008), pp. 23, 31, n. 32

    Google Scholar 

  21. C. W. Morris, ‘State Coercion and Force’, Social Philosophy & Policy, 29 (1) (2012), p. 39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. G. J. Postema, Bentham and the Natural Law Tradition (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 56–8; Rosler, ‘Racionalidad y autoridad política’, p. 6; Rosler, Political Authority and Obligation in Aristotle , p. 99

    Google Scholar 

  23. A. Rosler, ‘El enemigo de la república: Hobbes y la soberanía del Estado’, in T. Hobbes, Elementos Filosóficos. Del Ciudadano, A. Rosler (trans.) ( Buenos Aires: Editorial Hydra, 2010 ), pp. 55–60

    Google Scholar 

  24. A. Rosler, ‘Odi et Amo? Hobbes on the State of Nature’, Hobbes Studies , 24(1) (2011), p. 98; Shapiro, ‘Authority’, p. 396, n. 27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. S. Sreedhar, Hobbes on Resistance: Defying the Leviathan ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010 ), pp. 113–19

    Book  Google Scholar 

  26. E. N. Yankah, ‘The Force of Law: The Role of Coercion in Legal Norms’, University of Richmond Law Review, 42 (5) (2008), p. 1210.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See also D. Dyzenhaus, ‘How Hobbes Met the “Hobbes Challenge”’, The Modern Law Review, 72 (3) (2009), p. 496

    Google Scholar 

  28. D. Dyzenhaus, ‘Hobbes’s Constitutional Theory’, in T. Hobbes, Leviathan, I. Shapiro (ed.) ( New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2010 ), p. 460

    Google Scholar 

  29. D. Dyzenhaus, Hard Cases in Wicked Legal Systems: Pathologies of Legality, 2nd edn ( Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010 ), p. 213

    Google Scholar 

  30. D. Dyzenhaus, ‘Hobbes on the authority of law’, in D. Dyzenhaus and T. Poole (eds.), Hobbes and the Law ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012 ), p. 195

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  31. G. F. Gaus, ‘Hobbes’s Challenge to Public Reason Liberalism: Public Reason and Religious Conviction in Leviathan ’, in S. A. Lloyd (ed.), Hobbes Today: Insights for the 21st Century ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013 ), p. 162

    Google Scholar 

  32. D. Gauthier, ‘Thomas Hobbes and the Contractarian Theory of Law’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Suppl. 6 (1990), p. 30

    Google Scholar 

  33. L. Krasnoff, ‘Voluntarism and Conventionalism in Hobbes and Kant’, Hobbes Studies, 25 (1) (2012), p. 44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. S. A. Lloyd, Ideals as Interests in Hobbes’s Leviathan: The Power of Mind over Matter ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992 ), p. 119

    Book  Google Scholar 

  35. M. C. Murphy, ‘Hobbes on Conscientious Disobedience’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 77 (3) (1995), p. 268

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. L. Madanes, El árbitro arbitrario: Hobbes, Spinoza y la libertad de expresión (Buenos Aires: Eudeba, 2001), pp. 38–9, 43; Sreedhar, Hobbes on Resistance , p. 114.

    Google Scholar 

  37. See also K. Hoekstra, ‘Disarming the Prophets: Thomas Hobbes and Predictive Power’, Rivista di storia della filosofia, 21 (1) (2004), p. 109

    Google Scholar 

  38. K. Hoekstra, ‘The End of Philosophy (The Case of Hobbes)’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , 106(1) (2006), p. 50; Lloyd, Ideals as Interests , pp. 140–1, 183

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. S. A. Lloyd, Morality in the Philosophy of Thomas Hobbes: Cases in the Law of Nature (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), pp. 342, 348–51, 370–2; Martinich, The Two Gods of Leviathan, pp. 297–8

    Book  Google Scholar 

  40. J. B. Murphy, The Philosophy of Positive Law: Foundations of Jurisprudence (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2005), p. 168; Sreedhar, Hobbes on Resistance, pp. 101–2, 117–18

    Book  Google Scholar 

  41. H. Warrender, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes: His Theory of Obligation ( Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1957 ), p. 172.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2015 Luciano Venezia

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Venezia, L. (2015). The Authority of Law. In: Hobbes on Legal Authority and Political Obligation. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137490254_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics