Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ttngx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-24T08:32:52.930Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Theorizing Transnational Law – Varieties of Transnational Law and the Universalistic Stance

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

It is difficult to put a label on a historical period. Human history is full of variety, complexities and contradictory developments. Consequently, the precondition of grand theories of history is often their openness to unjustified simplification. On the other hand, some orientation is indispensable, and for this, general descriptions are helpful if one stays aware of their limited function and value. With this in mind it is possible to state that the post-war period is marked by what one may call a universalistic stance.

Type
GLJ@TEN – Theorizing Transnational Law
Copyright
Copyright © 2009 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 See Hart, H. L. A., The Concept of Law 189 (1961) (describing the minimal content of Natural Law).Google Scholar

2 Mahlmann, Matthias, 1798 Renewed? Prospects of the Protection of Human Rights in Europe, 11 Cardozo J. Int'l & Comp. L. 903 (2004).Google Scholar

3 See Mahlmann, Matthias, Gleichheitsschutz im Europäischen Rechtskreis, in Gleichbehandlungsrecht 87 (Beate Rudolf & Matthias Mahlmann eds., 2007).Google Scholar

4 See, e.g., Rorty, Richard, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (1989).Google Scholar

5 See Habermas, Jürgen, Faktizität und Geltung 17 (1992).Google Scholar

6 Plato, , Apology, 31 d, 41 d.Google Scholar

7 Kant, Immanuel, 5 Critique of Practical Reason (1788).Google Scholar

8 Jean-François Lyotard, Le Différend 208 (1983).Google Scholar

9 See Williams, Bernard, Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline, 75 Phil. 487 (2000) (discussing the notion of vindicatory statements and their impossibility).Google Scholar

10 Luhmann, Niklas, Das Recht der Gesellschaft (1995).Google Scholar

11 Posner, Richard A., Economic Analysis of Law, (7th ed. 2007).Google Scholar

12 See Jolls, Christine, Sunstein, Cass R. & Thaler, Richard, A Behavioural Approach to Law and Economics, in Behavioral Law and Economics 14 (Cass R. Sunstein ed., 2000) (“The task of behavioural law and economics, simply stated, is to explore the implications of actual (not hypothesized) human behavior for the law. How do ‘real people’ differ from homo economicus?”). For the role of heuristics, see the exchange in: Cass R. Sunstein, Moral Heuristics, 28 Behav. & Brain Sci. 531 (2005), and John Mikhail, Moral Heuristics or Moral Competence? Reflections on Sunstein, 28 Behav. & Brain Sci. 557 (2005).Google Scholar

13 Derrida, Jacques, Force of Law: The ‘Mystical Foundation of Authority,‘ in Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice 3 (Drucilla Cornell, Michael Rosenfeld, & David Gray Carlson eds., 1992). For more comments, see Matthias Mahlmann, Law and Force: 20th Century Radical Legal Philosophy, Post-Modernism and the Foundations of Law, 9 Res Publica 19 (2003).Google Scholar

14 Levinas, Emmanuel, Totalité et Infini 173 (1961).Google Scholar

15 Rorty, , supra note 4. Richard Rorty, Human Rights, Rationality, and Sentimentality, in On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 111 (Stephen Shute & Susan Hurley eds., 1993).Google Scholar

16 Habermas, Jürgen, 1 Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns 533, (“Die utopische Perspektive von Versöhnung und Freiheit ist in den Bedingungen einer kommunikativen Vergesellschaftung der Individuen angelegt, sie ist in den sprachlichen Reproduktionsmechanismen der Gattung schon eingebaut”.)Google Scholar

17 Habermas, , supra note 5, at 154.Google Scholar

18 See Mahlmann, Matthias, Elemente einer ethischen Grundrechtstheorie (2008).Google Scholar

19 Luhmann, , supra note 10, at 576 – 579. For a background understanding of human rights, see Niklas Luhmann, Grundrechte als Institution: Ein Beitrag zur politischen Soziologie (1965), and Niklas Luhmann, Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft 1075 (1997).Google Scholar

20 This concept was formulated in the Coase-Theorem. Ronald Coase, The Problem of Social Cost, 3 J.L. & Econ. 1 (1961).Google Scholar

21 See, e.g., the passages and the tacitly implied ethical norms in Rorty, supra note 4, at 84, 88, 91, though Rorty denies this. Id. at 88.Google Scholar

22 For more detail on the phenomenology of morality, see Mattias Mahlmann, Ethics, Law, and the Challenge of Cognitive Science, 8 German Law Journal 577, 580 (2007).Google Scholar

23 See, e.g., Noam Chomsky, Language and Problems of Knowledge: The Managua Lectures 152 (1988); Mahlmann, , supra note 22, at 577; Matthias Mahlmann, Rationalismus in der praktischen Theorie (2nd ed., 2009); Mikhail, John, Elements of Moral Cognition (2009). Marc D. Hauser, Moral Minds: How Nature Designed our Sense of Right and Wrong (2006) closely follows in constitutive parts Mikhail's previous work.Google Scholar

24 For examples of rules, see Mahlmann, , supra note 23, and on rights, see Mahlmann, supra note 18.Google Scholar

25 See Mahlmann, , supra note 18, at 487.Google Scholar