Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T20:11:52.999Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Further Insights on Fake-Barn Cases and Intuition Variation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 May 2021

Carsten Bergenholtz
Affiliation:
University of Aarhus, Department of Management, Fuglesangs Allé 4, Bygning 2622, C06, 8210 Aarhus V, Denmark
Jacob Busch*
Affiliation:
University of Aarhus, Department of Philosophy, Jens Chr. Skous Vej 7, Bygning 1465, 423, 8000 Aarhus C, Denmark
Sara Kier Praëm
Affiliation:
University of Aarhus, Department of Mathematics, Ny Munkegade 120, Bygning 1520, 8000 Aarhus C, Denmark
*
*Corresponding author. Email: filjab@cas.au.dk

Abstract

Studies in experimental philosophy claim to document intuition variation. Some studies focus on demographic group-variation; Colaço et al., for example, claim that age generates intuition variation regarding knowledge attribution in a fake-barn scenario. Other studies claim to show intuition variation when comparing the intuition of philosophers to that of non-philosophers. The main focus has been on documenting intuition variation rather than uncovering what underlying factor(s) may prompt such a phenomenon. We explore a number of suggested explanatory hypotheses put forth by Colaço et al., as well as an attempt to test Sosa's claim that intuition variance is a result of people ‘filling in the details’ of a thought experiment differently from one another. We show (i) that people respond consistently across conditions aimed at ‘filling in the details’ of thought experiments, (ii) that risk attitude does not seem relevant to knowledge ascription, (iii) that people's knowledge ascriptions do not vary due to views about defeasibility of knowledge. Yet, (iv) we find no grounds to reject that a large proportion of people appear to adhere to so-called subjectivism about knowledge, which may explain why they generally have intuitions about the fake-barn scenario that vary from those of philosophers.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adleberg, T., Thompson, M. and Nahmias, E. (2015). “Do Men and Women Have Different Philosophical Intuitions? Further Data.” Philosophical Psychology 28(5), 615–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergenholtz, C., Busch, J. and Kier Praëm, S. (Forthcoming). ‘Exclusion Criteria in Experimental Philosophy.’ Erkenntnis, online first. https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10670-019-00168-5?shared-article-renderer.Google Scholar
Bonsang, E. and Dohmen, T. (2012). ‘Cognitive Ageing and Risk Attitude.’ Netspar Discussion Paper, 1/2012-004.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buckwalter, W. and Stich, S. (2014). ‘Gender and Philosophical Intuition.’ In Knobe, J. and Nichols, S. (eds), Experimental Philosophy, Vol. 2, pp. 307–46. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, C.D., Payne, B.K. and Doris, J.M. (2013). ‘Morality in High Definition: Emotion Differentiation Calibrates the Influence of Incidental Disgust on Moral Judgments.’ Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 49(4), 719–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colaço, D., Buckwalter, W., Stich, S. and Machery, E. (2014). ‘Epistemic Intuitions in Fake-Barn Thought Experiments.Episteme 11(2), 199212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devitt, M. (2011). ‘Experimental Semantics.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82, 418–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Difallah, D., Filatova, E. and Ipeirotis, P. (2018). ‘Demographics and Dynamics of Mechanical Turk Workers.’ WSDM ‘18: Proceedings of the Eleventh ACM International Conference on Web Search and Data Mining, pp. 135–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dohmen, T., Falk, A., Huffman, D., Sunde, U., Schupp, J. and Wagner, G.G. (2011). ‘Individual Risk Attitudes: Measurement, Determinants and Behavioral Consequences.’ Journal of the European Economic Association 9, 522–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dowse, R. and Ehlers, M. (2005). ‘Medicine Labels Incorporating Pictograms: Do they Influence Understanding and Adherence?Patient Education and Counseling 58, 6370.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haidt, J., Koller, S. and Dias, M. (1993). ‘Affect, Culture, and Morality, or is it Wrong to Eat Your Dog?Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65, 613–28.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hauser, D.J. and Schwarz, N. (2016). ‘Attentive Turkers: MTurk Participants Perform Better on Online Attention Checks than do Subject Pool Participants.’ Behavior Research Methods 48(1), 400–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hauser, D.J., Paolacci, G. and Chandler, J.J. (2019). ‘Common Concerns with MTurk as a Participant Pool: Evidence and Solutions.’ In Kardes, F.R., Herr, P.P. and Schwarz, N. (eds), Handbook of Research Methods in Consumer Psychology, pp. 319–37. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
Henrich, J. (2020). The Weirdest People in the World: How the West Became Psychologically Peculiar and Particularly Prosperous. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Horvath, J. (2010). ‘How (Not) to React to Experimental Philosophy.’ Philosophical Psychology 23, 447–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2019 a). ‘Philosophical Intuitions are Surprisingly Robust Across Demographic Differences.’ Epistemology & Philosophy of Science 56(2), 2936.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J. (2019 b). ‘Difference and Robustness in the Patterns of Philosophical Intuition Across Demographic Groups.’ https://cpb-us-w2.wpmucdn.com/campuspress.yale.edu/dist/3/1454/files/2019/12/Difference-Robustness-2.pdf.Google Scholar
Levie, W.H. and Lentz, R. (1982). ‘Effects of Text Illustrations: A Review of Research .’ Educational Communication and Technology 30, 195232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, W.G. (2006). ‘On the Gettier Problem Problem.’ In Hetherington, S. (ed.), Epistemology Futures, pp. 148–68. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ludwig, K. (2007). ‘The Epistemology of Thought Experiments: First Person Versus Third Person Approaches.’ Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31, 128–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, E. and Stich, S. (2019). ‘Demographic Differences in Philosophical Intuition: A Reply to Joshua Knobe.’ Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S. and Stich, S. (2004). ‘Semantics, Cross-Cultural Style.’ Cognition 92, B1B12.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nado, J. (2014). ‘Philosophical Expertise.’ Philosophy Compass 9(9), 631–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S., Stich, S., and Weinberg, J. (2003). ‘Meta-Skepticism: Meditations on Ethno-Epistemology.’ In Luper, S. (ed.), The Skeptics, pp. 227–47. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing.Google Scholar
Semetko, H.A. and Scammell, M. (2012). The SAGE Handbook of Political Communication. London: Sage.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seyedsayamdost, H. (2014). ‘On Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions: Further Evidence for Cross-Cultural Uniformity of Epistemic Intuitions – Short Report.’ https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2538611.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. (2009). ‘A Defense of the Use of Intuitions in Philosophy.’ In Bishop, M. and Murphy, D. (eds), Stich and His Critics, pp. 101–13. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swain, S., Alexander, J. and Weinberg, J.M. (2008). ‘The Instability of Philosophical Intuitions: Running Hot and Cold on Truetemp.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76(1), 138–55. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2007.00118.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomas, K.A. and Clifford, S. (2017). ‘Validity and Mechanical Turk: An Assessment of Exclusion Methods and Interactive Experiments.’ Computers in Human Behavior 77, 184–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, J. (2013). ‘A Conspicuous Art: Putting Gettier to the Test.’ Philosophers’ Imprint 13(10), 116.Google Scholar
Turri, J. (2020). ‘Reasons and Basing in Commonsense Epistemology: Evidence from Two Experiments.’ In Bondy, P. and Carter, J.A. (eds), Well-Founded Belief: New Essays on the Epistemic Basing Relation. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Weinberg, J.M., Nichols, S. and Stich, S. (2001). ‘Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions.Philosophical Topics 29(1/2), 429–60. doi: 10.5840/philtopics2001291/217.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2007). The Philosophy of Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, L.T. (1996). Virtues of the Mind. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar