Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-mp689 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T10:20:37.841Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Phenomenal Intentionality and the Problem of Representation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 March 2016

WALTER OTT*
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY OF VIRGINIAwrottjr@gmail.com

Abstract:

According to the phenomenal intentionality research program, a state's intentional content is fixed by its phenomenal character. Defenders of this view have little to say about just how this grounding is accomplished. I argue that without a robust account of representation, the research program promises too little. Unfortunately, most of the well-developed accounts of representation—asymmetric dependence, teleosemantics, and the like—ground representation in external relations such as causation. Such accounts are inconsistent with the core of the phenomenal intentionality program. I argue that, however counterintuitive it may seem, the best prospect for explaining how phenomenal character represents is an appeal to resemblance.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aristotle. (1984) The Complete Works of Aristotle. Edited by Barnes, J.. 2 vols. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Burge, Tyler. (1986) ‘Cartesian Error and the Objectivity of Perception’. In Pettit, P. and McDowell, J. (eds.), Subject, Thought, and Context (Oxford: Clarendon Press), 117–36.Google Scholar
Descartes, René. (1984) The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Edited by Cottingham, John, Stoothoff, Robert, and Murdoch, Dugald. 3 vols. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred. (2002) ‘A Recipe for Thought’. In Chalmers, D. (ed.), Philosophy of Mind. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 491–99.Google Scholar
Farkas, Katalin. (2013) ‘Constructing a World for the Senses’. In Kriegel, Uriah (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 99115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. (1994) ‘A Theory of Content, II: The Theory’. In Stich, S. and Warfield, T. (eds.), Mental Representation: A Reader (London: Blackwell), 180220.Google Scholar
Gertler, Brie. (2013) ‘Understanding the Internalism-Externalism Debate: What is the Boundary of the Thinker?Philosophical Perspectives, 26, 5175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibson, James J. (1950) The Perception of the Visual World. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Goodman, Nelson. (1972) ‘Seven Strictures on Similarity’. In Goodman, Nelson, Problems and Projects (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett), 437–46.Google Scholar
Graham, George, Horgan, Terence, and Tienson, John. (2007) ‘Consciousness and Intentionality’. In Schneider, S. and Velmans, M. (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness (London: Blackwell), 468–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harnad, Stevan. (2005) ‘To Cognize is to Categorize’. In Cohen, Henri and Lefebvre, Claire (eds.), The Handbook of Categorization in Cognitive Science (New York: Elsevier), 2045.Google Scholar
Horgan, T., and Tienson, J.. (2002) ‘The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality’. In Chalmers, D. (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 520–33.Google Scholar
Isaac, Alistair. (2013) ‘Objective Similarity and Mental Representation’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91, 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobson, Anne Jaap. (2008) ‘What Should a Theory of Vision Look Like?Philosophical Psychology, 21, 641–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobson, Anne Jaap. (2013) Keeping the World in Mind. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kriegel, Uriah. (2011) Sources of Intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kriegel, Uriah, ed. (2013a) Phenomenal Intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kriegel, Uriah. (2013b) ‘The Phenomenal Intentionality Research Program.’ In Kriegel, U. (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lagerlund, Henrik. (2011) ‘Mental Representation in Medieval Philosophy.’ In Zalta, E. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University. Available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/representation-medieval/.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langsam, Harold. (2011) The Wonder of Consciousness. Boston, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, Rae, and Lewis, David. (1998) ‘Defining “Intrinsic”’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 333–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loar, Brian. (2003) ‘Phenomenal Intentionality as the Basis for Mental Content’. In Hahn, M. and Ramberg, B. (eds.), Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press), 229–58.Google Scholar
Lycan, William. (2009) ‘Giving Dualism its Due’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 87, 551–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John. (1998) Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Meyering, Theo C. (1989) Historical Roots of Cognitive Science. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth G. (1987) Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Montague, Michelle. (2013) ‘The Access Problem’. In Kriegel, U. (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 2748.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1903) ‘The Refutation of Idealism’. In Moore, G. E., Philosophical Studies (London: Routledge), 130.Google Scholar
Pautz, Adam. (2013) ‘Does Phenomenology Ground Mental Content?’ In Kriegel, U. (ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 194234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pitt, David. (2004) ‘The Phenomenology of Cognition, or, What is It Like to Think That P?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69, 136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pitt, David. (2009) ‘Intentional Psychologism’. Philosophical Studies, 146, 117–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. (1981) Reason, Truth, and History. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siewert, Charles. (1998) The Significance of Consciousness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swoyer, Chris. (1991) ‘Structural Representation and Surrogative Reasoning’. Synthese, 87, 449508.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swoyer, Chris. (1995) ‘Leibnizian Expression’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 33, 6599.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, Michael. (2000) Consciousness, Color, and Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watanabe, Satosi. (1969) Knowing and Guessing: A Quantitative Study of Inference and Information. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Watanabe, Satosi. (1985) Pattern Recognition: Human and Mechanical. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Watson, Richard. (1995) Representational Ideas from Plato to Patricia Churchland. New York: Springer.Google Scholar