Particle-free bodies and point-free spaces

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ijengsci.2013.06.002Get rights and content

Abstract

Few notions in mathematics and physics are as fundamental and useful as the notion of a “point”. However, in addition to the concept of a “point” being far from apparent, the concept is not suitable for describing several important problems in natural philosophy. A far more tangible and sensible idea that is immediately grasped by our mind is that of a “chunk” (a solid object) which seems ideally suited to describe precisely those problems which the notion of “point” seems to hinder. In this paper, I articulate the need for the use of topologies which are “point free” for the proper resolution of many important problems in natural philosophy.

Section snippets

Introductory remarks

I resisted the temptation to try and appear droll and title this work “Pointless bodies” as I remembered reading the witticism “A celebrated reviewer once described a certain paper (in a phrase which never actually saw publication in Mathematical Reviews) as being concerned with the study of ‘valueless measures on pointless spaces” in Johnstone’s article titled “The point of pointless bodies” (see Johnstone, 1983); I was apprehensive that this paper might suffer a review which actually sees

The need for point free topology to describe a body

The history of natural philosophy bears witness to the fact that the notion of a “point” was a contentious one. A “point” in mathematics is understood to habit an abstract space,11 while in the case of a “particle” it is supposed to lie in “physical space”. We first have to understand what is meant by an abstract mathematical space as well as what is meant by physical

Where the notion of a “point” hinders understanding certain problems of natural philosophy

Let us consider a few important problems in mechanics where the notion of a “point” comes in the way of clearly defining the problem and complicates issues rather than makes them tractable and amenable to meaningful analysis.

Philosophers have been interested in the question of the notion of a boundary, from the metaphysical as well as set theoretic point for a very long time. References to this literature can be found in the papers of Zimmerman, 1996a, Zimmerman, 1996b. Of interest to us here

Meaning of “point” in everyday usage

Most “definitions” of a “point” make a statement that articulates the following sentiment or meaning: “A point is a precise location in space, and it has no dimensions”. Such a “definition” is most unsatisfactory as it does not convey any meaning whatsoever. If a “point” has no dimensions, how are we to ascertain if it is indeed at some location in space? What does it mean to be in some location is space? What is the meaning of “location”? If we are to conceptualize a “point” as a “dot”,

The notion of a “point” in classical Euclidean Geometry

Contrary to popular perception amongst mathematicians, Euclid did not perceive a “point” as being an entity without dimension. In Heath’s authoritative translation of Euclid’s Elements we find the following definition of the notion of “point”45: Σημεῖóν ἐστιν, οῧ μέρος οὐθέν, which according to Heath means

Notion of points in mechanics

The earliest and simplest description of a body within the purview of mechanics is that of a particle, or more precisely a “point mass”, and much of the early studies in natural philosophy were devoted to the investigation of the motion of projectiles and planets within the context of such a description. While the mathematical notion of a point could be considered as an indispensable notion in mathematics, bereft of which it would be no exaggeration to say there would not be much point to

Abstract definitions of a body in continuum mechanics

The remarks of Fransescoe De Oviedo, that can be found in the translation that appears in “Discourse of things above reason” in the Selected Philosophical Papers of Robert Boyle, edited by Stewart, while somewhat harsh seems to have some merit even today, though most mathematicians will tend to view it as being without merit. Oviedo remarks (Stewart (1991)):

“We come to the composition of a continuum, whose hitherto unsurmounted difficulty has sorely taxed the wits of all the learned, and

Some concluding observations

I believe that it is necessary to use the language of point free topology if we are to describe certain problems of natural philosophy and resolve them satisfactorily. While there has been considerable effort in developing “point free” topology, there has been no effort in developing a Calculus where one can talk sensibly about the derivatives of functions that are defined on such topological spaces, the development of ordinary, partial differential and integral equations within such a

Acknowledgements

I thank Josef Malek, Dalibor Prazac, Vit Prusa, Miles Rubin, Brian Seguin, and Benjamin Vejnar for their input based on an earlier draft of the work. I thank the National Science Foundation for its support of my research for the past three decades that has allowed me to think about the issues discussed in this paper. I also thank the Office for Naval Research for support of this work. I also thank the Necas Center at the Charles University in Prague for its support over the years.

References (88)

  • R. Bacon

    Opus Majus, (1267), (The Opus Majus of Roger Bacon, Part 1, page 4, translated by Robert Belle Burke)

    (1928)
  • Barnes, J. (Ed.). (1995). The complete works of Aristotle (Vol. 1). Princeton: Princeton University...
  • Berkeley, G. (1710). A treatise containing the principles of human knowledge. Printed by Aaron Rhames, for Jeremy...
  • Berkeley, G. (1713). Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous in opposition to Sceptics and Atheists. In: C. W....
  • G.D. Birkhoff

    Lattice theory

    (1966)
  • A.I. Bobenko

    Discrete differential geometry

  • D. Bohm

    Causality and chance in modern physics

    (1957)
  • D. Bohm et al.

    The undivided universe

    (1993)
  • B. Bolzano

    Paradoxes of the infinite

    (1950)
  • R.G. Boscovich

    A theory of Natural Philosophy (tran. by J.M. Childs)

    (1966)
  • J. Boussinesq

    Application des Potentiels a L’etude de l’equilibre et due Mouvement des Solides Elastique

    (1885)
  • C. Boyer

    History of calculus

    (1959)
  • Bulicek, M., Malek, J., Rajagopal, K. R., & Walton, J. (2012). Existence of solution for anti-plane stress for a new...
  • J.M. Burgers

    Mechanical considerations model systems phenomenological theories of relaxation and viscosity

  • R. Cartwright
  • B.L. Clarke

    A calculus of individuals based on connection

    Notre Dame J. Formal Logic

    (1982)
  • W.K. Clifford

    On the space theory of matter

  • Clough, A. H. (Ed.). (1934). Plutarch, lives: Vol. 5. Modern library. New York [translated by John...
  • P.J. Cohen

    The independence of the continuum hypothesis

    Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA

    (1963)
  • P.J. Cohen

    The independence of the continuum hypothesis II

    Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA

    (1964)
  • R.G. Collingwood

    The idea of nature

    (1986)
  • Cosserat, E., & Cosserat, F. (1909). Theorie des corps deformables, Paris, Librairie Scientific A. Hermann et Fils....
  • S. DasGupta

    A history of Indian philosophy (in five volumes), Delhi, Varanasi, Patna: Motilal Banarsidas

    (1975)
  • T. de Laguna

    Point, line, and surface as sets of a solid

    Journal of Philosophy

    (1922)
  • T. de Laguna

    Nature of space – Part I

    Journal of Philosophy

    (1922)
  • T. de Laguna

    Nature of space – Part II

    Journal of Philosophy

    (1922)
  • J. Dryden

    The hind and the panther. A poem in three parts

    (1687)
  • Feller, W. 1950. An introduction to probability theory and its application (vol. 1). New York, London: John Wiley &...
  • Galilei, G. (1658). Discorzi e Dimostrazioni matematiche. (Translated by Henry Crew and Alfanso de Salvio), Dialogues...
  • G. Gerla et al.

    Geometry without points

    American Mathematical Monthly

    (1985)
  • Grzegorczyk, A. (1961). Axiomatizability of geometry without points. In Proceedings of the colloquium at Utrecht,...
  • A. Grunbaum

    A consistent conception of the linear extended continuum as an aggregate of unextended elements

    Philosophy of Science

    (1952)
  • T.L. Heath
    (1921)
  • E.V. Huntington

    A set of postulates for abstract geometry exposed in terms of the simple relation of inclusion

    Mathematische Annalen

    (1916)
  • P.T. Johnstone

    The point of pointless bodies

    Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society

    (1983)
  • Johnstone, P. T., (1991). The art of pointless thinking: a student’s guide to the category of locales. In Proc....
  • P.T. Johnstone

    Elements of the history of locale theory

  • P.T. Johnstone

    Stone spaces, cambridge studies in advanced mathematics

    (1982)
  • M. Kline

    Mathematics, the loss of certainty

    (1980)
  • V. Kulvait et al.

    Anti-plane stress for a plate with V-notch for a new class of elastic solids

    International Journal of Fracture

    (2013)
  • Laplace, S. P. (1951). (Essai Philosophique sur les Probabilités, Mme Ve Courcier, Imprimeur-Libraire pour les...
  • S. MacLane et al.

    Algebra

    (1967)
  • J.C.C. McKinsey et al.

    The algebra of topology

    Annals of Mathematics

    (1944)
  • J.C.C. McKinsey et al.

    On closed elements in closure algebras

    Annals of Mathematics

    (1946)
  • Cited by (6)

    • Developing improved mathematical models of aortic mechanics

      2024, Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery
    • Remarks on the notion of "pressure"

      2015, International Journal of Non-Linear Mechanics
    • A note on the classification of anisotropy of bodies defined by implicit constitutive relations

      2015, Mechanics Research Communications
      Citation Excerpt :

      Such bodies have been defined at various levels of abstraction (see [5–8,18,9]), but all these definitions share one common structure, namely the topological spaces are populated by entities that we refer to as “points”, that is the topology that is used is the traditional “point set topology”. However, as pointed out recently by Rajagopal [15] there are several problems in natural philosophy wherein the notion of a “point” comes in the way of describing the problem and in resolving them, which could possibly be dealt with within the context of a topology without points. We shall not get into a discussion of these issues here.

    • A thermodynamic basis for the derivation of the Darcy, Forchheimer and Brinkman models for flows through porous media and their generalizations

      2014, International Journal of Non-Linear Mechanics
      Citation Excerpt :

      We cannot get into these sorts of issues here. In a recent paper, Rajagopal [26] outlines the difficulties that are inherent with the notion of “points” in mathematics and particles in mechanics and hence the difficulty with regard to even defining what is meant by distance between “points”. Ideally, we ought to assume that in a rigid body, the Helmholtz potential is a constant.

    • Lecture notes in engineering: Introduction to linearized elasticity

      2023, Lecture Notes in Engineering: Introduction to Linearized Elasticity
    • A remark on the conception of a body in continuum mechanics

      2015, Mathematics and Mechanics of Solids

    This paper delves into the notion of a “point” as it pertains to its usage in mathematics; it, whatever “it” is has “position but no magnitude”. However, the word is also used in another sense, namely as “essential or indispensable”. This paper is dedicated to Chandrika who is the “point” to my life, in this latter sense of its usage.

    View full text