Elsevier

Economics Letters

Volume 70, Issue 1, January 2001, Pages 95-98
Economics Letters

Pareto principles from Inch to Ell

https://doi.org/10.1016/S0165-1765(00)00339-6Get rights and content

Abstract

Under mild conditions including the possibility of compensation by monetary transfer, this paper shows that all versions of the Pareto Principle, viz., the Pareto Indifference, the Weak Pareto, the Strong Pareto, and the Full Pareto, are in fact mutually equivalent.

Introduction

Consider a society with n individuals, where 2 ≤ n<+∞. Let R=(R1, R2,…, Rn) denote the profile of individual preference orderings on the set X of all social states such that, for all social states x, yX, xRiy means that x is at least as good as y according to i’s personal judgements. R denotes the social welfare ordering corresponding to R.

In the literature of Paretian welfare economics and social choice theory, one or the other of the following versions of the Pareto principle plays an important role.1


Pareto Indifference Principle

 If xI(Ri)y holds for all iN:={1, 2,…, n}, then xI(R)y holds.


Weak Pareto Principle

 If xP(Ri)y holds for all iN, then xP(R)y holds.


Strong Pareto Principle

 If xRiy holds for all iN and xP(Rj)y holds for at least one jN, then xP(R)y holds.


Full Pareto Principle

 The Strong Pareto as well as the Pareto Indifference holds.

By their very definitions, it is obvious that the Full Pareto implies the Strong Pareto and the Pareto Indifference, whereas the Strong Pareto implies the Weak Pareto. In general, this is all we can assert about the logical relations which hold among these Pareto principles. It is shown in this note, however, that all these Pareto principles are in fact mutually equivalent under several mild conditions including the possibility of compensation, which are standardly assumed in the literature on fair allocations with indivisible commodities.

Section snippets

An equivalence theorem

Suppose that the set X has the following decomposable structure: X:=En×Ω, where E is the set of real numbers, whereas Ω is the set whose structure need not be specified any further. The intended interpretation is that there exists an infinitesimally divisible good, and each and every social state xX is described by specifying the amount of this divisible good accruing to each and every individual, e:=(e1, e2,…, en)∈ En, and the other features of the world which is captured by ω∈Ω.

Assumption (i)

Each and

A remark on the possibility of compensation

Among the assumptions which support the validity of the equivalence theorem, the only one which may seem strong is that of the possibility of compensation, viz., the Assumption (iii). Note, however, that this assumption is in fact standardly invoked in the literature on fair allocations with indivisible goods. See Alkan et al. (1991) and Tadenuma and Thomson (1991). It is also worth pointing out that this assumption is indispensable for the validity of the equivalence theorem. We have only to

Acknowledgements

This research was completed while I was visiting the Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Sciences, the London School of Economics, UK. I am grateful to the warm hospitality and research facilities provided by the Centre. Thanks are also due to Professors Claude d’Aspremont, Louis Gevers, Michel Le Breton, Amartya K. Sen, Koichi Tadenuma, and Yongsheng Xu for their helpful comments and discussions. Needless to say, they should not be held responsible for any defect that may remain.

References (2)

  • A. Alkan et al.

    Fair allocation of indivisible goods and criteria of justice

    Econometrica

    (1991)
  • K. Tadenuma et al.

    No-envy and consistency in economies with indivisible goods

    Econometrica

    (1991)

Cited by (11)

  • When is weak Pareto equivalent to strong Pareto?

    2023, Economics Letters
    Citation Excerpt :

    Blackorby et al. (2005) provide a synthesis of the welfarist approach to welfare comparisons. Suzumura (2001) proves the equivalence of various Paretian axioms. Since his result includes a condition under which weak Pareto implies strong Pareto, we briefly discuss a relation to Suzumura’s framework.

  • Collective choice rules with social maximality

    2022, Journal of Mathematical Economics
  • Is the preference of the majority representative ?

    2021, Mathematical Social Sciences
  • Kaplow–Shavell welfarism without continuity

    2018, Mathematical Social Sciences
    Citation Excerpt :

    Section 5 concludes with some discussions. In a similar but slightly different context, Suzumura (2001) has defended his assumption, which he refers as Assumption (iii), that there is a continuous good that can be used for compensation. He said this assumption is the standard assumption in the literature of fair allocations.

  • On the impossibility of complete Non-Interference in Paretian social judgements

    2013, Journal of Economic Theory
    Citation Excerpt :

    Kaplow and Shavell [7] (see also the subsequent debate in Fleurbaey, Tungodden and Chang [6] and Kaplow and Shavell [8]) have highlighted a striking impossibility result: any non-welfaristic method of social evaluation (such as ‘the punishment must fit the crime’) leads to a violation of the Pareto principle. Related results have also been discussed by Campbell [3] and Suzumura [19]. These results suggest that the search for acceptable methods of social judgement ought to take place in a welfaristic framework.

  • Welfarism, Individual Rights, and Procedural Fairness

    2011, Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare
View all citing articles on Scopus
View full text