Skip to main content
Log in

Masahiko Aoki’s conception of institutions

  • Article
  • Published:
Evolutionary and Institutional Economics Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The present study examines Masahiko Aoki’s continual attempts to conceptualize institutions, with main focus on Aoki (Toward a comparative institutional analysis. MIT Press, Cambridge, 2001; J Econ Behav Organ, 79:20–34, 2011). The unique aspect of his approach is identified as his efforts to grasp the dynamic and collective-cognitive nature of institutions. Highly valuing this uniqueness, I identified several difficulties in this approach. In this study, I argue that the profound nature of institutions is beyond the formal description of game theory, which Aoki maintained in his lifetime. I also argue that the Hegelian perspective submitted by Herrmann-Pillath and Boldyrev (Hegel, institutions and economics: performing the social. Routledge, London, 2014) suggests a possible future direction of the research on institutions in economics, albeit not necessarily one amenable to mathematical formulation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The reason that game theory is helpful for understanding institutional phenomena is that the formal definition of games has a strong expressive power—it allows us to model fine details of asymmetric information, give predictions of the observed regularity of behavior, and understand the role of belief in sustaining the equilibrium behavior.

  2. Hodgson (2015) correctly points out that the task of defining institutions is conceptually different from the task of understanding or analyzing them. Searle (2015) warns us that we must be careful when we ask questions of the form “what is…?” With these precautions in mind, I take up this subject matter, because I believe that how we conceptualize institutions is important, as it directs our research, by defining what kind of phenomena we regard as important and want to understand.

  3. Whereas Aoki (2010) tries to understand and exposit the evolving diversity of corporations and is also relevant, the idea presented there is basically the same as in Aoki (2011).

  4. “Internalism” here refers to a stance in the philosophy of mind that regards actions as external phenomena to be explained by resorting to internal determinants, such as preferences and beliefs, whereas “externalism” grasps the workings of a mind more broadly, and thus emphasizes the interaction between brain, body, and external environments.

  5. This is the aspect embraced by Hindriks and Guala’s (2015) “rules-in-equilibrium” account of institutions, as we will see later in Sect. 3. Chapter 7 of Aoki (2001) is devoted to the elaboration of this view.

  6. Aoki recommended both of these books for Japanese translation and they were translated and published in Japanese.

  7. Lewis’s definition of proper equilibrium is the same as what we usually call “strict equilibrium”; he calls a strategy combination “a proper equilibrium if each agent likes it better than any other combination he could have reached, given the others’ choices” (Lewis 1969, p. 22).

  8. A meet is the finest common coarsening of agents’ information partitions.

  9. Aoki’s stance towards rigorous formulation is somewhat ambivalent. On the one hand, he writes “I rely mainly on game-theoretic language and frame of thought with liberal re-interpretations” (Aoki 2011, p. 21). On the other hand, mentions his conception of institutions “using rigorous set-theoretic notions” (Aoki 2015, p. 486).

  10. To quote, “[o]ne of the basic ideas in the book was that the essence of psychological process and knowledge as its outcome lies in the ‘classifications’ of perceived physical events in one way or another through the network of neurons. The formalization of the idea of classification is precisely at the basis of the notion of common knowledge in the contemporary theory of knowledge” (Aoki 2011, p. 24).

  11. Intentionality is a technical term in philosophy that denotes “aboutness” or “directedness” of the mind and/or linguistic expressions. For example, we cannot believe something without any object to be believed. Those states of mind are called “intentional states.” “Collective intentionality” means that we have common intentionality.

  12. In footnote 14 of their paper, they write “the reducibility of collective to individual intentions is a thorny issue in the philosophy of action.” However, they proceed by saying “it is perfectly possible to discuss the relation between the rules-in-equilibrium and constitutive rules approach while remaining neutral on this matter” (Hindriks and Guala 2015, p. 471).

  13. Recall North’s definition of institutions: “In the jargon of the economist, institutions define and limit the set of choices of individuals” (North 1990, p. 4).

  14. Sugden (2015) does not appreciate Hindriks and Guala’s or Aoki’s efforts to incorporate representation in the conception of institutions, contending that the regularities of behavior and affective response explained by evolutionary game theory are sufficient as a scientific explanation of conventions.

  15. To quote, “Just as instinct is older than custom and tradition, so then are the latter older than reason: custom and tradition stand between instinct and reason” (Hayek 1991, p. 23).

  16. In the expressivist view, actions are primary facts and therefore cannot be ontologically separated from their causes/intentions. Rather, actors are engaged in reflective activities, always discovering their own intentions related to their action.

  17. Herrmann-Pillath and Boldyrev (2014, Ch. 3) attempt at applying their approach to a reconsideration of money, given new historical evidence that money did not emerge to save transaction cost in a barter economy.

References

  • Akerlof G (1970) The market for “Lemons”: quality uncertainty and the market mechanism. Q J Econ 84:488–500

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aoki M (2001) Toward a comparative institutional analysis. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Aoki M (2007) Endogenizing institutions and institutional change. J Instit Econ 3:1–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aoki M (2010) Corporations in evolving diversity: cognition, governance and institutions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aoki M (2011) Institutions as cognitive media between strategic interactions and individual beliefs. J Econ Behav Organ 79:20–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aoki M (2015) Why is the equilibrium notion essential for a united institutional theory? a friendly remark on the article by Hindriks and Guala. J Inst Econ 11:485–488

    Google Scholar 

  • Aumann R (1976) Agreeing to disagree. Ann Stat 4:1236–1239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aumann R, Brandenburger A (1995) Epistemic conditions for Nash equilibrium. Econometrica 63:1161–1180

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997) Being there: putting brain, body, and world together again. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Denzau A, North D (1994) Shared mental models: ideologies and institutions. Kyklos 47:3–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fukuyama F (2011) Origins of political order: from prehuman times to the french revolution, 1st edn. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York (paperback)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gintis H (2009) The bounds of reason. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Greif A (1994) Cultural beliefs and the organization of society: a historical and theoretical reflection on collectivist and individualist societies. J Polit Econ 102:912–950

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA (1952) The sensory order: an inquiry into the foundations of theoretical psychology. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA (1991) The fatal conceit: the errors of socialism. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath J (2008) Following the rules: practical reasoning and deontic constraint. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann-Pillath C, Boldyrev I (2014) Hegel, institutions and economics: performing the social. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hindriks F, Guala F (2015) Institutions, rules, and equilibria: a unified theory. J Instit Econ 11:459–480

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson G (2015) On defining institutions: rules versus equilibria. J Instit Econ 11:497–505

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1969) Convention: a philosophical study. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • McMillan J (2002) Reinventing the bazaar: a natural history of markets. W.W. Norton & Co, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • North D (1990) Institutions, institutional change and economic performance. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1966) The tacit dimension. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Schotter A (1981) The economic theory of social institutions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1995) The construction of social reality. Allen Lane, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1998) Mind, language and society. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (2001) Rationality in action. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (2005) What is an institution? J Inst Econ 1:1–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (2015) Status functions and institutional facts: reply to Hindriks and Guala. J Inst Econ 11:507–514

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimojo S (2008) Subliminal impact (in Japanese). Chikuma-shinsho, Tokyo

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith A (1759/1976) The theory of moral sentiments. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Smith A (1776/1991) The wealth of nations. Prometheus Book, Buffalo

  • Sugden R (2015) On ‘Common Sense Ontology’: a comment on the paper by Frank Hindriks and Francesco Guala. J Inst Econ 11:489–492

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (2009) Why we cooperate. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hirokazu Takizawa.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author states that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

The author is grateful to Carsten Herrmann-Pillath for invaluable discussions on Professor Aoki’s approach to institutions. Thanks also go to the attendees of the session commemorating Masahiko Aoki at the Annual Meeting of Japan Association for Evolutionary Economics, March 26–27, 2016, Tokyo. This study was supported by JSPS Kakenhi Grant Number 16K03557 and the MEXT-Supported Program for the Strategic Research Foundation at Private Universities 2013–2017.

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Takizawa, H. Masahiko Aoki’s conception of institutions. Evolut Inst Econ Rev 14, 523–540 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40844-017-0087-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40844-017-0087-0

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation