Skip to main content
Log in

The Direct-Perception Model of Empathy: a Critique

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper assesses the so-called “direct-perception” model of empathy. This model draws much of its inspiration from the Phenomenological tradition: it is offered as an account free from the assumption that most, if not all, of another’s psychological states and experiences are unobservable and that one’s understanding of another’s psychological states and experiences are based on inferential processes. Advocates of this model also reject the simulation-based approach to empathy. I first argue that most of their criticisms miss their target because they are directed against the simulation-based approach to mindreading. Advocates of this model further subscribe to an expressivist conception of human behavior and assume that some of an individual’s psychological states (e.g. her goals and emotions, not her beliefs) can be directly perceived in the individual’s expressive behavior. I argue that advocates of the direct-perception model face the following dilemma: either they embrace behaviorism or else they must recognize that one could not understand another’s goal or emotion from her behavior alone without making contextual assumptions. Finally, advocates of the direct-perception model endorse the narrative competency hypothesis, according to which the ability to ascribe beliefs to another is grounded in the ability to understand narratives. I argue that this hypothesis is hard to reconcile with recent results in developmental psychology showing that preverbal human infants seem able to ascribe false beliefs to others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For the historical background, cf. Stueber (2008).

  2. What I call “the direct-perception model of empathy” combines assumptions, some of which are held by Gallagher (2008a) and others by Zahavi (2007, 2008).

  3. Cf. Gallagher (2001, 2004, 2008a, b).

  4. Whereas Zahavi (2001, 2007, 2008) seems to subscribe to the direct-perception model of both primary intersubjectivity in the broad sense and empathy, Gallagher (2001, 2004, 2007, 2008a, b) seems to subscribe only to the direct-perception model of primary intersubjectivity in the broad sense. Both stress the fact that primary intersubjectivity in the broad sense underlies social understanding based on everyday encounters (or interactions) with others.

  5. Acceptance of assumption (3) is characteristic of the direct-perception model of empathy. Acceptance of assumption (3) depends in part on the terminological decision to identify empathetic understanding with understanding generated by basic intersubjectivity. As I mentioned above, Zahavi (2007, 2008) explicitly endorses assumption (3). Deprived of assumption (3), the direct-perception model applies to basic intersubjectivity.

  6. For further evidence about modulation of empathetic responses, cf. Decety et al. 2011; Lamm et al. 2007, 2009.

  7. In order to meet the five conditions above, de Vignemont and Jacob (submitted) endorse an E-imagination based account of empathetic pain, which contrasts with both mirroring-based and hybrid accounts.

  8. Furthermore, on the pretense-theoretic version of the simulation account of the prediction of another’s decision, a mindreader uses her own decision-mechanism to run the simulation routine by giving it pretend inputs (i.e. representations of the other’s beliefs, desires and intentions). As a result, the mindreader’s decision mechanism generates a pretend output (i.e. a pretend decision). But if the problem of the pretend inputs can be solved, then why is the simulation routine needed after all?

  9. Although I do not agree either with his defense of Goldman’s simulation-based approach to mindreading or with each of his criticisms of Gallagher’s arguments against simulation-based approaches to mindreading, I have learnt a great deal from Barlassina’s (2010) paper presented at Institut Jean Nicod in the Spring of 2010 and subsequent discussions.

  10. For further discussion, see Jacob (2008b).

  11. Bogdan (1997: 104), whom Hutto credits for coining the expression, defines the “spectatorial” stance as portraying “the subject as a remote object of observation and prediction.”

  12. It may look awkward that a phenomenological approach to understanding others is open to the charge of behaviorism. But it is.

  13. Arguably, there are some differences between an agent’s goal-directed and an agent’s expressive behavior. But the argument could easily be run in terms of an agent’s expressive behavior.

  14. Fogassi et al. (2005) recorded the activity of single cells in area IPL of macaque monkeys in both executive and observational tasks of grasping a target. Iacoboni et al. (2005) showed human participants video-clips of actions of grasping a cup either within or outside a context. Cattaneo et al. (2007) recorded and compared the electromyographic (EMG) activity respectively in typically developing children and in children with autism, in both executive and observational tasks of grasping a target.

  15. For a good instance of the oscillation between the weaker and the stronger version of the narrative competency hypothesis, cf. Hutto (2008b: 178), who argues that it is incompatible with either simulation-based or theory-theory approaches to mindreading and nonetheless recognizes that “narratives do crucially important but nonetheless limited work. They are not responsible for introducing an understanding of mental concepts, such as desire and belief for the first time, rather, being complex linguistic representations of particular events, they put on show how these attitudes can integrate with one another (and also how they fit with other mental states and stand with respect to other contextual factors) […] kids already have a practical grasp on what it is to have a desire or belief before learning how to integrate their discrete understanding of these concepts in making sense of actions in terms of reasons […] Through shared encounters with [FP] narratives children become familiar with the forms and norms of giving and asking for reasons, knowing how and when these apply. In this way they develop the capacity to give and receive reason explanations, as and when required.”

  16. Cf. Call and Tomasello (2008).

  17. Sometimes, as noted by Herschbach (2008), advocates of the narrative competency hypothesis seem to take the view that the assumption that an agent’s psychological state is “hidden” (an assumption jointly accepted by simulation-based and theory-theory based approaches to mindreading) is appropriate “in those rare cases when we encounter puzzling behavior” such as an agent’s action based on a false belief (cf. Gallagher 2007: 354 and Zahavi 2008: 515). But human actions based on false beliefs are far from unusual.

  18. For a recent extensive review, cf. Caron (2009).

  19. In another VOE study, Surian et al. (2007) reported that 13-month-olds looked longer when a caterpillar approached the true location of its preferred food, when the food has been hidden there in the absence of the caterpillar. In still another VOE study, He and Baillargeon (2010) report that 11-month-olds looked reliably longer when an agent, who had not seen the shortening of the length of a toy, retrieved the toy from the shorter of a pair of boxes when only the other box would have been large enough to contain the toy before it was shortened in the agent’s absence.

References

  • Aviezer, H., R.R. Hassin, J. Ryan, C. Grady, J. Susskind, A. Anderson, M. Moscovitch, and S. Bentin. 2008. Angry, disgusted, or afraid? Studies on the malleability of emotion perception. Psychological Science 19(7): 724–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., R.M. Scott, and Z. He. 2010. False-belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14(3): 110–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. 1995. Mindblindness, an essay on autism and theory of mind. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barlassina, L. 2010. Sticking to simulation or why Gallagher’s arguments don’t refute Goldman’s theory of mindreading. Paper presented at Institut Jean Nicod, Spring 2010.

  • Bloom, P., and T. German. 2000. Two reasons to abandon the false belief task as a test of theory of mind. Cognition 77: B25–B31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogdan, R. 1997. Interpreting minds: The evolution of a practice. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Call, J., and M. Tomasello. 2008. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12(5): 187–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caron, A.J. 2009. Comprehension of the representational mind in infancy. Developmental Review 29: 69–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cattaneo, L., M. Fabbri-Destro, S. Boria, C. Pieraccini, A. Monti, G. Cossu, and G. Rizzolatti. 2007. Impairment of actions chains in autism and its possible role in intention understanding. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 104(45): 17825–17830.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csibra, G. 2007. Action mirroring and action understanding. In Sensorimotor foundations of higher cognition. Attention and performance XXII, ed. P. Haggard, Y. Rossetti, and M. Kawato. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dailey, M.N., G.W. Cotrell, C. Padgett, and R. Adolphs. 2002. EMPATH: a neural network that categorizes facial expressions. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 14(8): 1158–1173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Decety, J., Echols, S. and Correll, J. 2011. The Blame Game: The Effect of Responsibility and Social Stigma on Empathy for Pain. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience.

  • de Vignemont, F. and Jacob, P. submitted. What is it like to feel another’s pain?

  • Fogassi, L., P.F. Ferrari, B. Gesierich, S. Rozzi, F. Chersi, and G. Rizzolatti. 2005. Parietal lobe: from action organization to intention understanding. Science 308: 662–667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freedberg, D., and V. Gallese. 2007. Motion, emotion and empathy in esthetic experience. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11: 197–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2001. The practice of mind, theory, simulation or primary interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 83–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2004. Hermeneutics and the cognitive sciences. Journal of Consciousness Studies 11: 10–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2007. Simulation trouble. Social Neuroscience 2(3–4): 353–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2008a. Direct perception in the intersubjective context. Consciousness and Cognition 17: 535–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2008b. Understanding others: embodied social cognition. In Handbook of cognitive science: An embodied approach, eds. P. Calvo, and A. Gomila. Academic Press.

  • Gallagher, S. in press. Empathy, simulation, and narrative.

  • Gallagher, S., and D. Hutto. 2008. Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity, ed. J. Zlatev, T.P. Racine, C. Sinha, and E. Itkonen, 17–38. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. 2001. The ‘shared manifold’ hypothesis, from mirror neurons to empathy. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 33–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., and A.I. Goldman. 1998. Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mindreading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12: 493–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., C. Keysers, and G. Rizzolatti. 2004. A unifying view of the basis of social cognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8(9): 396–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I. 2006. Simulating minds, the philosophy, psychology and neuroscience of mindreading. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I. 2011. Two routes to empathy, insights from cognitive neuroscience. In Empathy: Philosophical and psychological perspectives, ed. A. Coplan and P. Goldie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • He, Z., and R. Baillargeon. 2010. False-belief understanding in 11-month-old infants. Manuscript in preparation.

  • Herschbach, M. 2008. False-belief understanding and the Phenomenological critics of folk psychology. Journal of Consciousness Studies 15(12): 33–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D.D. 2004. The limits of spectatorial folk psychology. Mind and Language 19(5): 548–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D.D. 2008a. Folk psychological narratives: The sociocultural basis of understanding reasons. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D.D. 2008b. The narrative practice hypothesis: clarifications and implications. Philosophical Explorations 11(3): 175–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iacoboni, M., I. Molnar-Szakacs, V. Gallese, G. Buccino, J.C. Mazziotta, and G. Rizzolatti. 2005. Grasping the intentions of others with one’s own mirror neuron system. PLoS Biology 3: 529–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. 2008a. What do mirror neurons contribute to human social cognition? Mind and Language 23(2): 190–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. 2008b. The scope and limits of enactive approaches to visual experience. Perception 37(3): 446–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. 2009. The tuning-fork model of social cognition: a critique. Consciousness and Cognition 18(1): 229–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamm, C., H.C. Nusbaum, A.N. Meltzoff, and J. Decety. 2007. What are you feeling? Using functional magnetic resonance imaging to assess the modulation of sensory and affective responses during empathy for pain. PLoS One. 212: e1292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamm, C., A.N. Meltzoff, and J. Decety. 2009. How do we empathize with someone who is not like us? A functional magnetic resonance imaging study. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 22(2): 362–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. 2000. “Theory of Mind” as a mechanism of selective attention. In The new cognitive neurosciences, ed. M.S. Gazzaniga. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. 2005. Developmental parallels in understanding minds and bodies. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9(10): 459–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meeren, H.K., C.C. Heijnsbergen, and B. de Gelder. 2005. Rapid perceptual integration of facial expression and emotional body language. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA 102: 16518–16523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. 2004. Action in perception. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onishi, K.H., and R. Baillargeon. 2005. Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science 308(5719): 255–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Reagan, K., and A. Noë. 2001. A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24: 939–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., and L. Craighero. 2005. Mirror neuron: a neurological approach to empathy. In Neurobiology of human value, ed. J.-P. Changeux et al. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., and C. Sinigaglia. 2008. Mirrors in the brain: How our minds share actions and emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., L. Fogassi, and V. Gallese. 2001. Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the understanding and imitation of action. Nature Review Neuroscience 2: 661–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. 1954. The nature of sympathy. Trans. P. Heath. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  • Singer, T., B. Seymour, J. O’Doherty, K.E. Stephan, R.J. Dolan, and C.D. Frith. 2006. Empathic neural responses are modulated by the perceived fairness of others. Nature 439: 466–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Southgate, V., A. Senju, and G. Csibra. 2007. Action anticipation through attribution of false belief by 2-year-olds. Psychological Science 18(7): 587–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stueber, K. 2008. Empathy. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/empathy.

  • Surian, L., S. Caldi, and D. Sperber. 2007. Attribution of beliefs by 13- month-old infants. Psychological Science 18: 580–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C.B. 1979. Communication and cooperation in early infancy: a description of primary intersubjectivity. In Before speech, ed. M. Bullowa, 321–347. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wicker, B., C. Keysers, J. Plailly, J.-P. Royet, V. Gallese, and G. Rizzolatti. 2003. Both of us disgusted in my insula: the common neural basis of seeing and feeling disgust. Neuron 40: 655–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 2001. Beyond empathy, phenomenological approaches to intersubjectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 151–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 2007. Expression and empathy. In Folk psychology re-assessed, ed. D.D. Hutto and M. Ratcliffe, 25–40. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 2008. Simulation, projection and empathy. Consciousness and Cognition 17: 514–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierre Jacob.

Additional information

I am grateful to Gyury Gergely for inviting me to the International Conference on Intersubjectivity and the Self, Marie Curie DISCOS Project, in Budapest (June 2010), where a version of this paper was presented. I am grateful to Shaun Gallagher and Dan Zahavi for their oral and written responses to the paper and to Dan Hutto for inviting me to contribute a paper to the present special issue of RPP and for his own comments on the paper. Thanks also to Frédérique de Vignemont for numerous discussions on this topic. I gratefully acknowledge support of a grant from the French ministry of research (ANR-BLAN SOCODEV). I dedicate this paper to the memory of my friend Marc Jeannerod, who died on July 1st, 2011.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Jacob, P. The Direct-Perception Model of Empathy: a Critique. Rev.Phil.Psych. 2, 519–540 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0065-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0065-0

Keywords

Navigation