Skip to main content
Log in

Taking the Relational Turn: Biosemiotics and Some New Trends in Biology

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A cluster of similar trends emerging in separate fields of science and philosophy points to new opportunities to apply biosemiotic ideas as tools for conceptual integration in theoretical biology. I characterize these developments as the outcome of a “relational turn” in these disciplines. They signal a shift of attention away from objects and things and towards relational structures and processes. Increasingly sophisticated research technologies of molecular biology have generated an enormous quantity of experimental data, sparking a need for relational approaches that could help to find recurrent patterns in the mass of data. Earlier conceptions of relational biology and cybernetics, once deemed too abstract and speculative, are now resurrected and applied by means of new computational and simulation tools. I think this receptivity should be extended to incorporate nets of semiotic relations as heuristic guides for discerning global patterns of interactions in living systems. In this article I review aspects of systems biology and new directions in evolutionary theory, focusing on the role of circular and downward causation in relational structures and dynamical networks. I also indicate promising avenues of integration of some ideas of biosemiotics with those emerging from these new currents in biology. Relational developments in biology bear a telling similarity to a parallel relational turn presently manifest in the philosophy of science, rooted in the philosophy of physics and mathematics and in different varieties of structural and informational realism. The recognition of the relational nature of reality within these disciplines entails a tacit repudiation of nominalistic biases in science that have hindered the reception of semitiotic conceptions in biology. In previous investigations I explored connections between two kinds of relational structures: the networks of self-referential circular loops that appear pervasively in living systems, and the triadic relational structures that Peircean semiotics places at the basis of all semiotic transactions. Current relational views in the sciences seem oblivious to the difference between dyadic and triadic relations. Incorporating this essential distinction from biosemiotics into other fields could be a first step in seizing the opportunities opened by the relational turn for a renewal of biology and of natural philosophy in general, across disciplinary boundaries.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Several recent monographs review the basic ideas and methods of systems biology, with different philosophical biases (see e.g. Kitano 2001, Konopka 2007, and Rigoutsos and Stephanopoulos 2007). Denis Noble’s The Music of Life: Biology beyond the Genome is a very readable non-technical introduction and eloquent manifesto (Noble 2006).

  2. Philosophical issues concerning special forms of causation in living systems underlie the systems approach. Recent analyses and key references concerning top-down causation can be found in Auletta et al. 2009. Mossio et al. 2009 offer a review and a new analysis of the relation of Rosen’s conception of “closure to efficient causation” and the issue of computability, backed by an extensive bibliography.

  3. Structural realism encompasses a group of related positions in the philosophy of science that coincide in emphasizing the role of relational structures, both in nature and in our theories about nature, updating and reassessing the arguments of some 19th and 20th century thinkers, such as Poincaré, Duhem, Weyl and Cassirer, whose ideas are closely associated with the importance of focusing on relational notions. Current debates about structural realism stem from a seminal article by Worrall (Worrall 1989). An excellent review of issues and positions is given in Ladyman 2009. An important form of structural realism of special interest for biosemiotics is presented in Floridi 2008. Fernández 2008 considers other issues relating Peirce’s philosophy, structural realism and biosemiotics.

  4. Category theory was incipiently applied by Robert Rosen in his earlier versions of relational biology. A recent introduction to the subject with possible applications to biology can be found in Ellerman 2007. Further discussions on the possible role of these and related mathematical notions in the structure of systems biology are presented in Bailly and Longo 2006.

  5. There are several interpretations of quantum mechanics that fall under this rubric. They have diverse origins but they seem to converge into the same basic idea for overcoming the interpretational problems of the theory: subordination of the notion of objects to that of relational systems. Physical states exist only in relation to other states, including that of the “observer” (which does not need to be a human being or even an organism). A recent review by two prominent advocates is given in Laudisa and Rovelli 2008.

  6. In ecosystems the circuits of nutrients, energy and other transports are usually depicted as trophic networks, or separated following the major cycles (nitrogen, carbon, water), or as global processes, such as primary production and respiration. At present many authors postulate a global time directionality impressed by an ultimate thermodynamic constraint, the maximization of entropy production (see e.g. Ulanowicz 2004, Kleidon 2009, and Trefil et al. 2009).

  7. Under the heading of “Peirce’s modal shift” Robert Lane analyzes in detail the tangled interconnections of these issues in Peirce’s later thought. See Lane 2007.

  8. In a review of Meyerson’s La déduction relativiste Einstein praises the author because he rightly insists “... on the error of many expositions of relativity which refer to the ‘spatialization of time’. Time and space are fused in one and the same continuum, but the continuum is not isotropic. The element of spatial distance and the element of duration remain distinct in nature…The tendency he denounces, although often latent, is nonetheless real and profound in the mind of the physicist, as is unequivocally shown by the extravagances of the popularizers and even of many scientists in their expositions of relativity.” (Einstein in 1928, cited by Stachel 2007).

  9. Peirce refers implicitly on several occasions to the self-referential nature of semiosis but I have not been able to find any explicit articulation of this important issue. The most explicit declaration I have come across reads: “The same form of distinction [as that of immediate and dynamical object] extends to the interpretant; but as applied to the interpretant, it is complicated by the circumstance that the sign not only determines the interpretant to represent (or take the form of) the object , but also determines the interpretant to represent the sign. Indeed in what we may, from a point of view, regard as the principal kind of signs [dicisigns], there is one distinct part appropriated for representing the object, and another for representing how this very sign itself represents that object [my emphasis].” (From a 1906 letter to Lady Welby, included in Peirce 1998, 477–478).

References

  • Auletta, G., Ellis, G. F. R., & Jaeger, L. (2009). Top-down causation by information control: from a philosophical problem to a scientific research problem. J R Soc Interface, 5, 1159–1172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bailly, F., & Longo, G. (2006). Mathématiques et sciences de la nature: La singularité physique du vivant. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernot, G., Comet, J.-P., Richard, A., & Guespin, J. (2004). Application of formal methods to biological regulatory networks: extending Thomas asynchronous logical approach with temporal logic. J Theor Biol, 229(3), 339–347.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • von Bertalanffy, L. (1950). The theory of open systems in physics and biology. Science, 111(2872), 23–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1928). A propos de la déduction relativiste de M. Emile Meyerson. Revue Philosophique, 105, 161–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellerman, D. (2007). Adjoints and emergence: applications of a new theory of adjoint functors. Axiomathes, 17, 19–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernandez, E. (2008). Peirce in 21st century science and philosophy: New prospects. Terceras Jornadas “Peirce en Argentina”, Buenos Aires, September 11–12, 2008. Available at http://www.lindahall.org/services/reference/papers/fernandez/P_en_A_English.pdf

  • Floridi, L. (2008). A defense of informational structural realism. Synthese, 161(2), 219–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Funkenstein, A. (1975). Descartes, eternal truths and the divine omnipotence. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part A, 6(3), 185–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Funkenstein, A. (1986). Theology and the scientific imagination from the míddle ages to the seventeenth century. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goudsmit, A. L. (2007). Some reflections on Rosen’s conceptions of semantics and finality. Chem Biodivers, 4, 2427–2435.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Goudsmit, A. L. (2009). Sense and self-referentiality in living beings. Biosemiotics, 2(1), 39–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gunji, Y., & Nakamura, T. (1991). Time reverse automata patterns generated by Spencer-Brown’s modulator: invertibility based on autopoiesis. Biosystems, 25(3), 151–177.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Gunji, Y., Shirakawa, T., & Niizato, T. (2008). Life driven by damaged damage. Prog Theor Phys, Suppl, 173, 26–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampis, G. (1995). Computability, self-reference, and self-amendment. Comm Cogn, 12(1–2), 91–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, L. H. (1987). Self-reference and recursive forms. J Soc Biol Struct, 10(1), 53–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman LH (2002) Time, imaginary value, paradox, sign and space. Available at http://www.math.uic.edu/∼kauffman/TimeParadox.pdf

  • Kauffman LH (2005) EigenForm. Kybernetes, 34 (1/2): 129–150. Available at http://www.math.uic.edu/∼kauffman/Eigen.pdf

  • Kitano, H. (Ed.). (2001). Foundations of systems biology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleidon, A. (2009). Nonequilibrium thermodynamics and maximum entropy production in the Earth system. Naturwissenschaften, 96(6), 653–677.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Konopka, A. (Ed.). (2007). Systems biology: principles, methods, and concepts. Boca Raton: CRC Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kull, A. (1997). Self-reference and time according to Spencer-Brown. In H. Atmanspacher & E. Ruhnau (Eds.), Time, temporality, now (pp. 71–79). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K., Emmeche, C., & Favareau, D. (2008). Biosemiotic questions. Biosemiotics, 1(1), 41–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, F. J., & Feldman, M. W. (1999). Evolutionary consequences of niche construction and their implications for ecology. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA, 96, 10242–10247.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J (2009). Structural realism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/structural-realism/

  • Lane, R. (2007). Peirce’s modal shift: from set theory to pragmaticism. J Hist Philos, 45(4), 551–576.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudisa, F., & Rovelli, C. (2008). Relational quantum mechanics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-relational//

  • Mendes, P. (2001). Modeling large biological systems from functional genomic data: parameter estimation. In Kitano, 2001, 163–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., Longo, G., & Stewart, J. (2009). A computable expression of closure to efficient causation. J Theor Biol, 257(3), 489–498.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Noble, D. (2006). The music of life: biology beyond the Genome. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1958) Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. 1–6 (1931–1935), Charles Hartshorne & Paul Weiss (eds); vols. 7–8 (1958) Arthur Burks (ed). Harvard University Press, Cambridge.

  • Peirce CS (1998) The essential Peirce: selected philosophical writings. Volume 2 (1893–1913). Peirce Edition Project (ed). Indiana University Press, Bloomington & Indianapolis.

  • Rigoutsos, I., & Stephanopoulos, G. (Eds.). (2007). Systems biology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, A., & Southgate, C. (2010). A general definition of interpretation and its application to origin of life research. Biol Philos, 25(2), 163–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1958). The representation of biological systems from the standpoint of the theory of categories. Bull Math Biophys, 20, 317–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rovelli, C. (1996). Relational quantum mechanics. Int J Theor Phys, 35, 1637–1678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoup RG (1995) Space, time, logic, and things. PhysComp ’94 Workshop on Physics and Computation. (1994: Dallas, Tex.). Los Alamitos, Calif.: IEEE Computer Society Press. Also available at http://www.boundarymath.org/papers/SpaceTime.pdf

  • Spencer-Brown, G. (1979). Laws of form (3rd ed.). New York: E. P. Dutton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stachel, J. (2007). A world without time: the forgotten legacy of Gödel and Einstein. (Review). Notices of the American Mathematical Society, 57(7), 861–868.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, R., & Rössler, O. E. (2006). Genèse de forme. Revue des Questions Scientifiques, 177(3–4), 279–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trefil, J., Morowitz, H. J., & Smith, E. (2009). The origin of life. A case is made for the descent of electrons. Am Sci, 97(1), 206–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ulanowicz, R. E. (2004). Quantitative methods for ecological network analysis. Comput Biol Chem, 8, 321–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1979). Principles of biological autonomy. New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: the best of both worlds? Dialectica, 43, 99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Victoria Alexander, Marcello Barbieri, John Collier, Don Favareau, Peter Harries-Jones, Kalevi Kull, and Charls Pearson for helpful comments, discussions and improvements of previous versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eliseo Fernández.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Fernández, E. Taking the Relational Turn: Biosemiotics and Some New Trends in Biology. Biosemiotics 3, 147–156 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-010-9084-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-010-9084-y

Keywords

Navigation