Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Risk and Distributive Justice: The Case of Regulating New Technologies

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There are certain kinds of risk for which governments, rather than individual actors, are increasingly held responsible. This article discusses how regulatory institutions can ensure an equitable distribution of risk between various groups such as rich and poor, and present and future generations. It focuses on cases of risk associated with technological and biotechnological innovation. After discussing various possibilities and difficulties of distribution, this article proposes a non-welfarist understanding of risk as a burden of cooperation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Right-based theories, such as the one defended by Robert Nozick, state that if imposing harm on someone violates their rights, then increasing the probability of that harm by imposing a risk also violates their rights (Nozick 1974, p. 4). Concerning the distribution of responsibility for risk taking, a popular stream of egalitarian theorists, the so-called ‘luck egalitarians’ (Dworkin 1981, 2000; Cohen 1989; Roemer 1996), have recognized the importance of developing theories of justice that are both sensitive to individual choices (for which individuals should be held accountable and responsible) and insensitive to circumstances that are beyond free choice (such as talents, ability, health and natural events). Regulation and public insurance schemes must be designed on the one hand to insulate citizens against the consequences of the natural lottery; on the other hand they should be sensitive to people’s choices. To give an example, in the case of health care this would imply a contributory health insurance system (universal basic health care system) coupled with a private insurance scheme (Dworkin 2000, p. 313).

  2. This is in part because global risks such as global warming and nuclear fission are considered catastrophic for humanity and, in this sense, have an equalizing distributive effect (Beck 1992).

  3. See note 1 above.

  4. Real-life decisions are very often made in conditions of uncertainty (probabilities are either unknown or known with less than full precision). However, most of the time decision-making situations are simplified by treating them as decisions under risk; that is, as cases with known probabilities (Hansson 2003, p. 293).

  5. See Keeton et al. (1984, pp. 534–535) “[i]n all civil acts (…) the law doth not so much regard the intent of the actor, as the loss and damage of the party suffering” so that “[t]here was, in other words, a rule […] that ‘he who breaks must pay’”.

  6. There is an asymmetry insofar as the equality of opportunities offers a chance that one is free to take up or ignore, whilst risk imposes the probability of a negative effect.

References

  • Abraham, K. S. (1986). Distributing risk: Insurance, legal theory and public policy. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, C. (2005). Equality, risk and responsibility: Dworkin on the insurance market. Economy and Society, 34(3), 451–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, U. (1992). Risk society: Towards a new modernity. New Delhi: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, U. (1999). World risk society. Malden, MA: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caney, S. (2005). Cosmopolitan justice, responsibility and global climate change. Leiden Journal of International Law, 18, 747–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, I. (1999). A measure of freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (1989). On the currency of egalitarian justice. Ethics, 99, 906–944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J. (1987). Rational ecology: Environment and political economy. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1981). What is equality? Part I: Equality of welfare; Part II: Equality of resources. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 10(3), 185–345.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1985). A matter of principle. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2000). Sovereign virtue: The theory and practice of equality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1984). Harm to others. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, M. P. (2007). Why public participation in risk regulation? The case of authorising GMO products in the European Union. Science as Culture, 16(4), 377–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finkelstein, C. (2003). Is risk a harm? University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 15, 963.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaskell, G. (2003). Seeds of discontent. Risk and Regulation, LSE, 6, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giddens, A. (1999). Risk and responsibility. Modern Law Review, 62(1), 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gosseries, A. (2007). Cosmopolitan luck egalitarianism and the greenhouse effect. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31(suppl.), 279–309.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2003). Ethical criteria of risk acceptance. Erkenntnis, 59, 291–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, D. (1997). Justice and nature and the geography of difference. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunold, C., & Young, I. M. (1998). Justice, democracy and hazardous siting. Political Studies, 46(1), 82–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff, S. (2003). Technologies of humility: Citizens participation in governing science. Minerva, 41(3), 223–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keeton, W., et al. (1984). Prosser and Keeton on torts. St. Paul: West Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, L. (1987). The morality of groups: Collective responsibility, group-based harm, and corporate rights. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1976). Moral luck. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 50 (supplementary volume), 115–135.

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, J. (2001). Representing people, representing nature, representing the world. Environment and Planning C: Government and Policy, 19(4), 483–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Riodan, T., & Cameron, J. (1994). Interpreting the precautionary principle. London: Earthscan Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1997). Equality and priority. Ratio, 10(3), 202–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, A. (1996). Dealing with difference: A politics of ideas, or a politics of presence? In S. Benhabib (Ed.), Democracy and difference: Contesting the boundaries of the political (pp. 139–152). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roemer, J. (1996). Theories of distributive justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slovic, P. (1987). Perception of risk. Science, 236, 280–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steffek, J., & Ferretti, M. P. (2009). Accountability or “good decisions”? The competing goals of civil society participation in international governance. Global Society, 23(1), 260–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, H. (1993). How free: Computing personal freedom. In A. Phillips-Griffiths (Ed.), Of liberty (pp. 73–89). London: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, G. D. (1998). Consumer demand for organic foods: What we know and what we need to know. American Journal of Agriculture Economics, 80, 1113–1118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (1995). Moments of carelessness and massive loss. In D. Owen (Ed.), Philosophical foundations of tort law (pp. 387–408). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1976). Moral luck. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 50 (supplementary volume), 115–135.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank the participants in the GARNET workshop on ‘Risk and Responsibility: Theoretical and Normative Issues of Environmental Governance’ at the University of Florence and the political theory seminar ‘Mercoledì filosofici del Maino’ at the University of Pavia. I am especially grateful to Renata Badii, Ian Carter and Filippo Magni for their valuable discussions and suggestions. Thanks also to Carl Cranor, James Holloway, Christian Joerges and Jens Steffek for discussing with me some earlier ideas later developed in this paper, and to the two anonymous referees of this journal for their very useful and constructive comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maria Paola Ferretti.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ferretti, M.P. Risk and Distributive Justice: The Case of Regulating New Technologies. Sci Eng Ethics 16, 501–515 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-009-9172-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-009-9172-z

Keywords

Navigation