Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Antitheodicy and the Grading of Theodicies by Moral Offensiveness

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Antitheodicy objects to all attempts to solve the problem of evil. Its objections are almost all on moral grounds—it argues that the whole project of theodicy is morally offensive. Trying to excuse God’s permission of evil is said to deny the reality of evil, to exhibit gross insensitivity to suffering, and to insult the victims of grave evils. Since antitheodicists urge the avoidance of theodicies for moral reasons, it is desirable to evaluate the moral reasons against theodicies in abstraction from the intellectual reasons for and against them. It is argued that the best known theodicies such as those based on soul-making and free will are guilty of moral faults as alleged. But Leibniz’s best of all possible worlds theory, often thought to be the most morally offensive ‘Panglossian’ theodicy, is morally blameless because it excuses God by the absolute impossibility of his choosing any world better than the present one. Theodicy should not be conceived of as a search for greater goods which may excuse God’s permitting evils. From the divine point of view, creation is an upfront choice between scenarios—in modern parlance, a Trolley problem rather than a Transplant problem. In cases of forced choice among scenarios, it is morally improper to criticize one who chooses the best.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A more minor debate as to whether theodicy may have harmful consequences such as making us less concerned about evil (Søvik 2008; Simpson 2009b) will not be considered here.

References

  • Beattie, J. (1771). An essay on the nature and immutability of truth, in opposition to sophistry and scepticism (2nd ed.). Edinburgh: Kincaid and Bell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benatar, D. (2006). Better never to have been: the harm of coming into existence. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, R. J. (2002). Radical evil: a philosophical interrogation. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Betenson, T. (2016). Anti-theodicy. Philosophy Compass, 11, 56–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, F. H. (1930). Appearance and reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (2006). The god delusion. London: Bantam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dostoevsky, F. (1879/80). The Brothers Karamazov.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (1996). God without the supernatural: A defense of scientific theism. Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press.

  • Franklin, J. (2002). Two caricatures II: Leibniz’s best world. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 52, 45–56.

  • Felderhof, M. C. (2004). Evil: theodicy or resistance. Scottish Journal of Theology, 57(4), 397–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (2010). Why Richard Swinburne won’t ‘rot in hell’: a defense of tough-minded theodicy. Sophia, 49(1), 37–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gleeson, A. (2010). More on the power of God: a rejoinder to William Hasker. Sophia, 49(4), 617–629.

  • Greenberg, I. (1977). Cloud of smoke, pillar of fire: Judaism, Christianity and modernity after the Holocaust. In E. Fleischner (Ed.), Auschwitz: Beginning of a new era? (pp. 7–55). New York: KTAV Publishing House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, D. R. (2004). God, power, and evil: a process theodicy. London: Westminster John Knox Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hick, J. (2007). D. Z. Phillips on God and evil. Religious Studies, 43(4), 433–41.

  • Holland, R. F. (1980). On the form of ‘the problem of evil’. In R. F. Holland (Ed.), Against empiricism: On education, epistemology and value (pp. 229–243). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knox, R. (1954). Essays in satire (2nd ed.). London: Sheed and Ward.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolb, D., & Lehe, R. (2009). The nihilistic consequences of the argument from evil. International Philosophical Quarterly, 49(4), 427–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraay, K.J. (2016). God and gratuitous evil (part 1). Philosophy Compass, 11, 905–912.

  • Leibniz, G.W. (1710/2009). Theodicy: Essays on the goodness of God, the freedom of man and the origins of evil. Trans. E.M. Huggard, ed. A.M. Farrer. New York: Cosimo.

  • Lewis, D. (1993). Evil for freedom’s sake? Philosophical Papers, 22, 149–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maitzen, S. (2019). Normative objections to theism. In G. Oppy (Ed.), A Companion to Atheism and Philosophy (pp. 204–215). Oxford: Wiley.

  • Phillips, D. Z. (1977). The problem of evil. In S. C. Brown (Ed.), Reason and religion (pp. 103–122). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D. Z. (2004). The problem of evil and the problem of god. London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pihlström, S., & Kivistö, S. (2016). Kantian Antitheodicy: philosophical and literary varieties. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pseudo-Dionysius (c 500/1920). On the Divine Names. In Dionysius the Areopagite: On the Divine Names and the Mystical Theology. Trans. C.E. Rolt. London: SPCK.

  • Shearn, S. (2013). Moral critique and defence of theodicy. Religious Studies, 49(4), 39–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, R. M. (2009a). Moral antitheodicy: prospects and problems. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 65(3), 153–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, R. (2009b). Some moral critique of theodicy is misplaced, but not all. Religious Studies, 45(3), 339–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Søvik, A. O. (2008). Why almost all moral critique of theodicies is misplaced. Religious Studies, 44, 479–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Søvik, A. O., & Eikrem, A. (2015). A critique of Samuel Shearn’s moral critique of theodicies. Religious Studies, 51(2), 261–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (1996). Is there a God? Oxford University Press.

  • Thomson, J. J. (1976). Killing, letting die and the trolley problem. Monist, 59, 204–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trakakis, N. (2008). Theodicy: the solution to the problem of evil, or part of the problem? Sophia, 47(2), 161–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trakakis, N. N. (2010). Against theodicy: a reply to Peter Forrest. Sophia, 49(1), 129–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trakakis, N. N. (2013). Antitheodicy. In J. P. McBrayer & D. Howard-Snyder (Eds.), Blackwell companion to the problem of evil (pp. 363–376). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (2005). The problem of evil. In W. Wainwright (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of religion (pp. 188–219). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Voltaire. (1759). Candide.

  • Williams, R. (1996). Redeeming sorrows. In D. Z. Phillips (Ed.), Religion and morality (pp. 132–148). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James Franklin.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Franklin, J. Antitheodicy and the Grading of Theodicies by Moral Offensiveness. SOPHIA 59, 563–576 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-020-00765-w

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-020-00765-w

Keywords

Navigation