Skip to main content
Log in

Mathematics embodied: Merleau-Ponty on geometry and algebra as fields of motor enaction

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper aims to clarify Merleau-Ponty’s contribution to an embodied-enactive account of mathematical cognition. I first identify the main points of interest in the current discussions of embodied higher cognition and explain how they relate to Merleau-Ponty and his sources, in particular Husserl’s late works. Subsequently, I explain these convergences in greater detail by more specifically discussing the domains of geometry and algebra and by clarifying the role of gestalt psychology in Merleau-Ponty’s account. Beyond that, I explain how, for Merleau-Ponty, mathematical cognition requires not only the presence and actual manipulation of some concrete perceptible symbols but, more strongly, how it is fundamentally linked to the structural transformation of the concrete configurations of symbolic systems to which these symbols appertain. Furthemore, I fill a gap in the literature by explaining Merleau-Ponty’s claim that these structural transformations are operated through motor intentionality. This makes it possible, in turn, to contrast Merleau-Ponty’s approach to ontologically idealistic and realistic views on mathematical objects. On Merleau-Ponty’s account, mathematical objects are relational entities, that is, gestalts that necessarily imply situated cognizers to whom they afford a specific type of engagement in the world and on whom they depend in their eventual structural transformations. I argue that, by attributing a strongly constitutive role to phenomenal configurations and their motor transformation in mathematical thinking, Merleau-Ponty contributes to clarifying the worldly, historical, and socio-cultural aspects of mathematical truths without compromising what we perceive as their universality, certainty, and necessity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

Not applicable.

Code availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. For example, Cassou-Noguès (1998) is mostly critical, while Hass and Hass (2000) and Matherne (2018) are appreciative. See also Besmer (2007) and Baldwin (2013), whose positions are mixed.

  2. I note that Hutto does not explicitly connect idealism with Husserl. However, among the authors discussed by Gallagher, Husserl seems to be one of those who may be labelled an idealist.

  3. In connection to this discussion, see also Hohol (2020, 89–108), who provides an analogical criticism of the idea of neural simulation of sensory experiences based on his review of literature that includes the works discussed by Gallagher and Hutto. However, Hohol adopts a moderately embodied stance and does not entirely reject the notion of representation.

  4. Husserl’s thoughts on this matter developed over time. While in his late discussions on the role of language and writing, Husserl (1989) comes close to the idea that expression plays a constitutive role with regard to ideal meaning, he explicitly rejects this in his earlier works (e.g., 1982, 296).

  5. Speech “is a praxis,” Merleau-Ponty claims, and the mathematical ideality appears “at the edge of speech” (2002, 56, 46). Regarding speech as operative intentionality implicated in abstract thought, including mathematics, see also Merleau-Ponty (1968b, 155, 188). For analyzes of Merleau-Ponty’s notion of speaking speech in a broader context, see Baldwin (2007); Kee (2018); Kiverstein and Rietveld (2021).

  6. While Merleau-Ponty emphasizes the role of perceptual and bodily expression from early on, he properly grasped the social and linguistic aspects only after 1947, when he adopted elements of structural linguistics. See, for example, Merleau-Ponty’s description of the process through which we express our thoughts within a dialogue (1973, 133–146). For interpretations of Merleau-Ponty’s theory of expression, see in particular Fóti (2013), Hass (2008, 146–192), Kee (2018), and Landes (2013).

  7. Merleau-Ponty is alluding here to Bergson’s (1946, 7–31) idea of the “retrograde movement of the true.”.

  8. For a more elaborate discussion of this point, see Sect. 4.3.

  9. Regarding this point, see Merleau-Ponty’s discussion of the idea of Stiftung (1970, 161–67; 2002, 16–65; 2010, 50–61). For interpretations of Merleau-Ponty’s relationship to Husserl (1989), see Baldwin (2013); Besmer (2007); Hass and Hass (2000), Hass (2008, 146–169); Lawlor (2002); Robert (2000); Vallier (2005); Watson (2016).

  10. In contrast to this view, Besmer’s (2007) reading of Merleau-Ponty, for example, emphasizes his continuity with Husserl and is correlatively origin-nostalgic, past-oriented, and teleologically objectivistic (see, e.g., 135–136). However, I believe that since Merleau-Ponty ultimately defined our relation to reality as “interrogative” and thus open-ended, he would not accept a teleologically objectivistic view (see, e.g., 1996, 375).

  11. The available English translations of Merleau-Ponty’s Résumés de cours (1968a) and La prose du monde (1969) contain many inaccuracies. I have modified the passages cited from these texts as noted and I invite the reader to compare the French originals by following the pagination indicated after the slash in the citations.

  12. Cassou-Noguès (1998, 398) and Baldwin (2013, 305, 325) criticize Merleau-Ponty for not acknowledging formalization as a specifically mathematical procedure and as an evidence-providing instrument. Yet neither Cassou-Noguès nor Baldwin discusses Merleau-Ponty’s own interpretation of formalization and his explicit criticism of this procedure. Moreover, Cassou-Noguès’ and Baldwin’s interpretations seem to lack an accurate account of the presumed counterpart of formal thought, namely, “intuitive” thought (a term Merleau-Ponty uses only very rarely, e.g., 2012, 405). Baldwin (2013, 326) claims that Merleau-Ponty rejects formal thought in favor of “informal” thought, but this is unconvincing. Unlike Husserl, Merleau-Ponty does not proceed with the idea of an intuitive insight, since he considers all experience dependent on habitual bodily schematizations and, more strongly, on socio-cultural acquisitions, which always formalize our experience at least to some degree. In contrast to Cassou-Noguès and Baldwin, Hass and Hass (2000, 182) explicitly analyze Merleau-Ponty’s account of geometry in relation to formalism in mathematics and find Merleau-Ponty’s position persuasive. In their view, a transition from premises to conclusions is never a purely formal but rather an “expressive” or structurally productive operation (cf. Watson, 2007, 536–37; Gallagher, 2017, 208). Moreover, as Hohol (2020, 135) explains, the contemporary formal approach to proving practice in geometry was completely unknown to the inventors of Euclidian geometry.

  13. Similarly, Hohol (2020, chapter 4) recently argued that Euclidian geometry is a cognitive artefact that cannot be explained universalistically.

  14. The English translation (1973, 105) of this passage is incorrect.

  15. In my opinion, Cassou-Noguès fails to recognize this point (see, e.g., 1998, 382).

  16. It is important to note that in the passages interpreted here, Merleau-Ponty speaks of drawing in a very narrow sense. However, in his other writings, he considers drawing and painting as expressive operations in their own right and acknowledges their capacity to bring forth a specific type of generality. Therefore, the difference between the generality of an expressive drawing and a geometric figure should be understood as of a degree and not of a kind.

  17. For example, the development of a non-Euclidian geometry enables a transition from a still naïve Euclidian expression of space to a less naïve alternative, not to an absolute truth (cf. Merleau-Ponty 2012, 414; 1973, 100/141, 103/146, 127–28/178–79). Euclidian space is by no means a priori for Merleau-Ponty, and even if it might be considered privileged in relation to other expressions of space, it is a historical invention and its privileged position is not absolute (1968b, 213; cf. Hass, 2008, 166). As Hass and Hass (2000, 180–81) note, “mathematical truths are historically and geographically located” and the demonstrative value of mathematical proofs comes from the fact that the mathematical object perseveres throughout the structural transformations involved in the proof (cf. Merleau-Ponty 2012, 405). In accordance with this view, Hohol (2020, chapter 4.4.) argues that the main source of generality and necessity of Euclid’s proofs is the intersubjective repeatability of reasonings “scaffolded on the consistent use of [cognitive] artifacts” such as geometric diagrams and formulas (2020, 137).

  18. One may understand this phenomenon by analogy with threshold phenomena in perception (cf., e.g., Merleau-Ponty 2012, 9).

  19. Merleau-Ponty later briefly interpreted an analogous geometric problem, namely, the calculation of the area of a parallelogram (2010, 55; based on Wertheimer, 2020, 14–78).

  20. In his interpretation of geometric demonstration, Merleau-Ponty does not address the differences between the actual visual field and the imaginary visual field. Such an explanation is, however, necessary if Merleau-Ponty’s argument is to be made entirely plausible. Generally, Merleau-Ponty interprets the imaginary field as founded on some elements of the perceptual world and refuses to conceive of the imaginary world as a purely mental domain (cf., e.g., 2010, 46–50; 1970, 48, 68–69). From this point of view, a transition to the field of imagination does not affect the fundamental aspects of Merleau-Ponty’s argument concerning geometry. For an analogical contemporary attempt to ground imagination in embodied action, see Rucińska and Gallagher (2021).

  21. Building on Merleau-Ponty, Irwin (2017) has developed an analogical interpretation of abstract words.

  22. For a detailed explanation of how the body schema provides the ground for perceptual figures according to Merleau-Ponty, see Halák (2021a, 35–38).

  23. Cf. Wertheimer’s detailed discussions of analogic geometrical examples (e.g., 2020, 18).

  24. Hohol (2020, 46), for example, does not seem to distinguish between perceptual figures and geometric properties. In contrast, see Zahidi and Myin’s (2016) critique of this widespread cognitive bias.

  25. Alternatively, it is possible that painters such as Cézanne were capable of liberating their perception from the influence of previously learned geometry. Cf. Merleau-Ponty’s analysis of “perspectival distortions” in Cézanne’s paintings (1964c, 13–15) or his thoughts on topological space (1968b, 212–13).

  26. The English translation (1970, 105) of this passage is incorrect.

  27. Cf. Kiverstein and Rietveld’s (2021, 178–180) critique of Gibson on this point.

  28. Merleau-Ponty would therefore satisfy the requirement for a relative independence of the two systems as presented by Hohol (2020), based on his review of recent empirical experiments.

  29. Merleau-Ponty (2020a, 123) makes a similar point regarding the system of speech.

  30. See Merleau-Ponty (1973, 105–106/149–150; 125–26/176–177; cf. 2010, 55–56).

  31. In contrast to that, Schneider cannot dispense with the operation itself. See below, Sect. 4.3.

  32. Husserl (1989) considers “sedimentation” the process through which an originally experienced ideal meaning becomes stabilized in language or other symbolic systems and thus, communicable across time and space (cf. Blomberg 2019).

  33. See Sect. 3.4. for an analogical argument regarding perceptual “physiognomies” and geometrical properties. For discussion on this relationship from the perspective of embodied cognition, see Zahidi (2021), Zahidi and Myin (2016), and Fabry (2018, 796–98).

  34. See above, note 7.

References

  • Baldwin, T. (2007). Speaking and spoken speech. In T. Baldwin (Ed.), Reading Merleau-Ponty (pp. 87–103). Oxon: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, T. (2013). Language as the embodiment of geometry. In R. Jensen & D. Moran D. (Eds.), The phenomenology of embodied subjectivity. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1946). The creative mind. New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Besmer, K. (2007). Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology: The problem of ideal objects. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blomberg, J. (2019). Interpreting the concept of sedimentation in Husserl’s Origin of Geometry. Public Journal of Semiotics, 9(1), 78–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cassou-Noguès, P. (1998). Le problème des mathématiques dans la philosophie de Merleau-Ponty. In M. Merleau-Ponty, Notes de cours sur L’Origine de la géométrie de Husserl (pp. 369–404). Paris: P.U.F.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuffari, E. (2012). Gestural sense-making: Hand gestures as intersubjective linguistic enactments. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11(4), 599–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1989). Introduction to The Origin of Geometry. London: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabry, R. E. (2018). Turing redux: Enculturation and computation. Cognitive Systems Research, 52, 793–808.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fóti, V. M. (2013). Tracing expression in Merleau-Ponty: Aesthetics, philosophy of biology, and ontology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2015). Doing the math: Calculating the role of evolution and enculturation in the origins of geometrical and mathematical reasoning. Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, 119(3), 341–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist Interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2019). Replies to Barrett, Corris and Chemero, and Hutto. Philosophical Studies, 176(3), 839–851.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, A. (2009). Some Aspects and Developments of Gestalt Psychology. In F. Kersten (Ed.), The collected works of Aron Gurwitsch (1901–1973): Volume II: Studies in phenomenology and psychology (pp. 1–61). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldin-Meadow, S., Nusbaum, H., Kelly, S. D., & Wagner, S. (2001). Explaining math: Gesturing lightens the load. Psychological Science, 12(6), 516–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halák, J. (2021a). Body schema dynamics in Merleau-Ponty. In Y. Ataria, S. Tanaka, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), Body schema and body image: New directions (pp. 33–51). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Halák, J. (2021b). Embodied higher cognition: Insights from Merleau-Ponty’s interpretation of motor intentionality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-021-09769-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hass, L. (2008). Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hass, M., & Hass, L. (2000). Merleau-Ponty and The Origin of Geometry. In F. Evans (Ed.), Chiasms: Merleau-Ponty’s notion of flesh (pp. 177–187). Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohol, M. (2020). Foundations of geometric cognition. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2019). Re-doing the math: Making enactivism add up. Philosophical Studies, 176(3), 827–837.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1965). Phenomenology and the crisis of philosophy. New York: Torchbooks.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1982). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy: First book: General introduction to a pure phenomenology. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1989). The origin of geometry. In J. Derrida (Ed.), Introduction to The Origin of Geometry (pp. 155–180). London: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, B. A. (2017). An enactivist account of abstract words: Lessons from Merleau-Ponty. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 16(1), 133–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isaac, A. M., & Ward, D. (2019). Introduction: Gestalt phenomenology and embodied cognitive science. Synthese, 198(Suppl 9), 2135–2151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kee, H. (2018). Phenomenology and ontology of language and expression: Merleau-Ponty on speaking and spoken speech. Human Studies, 41(3), 415–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kee, H. (2021). Phenomenology and naturalism in autopoietic and radical enactivism: Exploring sense-making and continuity from the top down. Synthese, 198, 2323–2343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J., & Rietveld, E. (2021). Scaling-up skilled intentionality to linguistic thought. Synthese, 198(1), 175–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. J., & Johnson, M. (2003). Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Núñez, R. E. (2000). Where mathematics comes from: How the embodied mind brings mathematics into Being. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landes, D. (2013). Merleau-Ponty and the paradoxes of expression. New York: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawlor, L. (2002). The Legacy of Husserl’s “Ursprung der Geometrie”: The limits of phenomenology in Merleau-Ponty and Derrida. In T. Toadvine & L. Embree (Eds.), Merleau-Ponty’s reading of Husserl (pp. 201–223). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2013). How things shape the mind: A theory of material engagement. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Matherne, S. (2018). Merleau-Ponty on abstract thought in mathematics and natural science. European Journal of Philosophy, 26(2), 780–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2013). The enculturated hand. In Z. Radman (Ed.), The hand: An organ of the mind (pp. 349–367). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2015). Mathematical cognition–A case of enculturation. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND: 25(T). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1959). Projet “Être et Monde”. In M. Merleau-Ponty, Projets de livres, 1958–1961 (pp. 147–231). Unpublished manuscript. Bibliothèque Nationale de France, NAF 26989, vol. 6.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1963). Structure of Behavior. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964a). The philosopher and sociology. In M. Merleau-Ponty, Signs (pp. 98–113). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964b). Everywhere and Nowhere. In M. Merleau-Ponty, Signs (pp. 126–158). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964c). Cézanne’s Doubt. In M. Merleau-Ponty, Sense and Non-Sense (pp. 9–25). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968a). Résumés de cours. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968b). The visible and the invisible. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1969). La prose du monde. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1970). Themes from the lectures. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1973). Prose of the world. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1988). In praise of philosophy and other essays. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1996). Brouillon d’une rédaction. In M. Merleau-Ponty, Notes des cours au Collège de France, 1958–1959 et 1960–1961 (pp. 355–378). Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2001). Reading notes and comments on Aron Gurwitsch’s The Field of Consciousness. Husserl Studies, 17(3), 173–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002). Husserl at the limits of phenomenology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003). Nature: Course notes from the Collège de France. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2007). An unpublished text by Maurice Merleau-Ponty: A prospectus of his work. In T. Toadvine & L. Lawlor (Eds.), The Merleau-Ponty Reader (pp. 283–290). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2010). Institution and passivity: Course Notes from the Collège de France (1954–1955). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2020a). The sensible world and the world of expression: Course Notes from the Collège de France, 1953. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2020b). Le problème de la parole. Cours au Collège de France. Notes, 1953–1954. Genève: MetisPresses.

  • Muller, R. M. (2021). Merleau-Ponty and the radical sciences of mind. Synthese, 198, 2243–2277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overmann, K. A. (2016). The role of materiality in numerical cognition. Quaternary International, 405, 42–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overmann, K. A. (2018). Constructing a concept of number. Journal of Numerical Cognition, 4(2), 464–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robert, F. (2000). Fondement et fondation. Chiasmi International, 2, 351–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z., & Gallagher, S. (2021). Making imagination even more embodied: Imagination, constraint and epistemic relevance. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03156-x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Saint-Aubert, E. (2011). Conscience et expression. Avant-propos. In M. Merleau-Ponty, Le monde sensible et le monde de l’expression (pp. 7–38). Genève: MetissPress.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheredos, B. (2017). Merleau-Ponty’s immanent critique of gestalt theory. Human Studies, 40(2), 191–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (2016). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vallier, R. (2005). Institution: The Significance of Merleau-Ponty’s 1954 Course at the Collège de France. Chiasmi International, 7, 281–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, S. H. (2007). Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenological itinerary from body schema to situated knowledge: On how we are and how we are not to “Sing the World.” Janus Head, 9(2), 525–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, S. H. (2016). “Philosophy is also an architecture of signs:” On Merleau-Ponty and Cavaillès. Research in Phenomenology, 46(1), 35–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. (1938). The syllogism and productive thinking. In W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A source book of gestalt psychology (pp. 274–282). London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. (2020). Productive thinking. Basel: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahidi, K. (2021). Radicalizing numerical cognition. Synthese, 198(1), 529–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahidi, K., & Myin, E. (2016). Radically enactive numerical cognition. In G. Etzelmüller & C. Tewes (Eds.), Embodiment in evolution and culture (pp. 57–71). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the two anonymous reviewers for their valuable comments on the manuscript. I am also thankful to Raymond Tallis for his interest and critique, and to Sunwoo Lee for her continous support.

Funding

Work on this study was supported by the project “The Dynamics of Corporeal Intentionality,” Palacký University Olomouc, Reg. No. JG_2019_006.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jan Halák.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest

The author declares that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Halák, J. Mathematics embodied: Merleau-Ponty on geometry and algebra as fields of motor enaction. Synthese 200, 34 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03526-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03526-z

Keywords

Navigation