1 Introduction

The conflict between the doctrine of Humeanism and quantum entanglement has historically been central to metaphysical foundations of quantum mechanics (QM). In particular, many different proposals have flourished with the goal of either finding alternative formulations of QM which remove the problematic features of entanglement (Esfeld et al. 2013; Esfeld 2014) or of individuating variants of the Humean thesis which are compatible with QM despite entanglement (Lyre 2009; Darby 2012; Miller 2014; Callender 2015; Bhogal and Perry 2017). The aim of our paper is different from both these approaches. Our approach falls squarely in the context of entanglement realism (as understood and defended against more eliminative approaches in Glick and Darby (2018)), roughly speaking the view that there are relations constitutive of entanglement in our fundamental ontology. Indeed, one might see this work as a specific proposal for a form of entanglement realism and its compatibility with Humeanism, in the context of quantum gravity (QG). We thus argue that one can attack the problem of reconciling entanglement and Humeanism not by modifying either one or the other, but instead by looking at some tantalising approaches and conjectures regarding the extension of QM to the realm of gravity and spacetime. Studying the interaction of QG with metaphysics is a practice more and more common in the literature, as witnessed by Le Bihan (2019), Matarese (2019), Wüthrich (2019) and Jaksland (2020). This approach holds much promise for the interaction between the edge of physical and metaphysical research.

Before getting to the core of our discussion, let us briefly address a preliminary question: why should QG be relevant to this problem? Or, more generally, why should QM not be enough to address the issue of reconciling entanglement with Humeanism? There are two sets of reasons for extending our sight beyond the realm of QM to QG: on the one hand, one might note that up to this point, most resolutions of the conflict between QM and Humeanism have proven unsatisfactory. Indeed, the fact that the debate is still going on shows that there are no universally accepted answers to these problems. Such a situation suggests that there might be something to the idea of trying new avenues to find possible alternatives to the standard options in the debate. On the other hand, and a more substantive note, QG seems to be especially relevant to the question of the relationship between entanglement and Humeanism, since this tension, as we make clear in the next sections, ultimately rests on the conflict between the causal structure of spacetime and the relations of entanglement. Since QG should be a theory which deals with quantum spacetime, and thus directly with the interplay between spacetime structure and entanglement, it is uniquely situated to provide insight on the compatibility of Humeanism and entanglement. Indeed, having a quantum spacetime is the goal of most theories of QG. Identifying ways in which these two sets of structures can be compatible is one of its main tasks.

Specifically, in this paper, we focus on the so-called ER=EPR conjecture (Maldacena and Susskind 2013), a speculative extension of the picture of spacetime coming from General Relativity (GR). ER=EPR incorporates some initial quantum effects into classical spacetime structure. As we argue in Sect. 5, it is a reasonable possibility that such conjecture is satisfied in the semiclassical regime of a complete theory of QG. For this reason, while ER=EPR is a conjecture, we think it can be useful to understand how this conjecture might impact the compatibility between Humeanism and entanglement since ER=EPR provides a concrete model of how QG might affect such problems, knowing however that such conclusions will always be conditional on the truth of ER=EPR. Our goal is to suggest a first avenue in which QG might inform the discussions on the compatibility between Humeanism and entanglement.

The paper’s structure is the following: we give a simple presentation of the conflict between Humeanism and entanglement (Sect. 2). In particular, we reformulate this tension in a way that makes its subsequent connection with QG particularly intuitive, from a conceptual point of view. We then introduce the so-called ER=EPR conjecture, that we later use to elucidate how we can reconcile entanglement and Humeanism (Sect. 3). We explain how ER=EPR renders Humeanism compatible with entanglement (Sect. 4) and then we argue for the generality of ER=EPR and defend a metaphysics based on it, notwithstanding its conditional character (Sect. 5). In (Sect. 6) we conclude.

2 Humeanism and entanglement

In general, it can be quite difficult to pin down what exactly is meant by Humeanism, and we certainly do not want to take stock on a precise definition of this thesis. Hence, in the present paper, we rely on a simple characterisation of the core aspects of Humeanism. Following Maudlin (2007) Humeanism is the conjunction of these two doctrines:

  1. Doctrine 1

    Separability: The complete physical state of the world is determined by (supervenes on) the intrinsic physical state of each spacetime point (or each pointlike object)Footnote 1 and the spatio-temporal relations between those points.

  2. Doctrine 2

    Physical Statism: All facts about the world, including modal and nomological facts, are determined by its total physical state.

Given these two doctrines, let us now see why entanglement appears to be in tension with Humeanism. In particular, we show that entanglement explicitly violates Separability. The violation of Separability is because entangled states are not factorisable, that is, given a certain quantum state \(|\psi \rangle \) for a composite system \(\psi \) of two subsystems \(\alpha \) and \(\beta \), we cannot express it as a product state of the states of the two subsystems, that is, as a state of the form \(|\psi \rangle = |\alpha \rangle \otimes |\beta \rangle \). The importance of product states for composite systems is that, whatever predictions one can derive from a product state, they are fully determined by the (intrinsic) state of its subsystems (equivalently, there is a common cause in the past which screens off any correlation in the product state). We cannot factorise the state of a composite system \(\psi \) since there are correlations between the two subsystems \(\alpha \) and \(\beta \) that cannot be understood simply by taking into account the (intrinsic) states of the subsystems. Equivalently, there is no common cause which screens off the correlations.Footnote 2 Hence, these correlations are irreducible, i.e. there are no intrinsic states (that is, in this quantum mechanical case, pure states) that one can assign to the subsystems \(\alpha \) and \(\beta \) that can reproduce the predictions that one derives from an entangled state for the composite system \(\psi \). A concrete example of such a state is the (in)famous singlet state, a state of two fermions (i.e. spin half particles), whose spins are entangled. The state of such a composite system is \(|\psi \rangle = \frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}(|\uparrow \downarrow \rangle - |\downarrow \uparrow \rangle )\). Being in this state entails that there is a correlation between the spins of the two particles. In particular, that their spins are anticorrelated, i.e. one particle has spin-up, the other has spin-down and vice versa. Indeed, it is this feature that engenders the conflict with Separability.Footnote 3 As Maudlin (2007, p. 51) says,

if the principle of Separability holds, then each electron, occupying a region disjoint from the other, would have its intrinsic spin state, and the spin state of the composite system would be determined by the states of the particles taken individually, together with the spatiotemporal relations between them. But, no pure state for a single particle yields the same predictions as the Singlet state.

Note that here we are following Maudlin (2007) in finding the tension between Humeanism and entanglement at the level of Separability. However, such a problem only emerges insofar as one keeps fixed the assumption of Physical Statism. One might then be tempted to consider Physical Statism the problematic assumption for the Humean and retain Separability instead.Footnote 4 This move, i.e. to negate that the state of the world determines modal and nomological facts, implies that the correlations between entangled systems are essentially nomological. Giving a proper Humean understanding of this fact is then the main goal of this type of approaches.Footnote 5 However, for the remainder of this paper, we will bracket this type of concerns and assume that Physical Statism has to be retained and that it is Separability which is problematic for the Humean vis a vis entanglement. Let us now step back slightly and recast this conflict in a way more conducive to its connection with QG.

The correlations involved in entangled states are particularly robust, in the sense that they are not merely accidental correlations between two subsystems, but are codified in the laws of nature of QM. They thus have, insofar as we take those laws to be a reliable guide at least to nomological modality, an important modal, and thus counterfactual, robustness.Footnote 6 Indeed, such counterfactual robustness of entanglement correlations has convinced some philosophers that we should understand these correlations as causal dependencies (Maudlin 2002). For simplicity of exposition, we too refer to entanglement correlations with talk of causal-like dependencies. Note, however, that for the notions that we introduce, this is not strictly necessary. The robustness of the correlations is sufficient to define all the notions that we use. In particular, nothing in our arguments hinges on some of the features typical of stronger accounts of causation, be them either energy-momentum exchange among causally related systems or causally significant interventions being possible. Since however, talking in causal terms renders the discussion much more straightforward, we make use of this talk. Those who disagree that entanglement correlations can be understood as encoding causal dependencies are free to substitute causality with robust counterfactual correlations. Indeed, outside of issues of linguistic simplicity, we encourage the reader to think, for the remainder of the paper, of all talk of causality as being concerned only with counterfactually robust correlations, and not necessarily with any stronger notion of causation.

Let us also note that we speak, quite liberally, as if it makes sense to locate quantum systems at spacetime points. This issue is controversial,Footnote 7 but we bracket such an issue, again for the sake of linguistic simplicity. We thus speak as if the location of quantum systems at points makes sense while noting that everything that we say continues to make sense even if we only had at our disposal regions of spacetime. However, we should note that while the core of our arguments is not influenced by whether or not quantum systems can be located at spacetime points, one might be sceptical that Humeanism can still make sense in the absence of definite location at spacetime points.Footnote 8 Given, however, that it is not settled in the literature that both these situations are the case, we proceed by bracketing these problems, speaking as if localisation at spacetime points of quantum systems made sense. At the same time, we think that it is useful to note that any satisfactory form of Humeanism should also address the concerns just mentioned.

Let us introduce the notion that is at the heart of our reformulation of the tension between Humeanism and entanglement.

(CS):

Causal Structure: given a theory T, we say that a causal structure according to the theory T is given by a set \(\varOmega \) of spacetime points/pointlike objects (with their intrinsic physical state) and a relation R which determines if two objects/points of spacetime can or cannot be causally related.Footnote 9

Given this definition of causal structure, we can understand a particular causal structure as being determined through (CS) by three things: a theory T, a set of objects \(\varOmega \) (with their intrinsic physical states) and a relation R. For example, we might take as our physical theory T GR, with its set of objects \(\varOmega \) being the spacetime points, and identify the relation R in (CS) with the relation \(R_{LC}\) of being connectable by a causal curve, obtaining between two points of spacetime p and q.Footnote 10 We understand the relation \(R_{LC}\) as obtaining if and only if there is a causal curve between the two points of spacetime p and q. By causal curve, we mean a timelike or null curve (that is a curve which is always within the light-cone, border included, or, equivalently, a curve representing the worldline of an object whose speed never exceeds the speed of light). We call this the causal structure of (relativistic) spacetime.Footnote 11 Thus, causal curves describe the causal structure of spacetime, in the sense that they determine which points can be in causal contact. Note that with this relation one automatically encodes the locality properties of relativity theory, since it follows that there cannot be spacelike separated points which are in causal contact.

Of course, for a given theory T, there might be more than one causal structure, i.e. more than one relation of causal connectedness, at least insofar as these relations are mutually compatible. However, since separability is only concerned with spacetime relations, the only relation of causal connectedness relevant for Separability is \(R_{LC}\). Equivalently, Separability only relies on the causal structure of spacetime. For this reason, the definition above of the causal structure of spacetime allows us to redefine Separability in the following way:

  1. Doctrine 1

    Separability\({}^\dagger \): The complete physical state of the world is determined by (supervenes on) the causal structure of spacetime.

Ultimately this is just an innocent way to recast Separability in terms of causal structures. Indeed, this is evident when we consider that, given any two spacetime points p and q (the objects with which Separability is concerned), the causal structure of spacetime, i.e. (CS) with \(R_{LC}\) as the relation of causal connectedness, encodes the causally relevant spatiotemporal relations of p and q and their intrinsic physical states. However, this is just the structure with which Separability is concerned since it only deals with spacetime points, their intrinsic physical states, and their spacetime relations. Thus Separability and Separability\({}^\dagger \) are equivalent and, as consequence, we speak just of Separability henceforth.Footnote 12 However, an advantage of our way of recasting the problem, is that our definition of causal structure allows us to define a causal structure for entanglement. The relevant theory T in the definition of (CS) would be QM, and the relation R is identified with the relation \(R_E\) of being entangled with, connecting two quantum systems \(\alpha \) and \(\beta \). Indeed, entanglement determines robust correlations among systems,Footnote 13 and, in this paper, robust correlations are all that we mean when we say that there is a causal relation. Thus, since entanglement fixes a set of (cor)related objects which are in causal contact according to our framework, we can use it to construct a structure which fits into our definition (CS) of causal structure, by using entanglement as its generating relation \(R_E\).Footnote 14 We can immediately see the sense in which in this framework we have a violation of Separability: one can have spacelike separated spacetime points (or regions, depending on our understanding of location for quantum systems) at which there are objects in entangled states. Thus, there are points causally separated for the causal structure of spacetime (defined by \(R_{LC}\)) but causally related for the causal structure defined by the entanglement relations \(R_E\).Footnote 15 Note that this fact does not imply action-at-a-distance, since entanglement, and thus the relation \(R_E\), only imply the existence of robust counterfactual connections which, however, do not necessitate any form of action at-a-distance.Footnote 16 The violation of separability is then understood as the mismatch between the two causal structures since this mismatch entails that the complete physical state of the world cannot be determined by the causal structure of spacetime alone, contra Separability.Footnote 17 Resolving this mismatch is the goal of the rest of this paper. To start, however, we need to introduce the specific formal and physical structures of the ER=EPR conjecture, which is the content of the following session.Footnote 18

3 Physical framework

Maldacena and Susskind (2013) point out the existence of a relation between entanglement and spacetime geometry, which they summed up with the slogan ER=EPR. ER refers to Einstein and Rosen (1935), a work regarding a novel solution of Einstein gravity which has been called Einstein–Rosen bridge (ERB henceforth). EPR refers to Einstein et al. (1935), the paper of the famous EPR paradox concerning quantum entanglement. In both papers, despite their different subject matter, locality appears to be challenged: ERB (wormholes) are non-local connections between black holes in GR; entanglement is a non-local correlation between particles in QM. Maldacena and Susskind (2013) conjecture that these two phenomena are the same. The natural place to look for such connections between GR and QM is the physics of black holes because they are one of the few known objects displaying quantum gravitational effects since around the singularity inside the black hole GR breaks down and QG is needed to understand physics. In particular, we are interested in entanglement-like correlations between black holes. Does it make sense for a system of two black holes to be entangled? If this is the case, can entanglement of black holes be compared with ERBs?

3.1 Entanglement

Let us define quantum entanglement so: given two arbitrary systems, a composite state \(|\psi \rangle \) is said to be entangled if it is not a product state of the two subsystems. As we already discussed in Sect. 2, the simplest entangled system is a composite system of two maximally entangled qubits, i.e. a Bell pair, also known as singlet state:

$$\begin{aligned} |\psi \rangle =\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}\left( {|}{\uparrow }\rangle _1{{|}{\downarrow }}\rangle _2 -{{|}{\downarrow }}\rangle _1{{|}{\uparrow }}\rangle _2\right) , \end{aligned}$$
(1)

where 1 stands for the first qubit and 2 stands for the second. A more relevant example for our purposes of entanglement comes from QFT. A key feature of this theory is that the vacuum is not simply empty space, but contains virtual particle-antiparticle pairs (see Fig. 1). These vacuum bubbles immediately annihilate and are not measurable.

Fig. 1
figure 1

In the figure, the dotted line represents the propagation of a virtual particle or antiparticle, the boxes represent the particles/antiparticles and the red line represents the entanglement between them. We use these conventions hereafter

The existence of such vacuum polarisation straightforwardly leads to entanglement. Consider empty space and divide it into two halves: the left side L and the right side R (see Fig. 2). Now take some cells, i.e. small regions of spacetime, near the boundary of the two halves. Consider then vacuum fluctuations across the boundary: if there is no particle on the left side then there is no particle on the right side; if there is a particle on the left side then there is its antiparticle on the right side.

Fig. 2
figure 2

This figure describes spacetime equipped with a rhomboidal grid and divided into two halves. Some cells have some vacuum polarisation, others not

Let us call \(|0\rangle \) the state where there is no particle and \(|1\rangle \) the state where a particle is present. The state which represents the system in each cell is the entangled state

$$\begin{aligned} |\psi \rangle = \frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} \biggl ({|0\rangle }_L {|0\rangle }_R + |1\rangle _L |1\rangle _R\biggr )~, \end{aligned}$$
(2)

where L and R refer to the left and the right side. By conformal invariance,Footnote 19 a property of Minkowski spacetime, one can consider bigger and bigger cells, moving farther and farther away from the boundary. Thus, it is possible to find entanglement-like correlations between regions on the left and right sides even far away from the boundary. We can call these correlations ground state or vacuum entanglement (Susskind 2016). In particular, if we take a quantum field to be a scalar field representing a coordinate system on spacetime, then it seems reasonable to say that vacuum entanglement captures a property of spacetime.

3.2 Entangled black holes

So far we explained what we mean by entanglement, and how two entangled systems can be constructed in any quantum theory using either quantum entanglement or vacuum entanglement. Now we can turn to how it is possible to build up systems made of two entangled black holes.Footnote 20 There are two ways of entangling black holes, using either quantum entanglement or vacuum entanglement (see Fig. 3).

Fig. 3
figure 3

The figure represents two different ways to construct a pair of two entangled black holes. On the left, one starting from many Bell pairs, divide them into two boxes and shrinking them into two entangled black holes; on the right, we start with a black hole, collect its Hawking radiation and shrink the Hawking radiation into a second black hole

Take, for instance, quantum entanglement. Start by taking two boxes and a Bell pair, putting one of the two particles of the Bell pair into one box and the second particle into the second box. Then repeat this procedure for several Bell pairs. The result is two large scale objects, one in each box, entangled with each other. Then, one can, in principle, create two entangled black holes just by shrinking the two boxes containing the entangled objects.Footnote 21

The second way of constructing entangled black holes goes along the following lines: consider the event horizon of a black hole, and consider the empty space entanglement across the horizon, i.e. the entanglement created by dividing empty space into two halves as in Fig. 2. The left part of Fig. 2 could be considered the black hole’s interior, while the right part the exterior. The presence of a (virtual) particle inside the black hole would imply the presence of its antiparticle outside the horizon. The particle, being outside the horizon, is free to move away from the black hole and indeed, it does so for modes created at sufficiently high energy. This process is equivalent to the emission of a particle from the black hole. Since this process can happen for any number of particles, we end up with an ensemble of Hawking quanta, i.e. particles emitted through vacuum fluctuations across the horizon. This ensemble is called Hawking radiation. By construction then, the cloud of Hawking radiation is entangled with some regions of spacetime inside the black hole. Then one might take the cloud of Hawking radiation and shrink it, to form a second black hole. Therefore we end up with two entangled black holes.

These are two ways to realise (theoretically) a system of two entangled black holes. In the next section, we will look at non-local connectivity between black holes within the framework of GR.

3.3 Einstein–Rosen bridges

The simplest black hole solution one can consider within GR’s framework is the Schwarzschild solution, which describes a black hole without charge and angular momentum, and with spherical symmetry. A straightforward generalisation of the Schwarzschild solution is the Kruskal extension, which is derived just by performing a coordinate transformation on the Schwarzschild black hole metric. The geometrical structure described by the new set of coordinates is still a solution of the vacuum Einstein equations since the metric components are real analytic functions of the coordinates. Defining \(r_\star = r+2M \log \left| \frac{r}{2M}-1 \right| \) (where M is the mass of the black hole and r is the radial coordinate of the Schwarzschild metric), the Kruskal–Szekeres coordinates can be written down as followsFootnote 22

$$\begin{aligned} U= & {} -e^{-\frac{t-r_\star }{4M}}\end{aligned}$$
(3)
$$\begin{aligned} V= & {} e^{\frac{t+r_\star }{4M}}\end{aligned}$$
(4)
$$\begin{aligned} \theta= & {} \theta \end{aligned}$$
(5)
$$\begin{aligned} \phi= & {} \phi , \end{aligned}$$
(6)

where by construction, \(U<0\) and \(V>0\). The black hole metric in the Kruskal–Szekeres coordinate system is then

$$\begin{aligned} ds^2 = -\frac{32 M^3 e^{-r(U,V)/2M}}{r(U,V)}dU\,dV + r(U,V)^2d\varOmega ^2 \end{aligned}$$
(7)

where r(UV) is a solution of the equation

$$\begin{aligned} UV=-e^{-r/(2M)}\left( \frac{r}{2M}-1\right) \end{aligned}$$
(8)

The function r(UV) can have definite values also for \(U\ge 0\) and for \(V\le 0\), i.e. outside the domain in which U and V were defined in (3). Since the metric components of (7) depend only on r(UV), the Schwarzschild solution written in terms of Kruskal–Szekeres coordinates (3) can be analytically extended through the surfaces \(U=0\) and \(V=0\) to new regions of spacetime with \(U>0\) and \(V<0\). The new geometrical structure one obtains through these procedures is still a solution of the vacuum Einstein equations, and it has some interesting features which we can describe through its Penrose diagram (Fig. 4).

Fig. 4
figure 4

This is the Penrose diagram of the Kruskal solution

The Penrose diagram of the Kruskal extension of the Schwarzschild solution underlines some interesting features. The solution has two horizons since \(r=2M\) (the horizon’s position in the Schwarzschild solution) corresponds either to \(U=0\) or \(V=0\). The diagram has four regions:

  • region I is the region for \(r>2M\) of the Schwarzschild black hole, i.e. its exterior;

  • region II is the interior of the Schwarzschild black hole, i.e. the region for \(0<r<2M\). Since the Schwarzschild coordinates break down at the horizon, the appropriate set of coordinates for region II is the Eddington–Finkelstein coordinates \(r^\star = r+ 2GM\ln \left| \frac{r}{2GM}-1\right| \), where r is the Schwarzschild radial coordinate;

  • region III is a region describing a white hole (which however is not relevant for our discussion);

  • region IV is a new region introduced by the analytic continuation performed above, where \(r>2M\).

In both region I and region IV, \(r>2M\), therefore both regions are described by the Schwarzschild solutions, and in particular, they can be understood as the exterior of two Schwarzschild black holes (since \(r>2M\)). So it is like there are two Schwarzschild black holes. Region I and Region IV are disconnected since they are spacelike separated, so it is impossible for an observer in Region I to send a signal in Region IV. The green lines represent r-constant and t-constant hypersurfaces. Moreover, since \(V/U=-e^{t/(2M)}\), a surface of constant t in the new coordinates is just a straight line through the origin of the Penrose diagram, which extends naturally from Region I to Region IV. One can then ask: which is the geometry of these constant time slices? Another change of coordinates is needed to investigate their geometry. We define the new coordinate \(\rho \) in the following way:

$$\begin{aligned} r=\rho +M+\frac{M^2}{4\rho } \end{aligned}$$
(9)

This equation has two solutions, one for \(\rho >M/2\) (which describes Region I) and one for \(0<\rho <M/2\) (which describes Region IV). The Schwarzschild metric, written in this new coordinates, and at constant time, is then

$$\begin{aligned} ds^2 = \left( 1+\frac{M}{2\rho }\right) ^4\left( d\rho ^2+\rho d\varOmega ^2\right) \end{aligned}$$
(10)

This geometry has two asymptotically flat regions for \(\rho \rightarrow \infty \) and \(\rho \rightarrow 0\) connected by a throat of minimum radius 2M. So a surface of constant time in the Kruskal metric is an Einstein–Rosen bridge (Fig. 5).

Fig. 5
figure 5

The left picture shows the Penrose diagram of the Kruskal extension. The right figure shows the \(t=0\) hypersurface in the parametrisation with \(\rho \). Region I and Region IV are respectively located at \(\rho =\infty \) and \(\rho =0\). These are two separate regions of space (it is evident that they are spacelike from the Penrose diagram), but a throat connects them. The blue dot in the Penrose diagram is a sphere \(S^2\), which is the Einstein–Rosen bridge

A bridge geometrically connects these two disconnected regions of space, i.e. there is a continuous path that connects the two disconnected black holes’ interior. Two completely disconnected worlds are connected by an ERB.

To conclude, we just showed a solution of the vacuum Einstein equation which describes a situation in which two disconnected regions are connected through a new geometrical structure, i.e. a wormhole. Since there is no causal curve connecting the two regions, the ERB is a form of non-local connectivity. The bridge has two fundamental properties: first of all, it is pure empty space, i.e. it is not a fancy region of spacetime with some fancy properties, it is made up only of geometry; moreover, it is not traversable, i.e. one cannot walk across the bridge since it would exceed the speed of light.

3.4 ER=EPR

So far, we have seen that black holes can, in principle, be connected through two prima facie significantly different kinds of non-local connectivities: entanglement and ERBs. In this section, we investigate the relations between them. We learnt that ERBs are solutions of the vacuum Einstein equations, which means that they are purely geometrical structures. The fact that they are purely geometrical means the bridge itself is pure empty space. Since it is pure empty space, and since we showed that pure empty space in the quantum theory is intrinsically entangled (via vacuum entanglement), we can consider vacuum entanglement between the two sides of the bridge (Fig. 6).

Fig. 6
figure 6

The figure shows empty-space entanglement across an ERB

This procedure suggests that two black holes that are connected through an Einstein–Rosen bridge are also entangled. This simple reasoning lead Maldacena and Susskind (2013) to formulate what Susskind (2016) calls the modest view of the ER=EPR conjecture:

(MV):

Modest View: Black holes connected by an Einstein–Rosen bridge are entangled. Entangled black holes are connected by an Einstein–Rosen bridge.Footnote 23

That is to say that, when we consider entanglement between two spacelike macroscopic objects and those macroscopic objects get dense, then the entanglement turns into new regions of spacetime. Those regions would not have been there if the systems were not entangled. In other words, there is a one-to-one correspondence between wormholes and entangled black holes, i.e. any entanglement between two black holes corresponds to one particular wormhole geometry and vice versa. The diagram in Fig. 7 can pictorially describe the modest view of the ER=EPR conjecture.

Fig. 7
figure 7

This figure gives a representation of how the modest version of ER=EPR can come about. One should read the panel as ordered from left to right, and from top to bottom

We may ask the following question: is the equivalence between entanglement and ERBs restricted to the case of black holes? Or, in other words, given two entangled particles, does their entanglement turn into a new region of spacetime which connects the two particles? Susskind (2016) calls this the ambitious view of the ER=EPR conjecture:

(AV):

Ambitious View: Some future conception of quantum geometry will allow us to think of two entangled systems as being connected by a Planckian wormhole.

In this definition by Planckian wormhole it is meant a wormhole of Planckian size, i.e. a wormhole for which the mass in (10) is of the same order of the Planck mass and thus invisible for standard experiments dealing with quantum entanglement. (AV) then states a complete equivalence between entanglement and ERBs. (AV) generalises (MV) by extending the correspondence between entangled black holes and wormhole geometry to any entangled systems, i.e. there is a one-to-one correspondence between entangled systems and wormhole geometry.

3.5 Fungibility of entanglement

The ER=EPR conjecture allows us to think about entanglement in a very different way. Susskind (2016) describes entanglement as a fungible resource.

The idea can be stated in terms of entanglement being a “fungible resource.” Entanglement is a resource because it is useful for carrying out certain communication tasks such as teleportation. It is fungible because like energy, which comes in different forms - electrical, mechanical, chemical, etc. - entanglement also comes in many forms which can be transformed into one another. Some forms of entanglement: ground state or vacuum entanglement, entangled particles, Einstein–Rosen bridges, [...]. What about the conservation of the resource? Energy is conserved, but entanglement is not, except under special circumstances. If two systems are distantly separated so that they can’t interact, then the entanglement between them is conserved under independent local unitary transformations. Thus if Alice and Bob, who are far from one another, are each in control of two halves of an entangled system, the unitary manipulations they do on their own shares cannot change the entanglement entropy.

To understand this, let us recall a simple fact that we already mentioned before regarding entangled systems: how to create macroscopic objects displaying entanglement correlations (see Fig. 3). To create a macroscopic object displaying entanglement correlations, we need to take a pair of quantum systems in an entangled state and put each of them in a box. We can repeat this process and then, after adding a sufficiently large number of particles to the boxes, we end up with two entangled macroscopic objects, one for each box. We could then decide to shrink the size of the two boxes and, if we make them small enough, they become entangled black holes. However, since we are in the context of entangled black holes, (MV) applies. Therefore, we can equivalently regard the two black holes as being connected by a wormhole, whose interior geometry encodes their state’s entanglement properties. In this way, we have seen how we can transform two entangled systems in two entangled black holes, thus susceptible to (MV). In this sense, we can say that fungibility is the property which makes possible the transformation from vacuum entanglement to quantum entanglement, to ERBs.

4 Humeanism and ER=EPR

As we showed in Sect. 2, the violation of Separability, i.e. that entanglement relations cannot be understood in terms of the intrinsic states of spacetime points/pointlike objects, together with their spacetime relations, is the cause of the conflict between entanglement and Humeanism. Such a violation is understood as entanglement and spacetime inducing two incompatible causal structures. These two causal structures are different because there are events causally connected in one which are causally disconnected in the other. A straightforward strategy to solve the problem might be eliminating entanglement relations or reducing them to some intrinsic property of quantum objects. Since entanglement is one of the fundamental discoveries of QM, and since we assume a form of entanglement realism,Footnote 24 we think a better strategy is to search for a physical theory that resolves the inconsistency between causal structures induced by spacetime and entanglement. This section aims to argue that ER=EPR gives us the resources to solve the mismatch between these two causal structures. We thus submit that ER=EPR might provide a possible framework to overcome the conflict between entanglement and Humeanism in the context of QG. Or, at the very least, it provides a useful example of how one might think about these issues in QG.

ER=EPR harmonises the two causal structures by unifying a general relativistic spacetime with the entanglement of QM. The two structures are harmonised by associating to any two entangled quantum systems an ERB connecting them, thus assigning a spacetime connection to any entanglement correlation. The wormhole opens the possibility to create a path in spacetime which connects the two entangled quantum systems. This new type of connectivity allows us to supplement the standard spacetime relations (light-cone structure, i.e. the relation \(R_{LC}\) of being connectable by a causal curve).

To formalise the view emerging from the ER=EPR conjecture, starting from our notion of causal structure (CS), we generalise the notion of the causal structure of spacetime to incorporate this new kind of connectivity introduced by the ER=EPR conjecture. The new definition of the causal structure of spacetime is determined by the relation \(R_{ERB}\) of being non trivially connectable in spacetime. We say that there is a non-trivial connection in spacetime if there is (i) a continuous path in spacetime connecting two points p and q such that (ii) the presence of this path determines whether or not there is a robust counterfactual correlation between the systems/points it connects. We call this new causal structure the generalised causal structure of spacetime.

Note that, if we go back to the context of standard Minkowski spacetime, the generalised causal structure of spacetime (and the notion of Separability defined by \(R_{ERB}\)) are equivalent to the notions of the causal structure of spacetime and Separability defined in terms of \(R_{LC}\), i.e. causal curves. Indeed, in Minkowski spacetime, the only paths which can determine whether or not there are robust counterfactual correlations are causal curves, and thus we recover our original definition (and with it the problem of violations of Separability by entanglement). The real advantage of using the generalised causal structure of spacetime is that it captures the causal structure of the spacetimes emerging from ER=EPR. Since the ERBs determine whether two systems are entangled, and in which entangled state they are, they determine whether or not there is a robust counterfactual correlation between the two systems. Thus we can consider the ERBs as non-trivial paths in spacetime, despite being spacelike. To better understand the argument and the nature of this new kind of connectivity encoded by wormholes, let us now consider the ambitious version (AV) and the modest versions (MV) of ER=EPR individually.

4.1 Ambitious ER=EPR

That the two causal structures are harmonised is particularly evident in (AV), since for any two entangled systems we have an associated wormhole connecting them. It is, however, essential to be clear on what is going on in this case. What (AV) says is that, given two entangled quantum systems, they are equivalent to a wormhole. What is important to note, then, is that we are not claiming that there is a wormhole connecting the two systems, but rather that the two entangled systems are equivalent to the wormhole: entanglement is equivalent to a specific type of spacetime connection, encoded via an ERB. The mismatch between the causal structure of entanglement and spacetime is resolved by this equivalence, which allows us to represent entanglement relations with non-trivial spacetime connections, i.e. ERBs, as captured by the generalised causal structure of spacetime. Thus Humeanism is again viable since specifying all the non-trivial spacetime relations in (AV) is equivalent to specifying the entanglement relations. We can determine the state of the world from the generalised causal structure of spacetime, satisfying Separability.

Indeed our reformulation of the problem in terms of causal structures becomes particularly useful in allowing us to see how to resolve it. What (AV) allows us to do is to construct a new causal structure, i.e. the generalised causal structure of spacetime defined by the relation \(R_{ERB}\) of being non trivially connected in spacetime. In the generalised causal structure of spacetime, both the causal structure defined in terms of \(R_{LC}\), i.e. causal curves, and the causal structure defined by \(R_E\), i.e. entanglement relations, can be consistently embedded. Furthermore, this causal structure is still ultimately a spacetime causal structure, given that the relation \(R_{ERB}\) is still a spacetime relation. Let us briefly expand on this point. As noted in Brown (2005), understanding what exactly counts as a piece of spacetime structure is far from obvious. An influential account of how to identify spacetime structure, starting from the work of Brown himself, is that of Knox (2013), who uses it to articulate her preferred version of spacetime functionalism.Footnote 25 In particular, Knox (2019, p. 122) characterises her criterion by saying that “[...] spacetime is whatever serves to define a structure of inertial frames, where inertial frames are those in whose coordinates the laws governing interactions[footnote suppressed] take a simple form (that is universal insofar as curvature may be ignored), and with respect to which free bodies move with constant velocity.”Footnote 26 To see why \(R_{ERB}\) counts as a piece of spacetime structure from this point of view, it is simpler to consider the firewall paradox (Almheiri et al. 2013). In that context, Almheiri et al. (2013) constructed a situation in which the equivalence principle of GR is violated, and thus no local inertial frame in the sense of Knox (2013) can be defined. ER=EPR, and thus \(R_{ERB}\), were introduced for the explicit purpose of avoiding this situation and ensuring the validity of the equivalence principle, a task accomplished with remarkable success (Maldacena and Susskind 2013; Penington 2020). Thus, it is safe to conclude that \(R_{ERB}\) plays a crucial role in determining the structure of local inertial frames and that, following Knox (2013)’s criterion, it counts as a piece of spacetime structure.

The fundamental new tools that (AV) puts at our disposal to reconcile the structure of spacetime with that of entanglement are (i) for each entangled state there is an ERB, and (ii) the features of the entangled state are encoded in the geometry of the wormhole. Thus, in the context of (AV), Humeanism is a viable metaphysical picture of the world again.

4.2 Modest ER=EPR

We can now turn to (MV) and see how in this case entanglement and spacetime can be harmonised, and thus Humeanism saved. Here, the situation is a bit more complicated than in the case of (AV), since we cannot directly embed the two causal structures into a larger one, not in general at least. Indeed, in (MV), we only have a correspondence between entanglement and wormholes for the case of black holes, not for any two quantum systems. This limited correspondence does not allow us to resolve the conflict between entanglement and spacetime as quickly but requires us to be more careful in treating the two causal structures. The fundamental concept that allows us to resolve the problems of Humeanism also in (MV) is that of the fungibility of entanglement explained in Sect. 3.5. In this context, in particular, what we mean when we say that entanglement is a fungible resource is that we can transform entangled systems in entangled black holes which are then, by (MV), connected by wormholes, with the same properties of the original quantum systems. This connection is the core of what we mean, in (MV), when we say that entanglement is fungible.

While for (AV), as noted above, we can simply embed the two causal structures, of spacetime and entanglement, in the generalised causal structure of spacetime, this is not so for (MV), since entanglement and wormholes are not identified. However, the fungibility of entanglement shows that, while not identical, the two causal structures are compatible in a robust sense. Indeed, while not every entanglement relation corresponds to an ERB, we can transform with a sequence of unitary transformation two entangled systems into two black holes connected by a wormhole, with the same properties of the entangled pair, provided that we have a sufficient amount of entangled pairs to carry out constructions along the lines of Sect. 3.2.Footnote 27 For any world with, for example, two entangled systems, there is an equivalentFootnote 28 world with the same overall physical state. There, however, entanglement has been substituted by a wormhole with the same properties. Thus, we can see that even in (MV), Humeanism and entanglement can be reconciled. Fixing spacetime relations, even in the more general sense of \(R_{ERB}\), i.e. non-trivial spacetime connections, might not be enough to determine the physical state of the world since entanglement still does not fall within the purview of this causal structure. Nonetheless, by a finite number of unitary transformations, what we can do is change this entangled system into an equivalent one in which the generalised causal structure of spacetime is sufficient to determine the state of the world, without ever changing it.

The version of Humeanism that emerges is a somewhat weaker one, but still adequate in our opinion to the spirit of Humeanism. While it might not be true that the intrinsic state of spacetime points and their spacetime relations (equivalently, the generalised causal structure of spacetime) is sufficient to determine the physical state of the world, it is nevertheless the case that there is an equivalent world whose generalised spacetime causal structure does determine the global state of the world.Footnote 29 By equivalent, we mean that we can construct the generalised causal structure via a finite sequence of unitary transformations on the two (apparently) contrasting causal structures.

In fewer words, we can take an entangled state and act on it to transform into a wormhole (with the same properties). Thus, there cannot be any deep conflict between spacetime and entanglement’s causal structures, only an apparent one. The dictionary between these two situations, provided by the fungibility of entanglement, guarantees that they are compatible, and thus that entanglement cannot threaten Separability in any significant way.Footnote 30 Thus Humeanism, albeit somewhat weakened, can be saved even if (MV) is retained.

5 In defence of ER=EPR

In this section, we defend the generality of ER=EPR and the viability of constructing a metaphysics based on it. First of all, we observe that doing metaphysics on speculative theories of QG is by now a common practice in the literature (Sect. 5.1), even though the resulting metaphysics is equally speculative. The core of the section is the defence of the claim that the ER=EPR conjecture is rather general since it relies only on gravity’s semiclassical features (Sect. 5.2). We then conclude by noting that wormholes being non-traversable is not a problem for our view (Sect. 5.3).

5.1 ER=EPR and metaphysics

The first, and most natural, criticism of our view is that it crucially depends on the ER=EPR conjecture, a particular, narrow and ultimately unproven conjecture regarding a possible future theory of QG. How can we draw metaphysical lessons from such a speculative and uncertain physics? First of all, let us briefly note that one might object that the dependence on a conjecture such as ER=EPR renders our view empirically falsifiable. In keeping with the methodology of naturalised metaphysics (Ladyman et al. 2007), empirical falsifiability should be one of the main features of an acceptable metaphysical position. From this point of view what seemed a bug of our position, should instead be seen as a feature. While we broadly agree with the perspective of naturalised metaphysics, however, we take that the criticism articulated above is still excessive. While we certainly agree that ER=EPR is ultimately still a conjecture, it is not nearly as far fetched as might appear at first sight. In particular, various experiments have been proposed in recent years which might test various aspects of the ER=EPR conjecture, which might soon be concretely performed in a lab (Nezami et al. 2021; Brown et al. 2021; Dai et al. 2020). Moreover, recent advances in quantum black holes have shown that various black hole models display the features characteristic of ER=EPR (Papadodimas and Raju 2013; Almheiri et al. 2019; Penington 2020; Almheiri et al. 2020c), some of which derived directly from the gravitational path integral (Penington et al. 2019; Almheiri et al. 2020a, b). For these reasons, it seems to us that it is reasonable to begin the project of elucidating some of the metaphysical consequences that ER=EPR seems to suggest about the world, keeping in mind, of course, the unproven nature of the conjecture. Indeed, this type of metaphysical project should be understood as trying to articulate what the (still speculative) physics of QG might be ultimately telling us about reality. Something that has become, if not ordinary, at least broadly accepted in the literature on the metaphysical foundations of QG (Matarese 2019; Vistarini 2019; Wüthrich 2019; Le Bihan 2020; Jaksland 2020). Moreover, the ER=EPR conjecture, and thus the metaphysics based on it, does not rely for its formulation on the details of the (yet to be discovered) theory of QG. Instead, it relies only on (general features of) its expected semiclassical limit and GR’s spacetime picture, as we argue in the next section.

5.2 ER=EPR and semiclassical gravity

Let us now substantiate the claim that ER=EPR does not depend on the details of any specific theory of QG. Indeed, ER=EPR relies only on the semiclassical structure of spacetime. As such, insofar as the conjecture is correct, any QG theory should include it in its semiclassical description of reality.Footnote 31

First of all, let us remember the context in which the ER=EPR conjecture emerged: as a(n ingredient of a) solution to the AMPS paradox (Almheiri et al. 2013), also called the firewall paradox, the latest incarnation of the (in)famous information loss problem for black holes (Wallace 2020). In the specific context of the eternal black hole, ER=EPR works beautifully in resolving the paradox, as shown in Maldacena and Susskind (2013). Furthermore, in such a model, constructed within the AdS/CFT correspondence (Maldacena 1999),Footnote 32 one can prove the conjecture to be true: entanglement between the two horizons (which, from the CFT perspective, are described by two entangled CFTs) of the eternal black hole is equivalent to a wormhole connecting them. ER=EPR, then, is not only a fundamental ingredient in some of the leading solutions to the firewall paradox,Footnote 33 but it has already shown to be valid in some specific models of QG, based on the AdS/CFT duality.

Indeed, more than this can be said. Recent advances in the study of the black hole information paradox have shown that the basic structure of the ER=EPR conjecture can be derived already form the path integral of semiclassical gravity (Penington et al. 2019; Almheiri et al. 2020b, a).Footnote 34 This fact shows that ER=EPR is independent of the specific details of any full theory of QG, given that it is reasonable to expect that any successful theories of QG will recover the path integral of semiclassical gravity, in the appropriate limit. Indeed, this computation gives some evidence in favour of the idea that any theory of QG will include the realisation of the ER=EPR conjecture in its semiclassical limit.

Thus, the features on which we rely in our arguments can be expected to be a part of the semiclassical structure of a future theory of QG, lending a reasonable, though not absolute, degree of credibility to the ER=EPR conjecture and the metaphysics based upon it. Indeed, insofar as we are interested in ER=EPR as a possible guide as to how issues regarding Humeanism might be treated in the context of QG, it seems that the results that we have summarised in this section make the features central to the conjecture and to our argument robust enough that we can at least take them into account for metaphysical theorising. Ultimately, however, any results obtained in this way are conditional on the eventual confirmation of the ER=EPR conjecture or any possible cousin of it that might be instantiated in a future theory of QG.

5.3 ER=EPR and non-traversable wormholes

Let us turn to an objection to the metaphysical proposal that we are advancing. One might be worried that our notion of generalised causal structure is problematic since it relies on non-trivial connections in spacetime via wormholes, and those connections are not causal curves. Indeed, since wormholes, as we have seen in Sect. 3.3, are typically non-traversable, i.e. there cannot be a causal curve through the wormhole (though there are exceptions, see Maldacena et al. (2018)), no signal can be sent from one side to the other of the wormhole.

However, note that all a relation needs to be admitted in the building blocks of the Humean’s metaphysics is that it is a spatiotemporal relation. Moreover, as we showed in Sect. 2, these relations should be part of the causal structure of spacetime, supporting robust counterfactual correlations. For example, standard spacelike connections in Minkowski spacetime are not useful for the Humean since they do not support any robust counterfactual correlations. The relation \(R_{ERB}\) of being connected by a wormhole with such and such interior geometry is a spacetime relation too, as we argued in Sect. 4.1. However, contrary to spacelike connections in Minkowski, the interior geometry of the ERB encodes entanglement properties, captured in the generalised causal structure by the requirement that \(R_{ERB}\) be non-trivial. These two properties of \(R_{ERB}\) allow the Humean to resolve her conflict with entanglement.

Furthermore, the fact that the wormholes are non-traversable is an essential feature of the proposal. If this were not the case, then one would be able to send signals through the wormhole, and thus, given that by the conjecture this should be equivalent to an entangled system, via the entanglement relation. However, the no signalling theorem of QM prohibits such signal transmission via entanglement since it would amount to superluminal information transmission. The fact that wormholes are non-traversable is a feature, not a bug of the proposal. In conclusion, not any spacetime relation can resolve the conflict between Humeanism and entanglement, only those of ER=EPR captured by \(R_{ERB}\) can.

6 Conclusions

In this paper, we have argued that the ER=EPR conjecture can be usefully employed to resolve the apparent contradiction between the metaphysical position of Humeanism and the relation of quantum entanglement. Moreover, we have shown that the notion of causal structure \(\mathbf (CS) \) can be useful in elucidating the conceptual structure of ER=EPR.Footnote 35 Of course, our reliance on such a conjecture brings with itself a certain degree of risk for the conclusion that we draw. Independently of whether or not our argument ultimately succeeds in its goals, it might be the case that ultimately it is the world to show us wrong, by rendering the ER=EPR conjecture false. If this ended up being the case, then the Humean would need to find new avenues to defend her position. We do not claim to have proven Humeanism to be the best metaphysics of the world available. Indeed, we do not even want to claim to have definitively resolved its tensions with entanglement. Instead, in the spirit of naturalised metaphysics, we provided a possible, empirically falsifiable, avenue to connect the metaphysical hypothesis of Humeanism with some of the fascinating aspects of recent research in QG.