Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemic feelings, metacognition, and the Lima problem

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Epistemic feelings like tip-of-the-tongue experiences, feelings of knowing, and feelings of confidence tell us when a memory can be recalled and when a judgment was correct. Thus, they appear to be a form of metacognition, but a curious one: they tell us about content we cannot access, and the information is supplied by a feeling. Evaluativism is the claim that epistemic feelings are components of a distinct, primitive metacognitive mechanism that operates on its own set of inputs. These inputs are heuristics that correlate with the presence of mental content that can’t be accessed directly. I will argue that evaluativism is unmotivated, unsupported, and ill-conceived. I will critique the philosophical and empirical arguments for evaluativism and conclude that there is no reason to posit a distinct mechanism to explain epistemic feelings. I will conclude, however, that epistemic feelings may constitute a nonconceptual form of metacognition, which if true is a significant claim.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This example is taken from Dokic (2012).

  2. Some evaluativists (e.g., Proust, 2013) reserve the term ‘metacognition’ for the System 1 version. This form of metacognition is described in detail in Sect. 2.3. I will use ‘metacognition’ to denote any intentional relation between mental states or processes. Thus, I will refer to theory-theoretic processes (Sect. 2.2) as ‘metacognition’, whereas evaluativists would use ‘metarepresentation’.

  3. Dokic (2012, p. 312, note 16) stops short of committing to the existence of a distinct mechanism, but does commit to what I will call ‘core evaluativism’.

  4. Arango-Munoz (2014a) offers this: “E-feelings are phenomenal experiences that point towards mental capacities, processes, and dispositions of the subject, such as knowledge, ignorance, or uncertainty” (p. 158). We will soon see that every part of this definition is controversial.

  5. Dokic claims that epistemic feelings register “internal physiological conditions and events” (2012, p. 307). Perrin, Michaelian, and Sant’Anna (2020) offer a phenomenological description of the feeling of remembering as one of “pastness, self, causality, and singularity.” In either case the properties picked out are arguably non-mental.

  6. Whether associative strength is a direct access account may depend on how one conceives the metaphysics of the relation.

  7. The traditional claim that memory consists in a “trace” of an original event stored in memory is contested by those who take memory to be an entirely reconstructive process (e.g., Michaelian, 2016). But the issue here is whether memory is the informational source of epistemic feelings, not whether that source is reconstructed or stored.

  8. Hart (1965) and Nelson and Narens (1990) are also cited by evaluativists as the sort of psychological direct-access accounts they oppose (Arango-Munoz, 2019; Proust, 2013). But Hart’s claims about a memory “monitor” are too brief and general to characterize as direct access, and while Nelson and Narens sometimes seem to favor direct access (p. 150) at other times they sound like evaluativists (p. 158).

  9. To take one example of the weaker evidence I will skip, Arango-Munoz (2019) cites work by Whittlesea and Williams (1998, 2001) in support of the claim that feelings of familiarity are causally sensitive to fluency. But Whittlesea and Williams operationalize feelings of familiarity as false alarms on a recognition task. False alarm rates are a first-order phenomenon, not a metacognitive measure.

  10. To take one example, Hertzog et al. (2010) examine varieties of the partial information heuristic, claiming that “All extant theories of FOKs reject the idea that individuals have direct access to information held in memory (p, 772).”

  11. Schwartz and Metcalfe (2010) also point out that the partial information heuristic is “compatible” with direct access.

  12. Carruthers (2011) makes such a distinction and claims that access to one’s own propositional attitudes is indirect, but he is no evaluativist. He denies that epistemic feelings have metacognitive content and suggests a direct causal relationship between memory and action for feelings of knowing (2017).

  13. The model does not posit that subjects access drift rate directly, which would implicitly involve a measure of RT. It posits different response criteria for different confidence levels. Higher quality evidence will tend to hit a higher confidence criterion in a given time interval.

  14. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out.

References

  • Arango-Munoz, S. (2011). Two levels of metacognition. Philosophia, 39, 71–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arango-Munoz, S. (2013). Scaffolded memory and metacognitive feelings. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4, 135–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arango-Munoz, S. (2014b). The nature of epistemic feelings. Philosophical Psychology, 27(2), 193–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arango-Munoz, S. (2014a). Metacognitive feelings, self-ascriptions and mental actions. Philisophical Inquiries, 2(1), 145–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arango-Munoz, S. (2019). Cognitive phenomenology and metacognitive feelings. Mind and Language, 34, 247–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, A. S., Bjork, R. A., & Schwarz, B. L. (1998). The mismeasure of memory: When retrieval fluency is misleading as a metamnemonic index. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 127(1), 55–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, A. S. (1991). A review of the tip-of-the-tongue experience. Psychological Bulletin, 109(2), 204–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, R., & McNeill, D. (1966). The“tip of the tongue”phenomenon. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 5, 325–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2005). Introspection. Philosophical Topics, 33(1), 79–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2008). Knowing that I am thinking. In A. E. Hatzimoysis (Ed.), Self-Knowledge (pp. 105–124). Oxford University Press.

  • Carruthers, P. (2011). The opacity of mind. Oxford University Press.

  • Carruthers, P. (2017). Are epistemic emotions metacognitive? Philosophical Psychology, 30, 58–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cussins, A. (1992). Content, embodiment and objectivity: The theory of cognitive trails. Mind, 101, 651–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Sousa, R. (2009). Epistemic feelings. Mind and matter, 7(2), 139–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dellantonio, S., & Pastore, L. (2019). How can you be sure? Epistemic feelings as a monitoring system for cognitive contents. In A. Nepomuceno Fernández, L. Magnani, F. J. Salguero-Lamillar, C. Barés-Gómez, & M. Fontaine (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in science and technology (pp. 407–426). New York: Springer.

  • Dokic, J. (2012). Seeds of self-knowledge: Noetic feelings and metacognition. In M. Beran, J. Brandl, J. Perner, & J. Proust (Eds.), The foundations of metacognition (pp. 302–321). Oxford University Press.

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. MIT Press.

  • Duke, D., Fiacconi, C. M., & Kohler, S. (2014). Parallel effects of processing fluency and positive affect on familiarity-based recognition decisions for faces. Frontiers in Psychology, 5(328), 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emery, N., Dally, J., & Clayton, S. (2004). Western scrub-jays (Aphelocoma californica) use cognitive strategies to protect their caches from thieving conspecifics. Animal Cognition, 7, 37–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. (2003). In two minds: Dual-process accounts of reasoning. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(10), 454–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J., & Stanovich, K. (2013). Dual-process theories of higher cognition: Advancing the debate. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8(3), 223–241.Feustel, T. C., Shiffrin, R. M., & Salasoo, A. (1983). Episodic and lexical contributions to the repetition effect in word identification. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 112, 309–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finn, B., & Tauber, S. K. (2015). When confidence is not a signal of knowing: How students’ experiences and beliefs about processing fluency can lead to miscalibrated confidence. Educational Psychology Review, 27, 567–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1998). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. Oxford University Press.

  • Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating minds. Oxford University Press.

  • Gopnik, A. (1993). How we know our own minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16, 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graf, L., Mayer, S., & Landwehr, J. (2017). Measuring processing fluency: One versus five items. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 28(3), 393–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greely, N. (2021). Nonconceptual metacognition. Manuscript in preparation.

  • Grimaldi, P., Lau, H., & Basso, M. A. (2015). There are things that we know that we know, and there are things that we do not know we do not know: Confidence in decision-making. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 55, 88–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grush, R. (2000). Self, world and space: The meaning and mechanisms of ego- and allocentric spatial representation. Brain and Mind, 1, 59–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanczakowski, M., Pasek, T., Zawadzka, K., & Mazzoni, G. (2013). Cue familiarity and ‘don’t know’ responding in episodic memory tasks. Journal of Memory and Language, 69, 368–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, J. T. (1965). Memory and the feeling-of-knowing experience. Journal of Educational Psychology, 56(4), 208–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hertzog, C., Dunlosky, J., & Sinclair, S. M. (2010). Episodic feeling-of-knowing resolution derives from the quality of original encoding. Memory & Cognition, 38, 771–784.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hertzog, C., Fulton, E., Sinclair, S., & Dunlosky, J. (2014). Recalled aspects of original encoding strategies influence episodic feelings of knowing. Memory and Cognition, 42, 126–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hosey, L. A., Peynircioglu, Z. F., & Rabinovitz, B. E. (2009). Feeling of knowing for names in response to faces. Acta Psychologica, 130(3), 214–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, F. W., Smith, W. A. S., & Mayfield, J. F. (1956). Tests of two theories of decision in an “expanded judgment” situation. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 51, 261–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isingrini, M., Sacher, M., Perrotin, A., Taconnat, L., Souchay, C., Stoehr, H., & Bouazzaoui, B. (2016). Episodic feeling-of-knowing relies on noncriterial recollection and familiarity. Consciousness and Cognition, 41, 31–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacoby, L. L. (1983). Perceptual enhancement: Persistent effects of a stimulus. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 9(1), 21–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelley, C. M., & Jacoby, L. L. (1998). Subjective reports and process dissociation: Fluency, knowing, and feeling. Acta Psychologica, 98, 127–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiani, R., Corthell, L., & Shadlen, M. (2014). Choice certainty is informed by both evidence and decision time. Neuron, 84(6), 1329–1342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A. (1993). How do we know that we know? The accessibility model of the feeling of knowing. Psychological Review, 100(4), 609–639.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A. (1997). Monitoring one’s own knowledge during study: A cue-utilization approach to judgments of learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 126, 349–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A. (2000). The feeling of knowing: some metatheoretical implications for consciousness and control. Consciousness and Cognition, 9, 149–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A. (2006). Metacognition and consciousness. In P. D. Zelazo, M. Moscovitch, & E. Thompson (Eds.), Cambridge handbook of consciousness (pp. 289–325). Cambridge University Press.

  • Koriat, A., & Ackerman, R. (2010). Metacognition and mindreading: Judgments of learning for self and other during self-paced study. Consciousness and Cognition, 19, 251–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A., & Bjork, R. A. (2005). Illusions of competence in monitoring one’s knowledge during study. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 31(2), 187–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A., & Levy-Sadot, R. (2001). The combined contributions of cue-familiarity and accessibility heuristics to feelings of knowing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 27(1), 34–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A., Nussinson, R., Bless, H., & Shaked, N. (2008). Information-based and experience-based metacognitive judgments. In J. Dunlosky & R. A. Bjork (Eds.), Handbook of metamemory and memory (p. 117–135). Hove: Psychology Press.

  • KoriatMa’ayan, A. H. (2005). The effects of encoding fluency and retrieval fluency on judgments of learning. Journal of Memory and Language, 52(4), 478–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Y., Su, Y., Xu, G., & Chan, R. (2007). Two dissociable aspects of feeling-of-knowing: Knowing that you know and knowing that you do not know. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 60(5), 672–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1689). An essay concerning human understanding. UK: Oxford University Press.

  • Lycan, W. (1996). Consciousness and experience. MIT Press.

  • Metcalfe, J., & Finn, B. (2008). Familiarity and retrieval processes in delayed judgments of learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 34(5), 1084–1097.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metcalfe, J., Schwartz, B. L., & Joaquim, S. G. (1993). The cue-familiarity heuristic in metacognition. Journal of Experimental Philosophy: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 19(4), 851–861.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2016). Mental time travel. MIT Press.

  • Millikan, R. (1987). Language, thought, and other biological categories. MIT Press.

  • Nelson, T. O., & Narens, L. (1990). Metamemory: A theoretical framework and new findings. Psychology of Learning and Motivation, 26, 125–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, T. O., Gerler, D., & Narens, L. (1984). Accuracy of feeling-of-knowing judgments fore predicting perceptual identification and learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 113(2), 282–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • PaynterRederKieffaber, C. A. L. M. P. D. (2009). Knowing before we know: ERP correlates of initial feeling-of-knowing. Neuropsychologica, 47(3), 796–803.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perrin, D., Michaelian, K., & Sant’Anna, A. (2020). The phenomenology of remembering is an epistemic feeling. Frontiers in Psychology, 11(1531), 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, D. (2004). The phenomenology of cognition or what is it like to think that p? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69(1), 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pleskac, T. J., & Busemeyer, J. R. (2010). Two-stage dynamic signal detection: A theory of choice, decision time, and confidence. Psychological Review, 117(3), 864–901.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Proust, J. (2013). The philosophy of metacognition. Oxford University Press.

  • Ratcliff, R. (1978). Theory of memory retrieval. Psychological Review, 85, 59–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliff, R., & Starns, J. J. (2013). Modeling confidence judgments, response times, and multiple choices in decision making: Recognition memory and motion discrimination. Psychological Review, 120(3), 697–719.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reber, R., Fazendeiro, T. A., & Winkielman, P. (2002). Processing fluency as the source of experiences at the fringe of consciousness. Psyche, 8(10), 175–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reder, L. M., & Ritter, F. E. (1992). What determines initial feeling of knowing? Familiarity with question terms, not with the answer. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 18, 435–451.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, B. L. (2010). The effects of emotion on tip-of-the-tongue states. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 17, 82–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, B. L., & Metcalfe, J. (2010). Tip-of-the-tongue (TOT) states: Retrieval, experience, and behavior. Memory and Cognition, 39(5), 737–749.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, N., Bless, H., Strack, F., Klumpp, G., Rittenauer-Schatka, H., & Simons, A. (1991). Ease of retrieval as information: Another look at the availability heuristic. Journal of Personality & Social Psychology, 61, 195–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siedlecka, M., Paulewicz, B., & Wierzchon, M. (2016). But I was so sure! Metacognitive judgments are less accurate given prospectively than retrospectively. Frontiers in Psychology, 7(218), 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals. Methuen.

  • Thomas, A., & K., Bulevich, J. B., & Dubois, S. J. . (2012). An analysis of the determinants of feelings of knowing. Consciousness and Cognition, 21, 1681–1694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vickers, D., & Lee, M. D. (1998). Dynamic models of simple judgments I Properties of a self-regulating accumulator module. Nonlinear Dynamics, Psychology, and Life Sciences, 2(3), 169–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Volkman, J. (1934). The relation of the time of judgment to the certainty of judgment. Psychological Bulletin, 31, 672–673.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, M. M., & Anderson, J. R. (2009). The strategic nature of changing your mind. Cognitive Psychology, 58(3), 416–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittlesea, B. W. A., & Williams, L. D. (1998). Why do strangers feel familiar, but friends don’t? A discrepancy-attribution account of feelings of familiarity. Acta Psychologica, 98, 141–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittlesea, B. W. A., & Williams, L. D. (2001). The discrepancy-attribution hypothesis: The heuristic basis of feelings of familiarity. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 27(1), 3–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winkielman, P., Schwarz, N., Fazendeiro, T. A., & Reber, R. (2003). The hedonic marking of processing fluency: Implications for evaluative judgment. In J. Musch & K. C. Klauer (Eds.), The psychology of evaluation: Affective processes in cognition and emotion (pp. 189–217). Earlbaum.

  • Yu, S., Pleskac, T. J., & Zeigenfuse, M. D. (2015). Journal of Experimental Psychology, 144(2), 489–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Matthew Fulkerson, Eric Schwitzgebel, David Barner, Jonathan Cohen, Rick Grush, audiences at the 2020 meeting of the Southern Society for Philosophy and Psychology, and several anonymous referees for their comments on earlier versions of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nathaniel Greely.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Greely, N. Epistemic feelings, metacognition, and the Lima problem. Synthese 199, 6803–6825 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03094-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03094-8

Keywords

Navigation