Skip to main content
Log in

Some fallibilist knowledge: Questioning knowledge-attributions and open knowledge

  • Themes from Elgin
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We may usefully distinguish between one’s having fallible knowledge and having a fallibilist stance on some of one’s knowledge. A fallibilist stance could include a concessive knowledge-attribution (CKA). But it might also include a questioning knowledge-attribution (QKA). Attending to the idea of a QKA leads to a distinction between what we may call closed knowledge that p and open knowledge that p. All of this moves us beyond Elgin’s classic tale of the epistemic capacities of Holmes and of Watson, and towards a way of resolving Kripke’s puzzle about dogmatism and knowing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, Reed (2002, 2012), Fantl and McGrath (2009, pp. 7–15), Dougherty (2011), and Hetherington (1999, 2005, 2016b, 2018).

  2. Pasnau (2017, pp. 121–126) argues that even God’s knowledge would at best be fallible, since God could not help but ask whether His knowledge really is knowledge. In this paper’s terms, this might be better interpreted as God’s knowledge being fallibilist—thanks to His viewing his knowledge in some fallibilist terms.

  3. This will not involve entering into all of the suggestion’s aspects. Elgin discusses mainly understanding a domain of inquiry, rather than (as will be this paper’s topic) knowledge of a single state of affairs. The concept of knowledge cannot do justice to the reality of scientific progress, argues Elgin: for a start, knowledge entails truth, whereas scientific understanding does not. Actually, as I explain elsewhere (2011, Sect. 5.15), knowledge and understanding might not be so far apart in nature. But none of this matters for my argument here. Nor will I be arguing for the correctness of fallibilism as a stance. My aim is to expand upon this basic idea of Elgin’s (describing fallibilism as ‘a stance’—in the sense of ‘an active orientation toward … inquiry’), by investigating one associated explicative path that a fallibilist might follow. (I have offered defences of fallibilist thinking elsewhere: 2001, 2002, 2013.).

  4. Others who do so include Kaplan (1985) and Johnsen (2017).

  5. Just to remind ourselves: Elgin discussed causal theories of knowledge (Goldman 1967, 1976) and reliabilist theories (Dretske 1971; Nozick 1981), along with (internalistic) coherence (Lehrer 1974, 1986) and defeasibility theories, including social defeasibility theories (Harman 1973; Cohen 1986).

  6. It is perhaps a virtue that Holmes himself would have scorned, since (as we will find) it involves self-questioning, and since Doyle, his literary creator, left us in no doubt as to Holmes’s intellectual arrogance. As I mentioned, Elgin regarded Holmes’s epistemic superiority—other than as a knower (given, she argued, how this was being conceived of by various representative forms of epistemological theory)—as reflecting significant deficiencies in knowledge’s nature, rather than in Holmes. As Elgin was interpreting the case, if Holmes lacks knowledge because he has various epistemic qualities not viewed by those epistemological theories as constitutive of knowing, then epistemology should be altered to be about such qualities, instead of remaining so much about knowledge; and, in any event, knowledge is thereby an attainment that is itself lessened in stature, given its ready availability to Watson and not Holmes. Even without engaging directly with Elgin’s Holmes/Watson argument, then, if we wish to maintain an epistemological focus on knowledge, we should take from her argument this potentially useful challenge: namely, conceive of knowledge in a more subtle way, a way that can do justice to Holmes’s superior intellect (if we could prevail upon him to set aside his intellectual arrogance). The conception to be presented in this paper should help in that respect.

  7. For some discussions of concessive knowledge-attributions and fallibilism, see Stanley (2005), Dougherty and Rysiew (2009), and Dodd (2010).

  8. We might ultimately want to defend a stronger—non-minimal—conception, such as ‘All knowledge is fallible’ or even ‘Necessarily, all knowledge is fallible.’ This paper’s discussion does not need to engage directly with any such stronger conceptions.

  9. How often do people often actually utter or think concessive knowledge-attributions? I do not know. Nor does it matter, for our immediate purposes. Epistemologists discuss concessive knowledge-attributions with another question in mind: if a concessive knowledge-attribution was to be offered, would it be a coherent thought or utterance? If it can be, then knowledge-fallibilism passes at least this test of its own coherence – hence of its at least possibly being true.

  10. But see Hetherington (2013) for an extended discussion of concessive knowledge-attributions.

  11. What is the nature of this entailment? Is it conceptual? Is it metaphysical? Is it logical? I will treat it as conceptual, given how readily epistemologists characterize their project of understanding knowledge’s nature as being an exercise in conceptual analysis. And I will take it that conceptual entailments include a clarity component, rendering any denial of such an entailment clearly mistaken—clearly enough that the denial would cause conceptual confusion or consternation, for a start.

  12. I talk here of ‘evidence’ to reflect (generically) an internalist focus, and of ‘any other justificatory means’ to do (generic) justice to an externalist’s approach. So, my aim is to be discussing (albeit generically) all kinds of justificatory component within the initially claimed knowledge. On the difference between epistemic internalism and epistemic externalism, see Conee and Feldman (2001), Bergmann (2006), Coppenger and Bergmann (2016), and Hetherington (1996: chs, 14, 15; forthcoming b).

  13. Incidentally, this lack of a guarantee does not depend on p’s being only contingently true. Even a necessarily true p can be known fallibly. When this occurs, it reflects something of the means by which the (true) belief has been formed: for example, a false belief could have been formed instead of the (necessarily) true one that has actually been formed. Even one’s attending and responding only to one’s evidence, say, need not have resulted in one’s forming the true belief that p.

  14. Moreover, recognising this previously unnoticed category of knowledge has epistemological benefits. Section 6 will describe one of them.

  15. Does this make a questioning knowledge-state a higher-order knowledge-state? I do not think of it in quite that way. It is knowing while also asking whether one knows. So, this is not one’s knowing that one knows, for instance—a paradigmatic higher-order knowledge-state. It need not even be an awareness of one’s knowing. As far as the knower is concerned, it could amount simply to her asking whether she knows; it just so happens that she does this while in fact she does know.

  16. On the general idea of an extended knowing-state, see Hetherington (2012).

  17. For more on the proper basing relation, see Hetherington (forthcoming a).

  18. I realise that this not a problem if we do not need to accept that there could be both open knowledge that p and closed knowledge that p. At this stage of the paper, I am relying on the foregoing (if programmatic) motivation for adding that distinction to our epistemology.

  19. For the initial such account, see Lehrer and Paxson (1969). For some refinements, see Pollock (1986). For a recent version, see de Almeida and Fett (2016).

  20. For prominent such conceptions, see Zagzebski (1996), Sosa (2007), and Greco (2010).

  21. It might be asked whether I am being too dismissive too quickly of too much contemporary epistemology; after all, not all prominent sorts of theory of knowledge have been considered in this section’s argument. But I am not being ‘too dismissive’, because I am not arguing that existing theories could not be expanded to encompass this paper’s suggestion. I am not advocating an overthrow of traditional epistemology; I am noting simply some respects in which epistemology can be modified. [Still, for arguments that do develop reasons to be more deeply suspicious of some key aspects of contemporary epistemology, see Hetherington (2011, 2016a).] Moreover, I do not claim to have discussed all currently prominent sorts of theory of knowledge. Like Elgin’s, my approach is programmatic, talking about just some representative sorts of theory of knowledge.

  22. It was through Harman (1973, pp. 147–149) that most epistemologists first became aware of this Kripkean puzzle.

  23. Thanks to three referees from this journal, for their probing and extensive comments on an earlier version of this paper.

References

  • Bergmann, M. (2006). Justification without awareness: A defense of epistemic externalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1986). Knowledge and context. The Journal of Philosophy, 83, 574–585.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2001). Internalism defended. In H. Kornblith (Ed.), Epistemology: Internalism and externalism (pp. 231–260). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coppenger, B., & Bergmann, M. (Eds.). (2016). Intellectual assurance: Essays on traditional epistemic internalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Almeida, C., & Fett, J. R. (2016). Defeasibility and gettierization: A reminder. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94, 152–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodd, D. (2010). Confusion about concessive knowledge attributions. Synthese, 172, 381–396.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty, T. (2011). Fallibilism. In S. Bernecker & D. Pritchard (Eds.), The Routledge companion to epistemology (pp. 131–143). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty, T., & Rysiew, P. (2009). Fallibilism, epistemic possibility, and concessive knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78, 123–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1971). Conclusive reasons. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 49, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. Z. (1988). The epistemic efficacy of stupidity. Synthese 74: 297–311. Reprinted in N. Goodman & C.Z. Elgin (1988), Reconceptions in Philosophy and Other Arts and Sciences (pp. 135–152). Indianapolis: Hackett. (Page references in this paper are to that reprinting.)

  • Elgin, C. Z. (2017). True enough. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2009). Knowledge in an uncertain world. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2013). Question-directed attitudes. Philosophical Perspectives, 27, 145–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1967). A causal theory of knowing. The Journal of Philosophy, 64, 357–372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, 73, 771–791.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (1996). Knowledge puzzles: An introduction to epistemology. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (1999). Knowing failably. The Journal of Philosophy, 96, 565–587.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2001). Good knowledge, bad knowledge: On two dogmas of epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2002). Fallibilism and knowing that one is not dreaming. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 32, 83–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2005). ‘Fallibilism’. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/f/fallibil.htm.

  • Hetherington, S. (2008). Knowing-that, knowing-how, and knowing philosophically. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 77, 307–324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2011). How to know: A practicalist conception of knowledge. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2012). The extended knower. Philosophical Explorations, 15, 207–218.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2013). Concessive knowledge-attributions: Fallibilism and gradualism. Synthese, 190, 2835–2851.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2016a). Knowledge and the Gettier problem. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2016b). Understanding fallible warrant and fallible knowledge: Three proposals. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 97, 270–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2018). Skepticism and fallibilism. In D. Machuca & B. Reed (Eds.), Skepticism: From antiquity to the present (pp. 609–619). London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (forthcoming a). ‘The epistemic basing relation and knowledge-that as knowledge-how’. In P. Bondy & J. A. Carter (Eds.), Well-founded belief: New essays on the epistemic basing relation. New York: Routledge.

  • Hetherington, S. (forthcoming b). The grounds of one’s knowledge need not be accessible to one. In S. Cowan (Ed.), Introduction to philosophical problems, Vol. 1: Contemporary debates. London: Bloomsbury.

  • Johnsen, B. (2017). Righting epistemology: Hume’s revolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, M. (1985). It’s not what you know that counts. The Journal of Philosophy, 82, 350–363.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (2011). Philosophical troubles: Collected papers (Vol. I). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1974). Knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1986). The coherence theory of knowledge. Philosophical Topics, 14, 5–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K., & Paxson, T. D. (1969). Knowledge: Undefeated justified true belief. The Journal of Philosophy, 66, 225–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 549–567.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pasnau, R. (2017). After certainty: A history of our epistemic ideals and illusions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (1986). Contemporary theories of knowledge. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1966 [1945]). The open society and its enemies, Vol. I: The spell of Plato (5th edn.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, B. (2002). How to think about fallibilism. Philosophical Studies, 107, 143–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, B. (2012). Fallibilism. Philosophy Compass, 7(9), 585–596.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. I). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2009). Reflective knowledge: Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. II). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Fallibilism and concessive knowledge attributions. Analysis, 65, 126–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. T. (1996). Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephen Hetherington.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hetherington, S. Some fallibilist knowledge: Questioning knowledge-attributions and open knowledge. Synthese 198, 2083–2099 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02194-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02194-w

Keywords

Navigation