Skip to main content
Log in

Embodied cognition and temporally extended agency

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to radical versions of embodied cognition, human cognition and agency should be explained without the ascription of representational mental states. According to a standard reply, accounts of embodied cognition can explain only instances of cognition and agency that are not “representation-hungry”. Two main types of such representation-hungry phenomena have been discussed: cognition about “the absent” and about “the abstract”. Proponents of representationalism have maintained that a satisfactory account of such phenomena requires the ascription of mental representations. Opponents have denied this. I will argue that there is another important representation-hungry phenomenon that has been overlooked in this debate: temporally extended planning agency. In particular, I will argue that it is very difficult to see how planning agency can be explained without the ascription of mental representations, even if we grant, for the sake of argument, that cognition about the absent and abstract can. We will see that this is a serious challenge for the radical as well as the more modest anti-representationalist versions of embodied cognition, and we will see that modest anti-representationalism is an unstable position.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This formulation is sufficiently general and precise in order to set the scene, as it were. According to a more general version, all instances of cognition and agency, including non-human cognition and agency, are to be explained in terms of mental representations. According to a less general version, core cases of human cognition and agency are to be explained in terms of mental representations.

  2. There is an alternative minimal characterization, according to which mental representations are agent-internal physical states that are the vehicles of content. There is no apparent advantage in appealing to content, as opposed to aboutness, as those two notions are very closely related and as they are both as much in need of explanation as the notion of mental representation itself. Some may prefer the formulation in terms of an internal stand in, as opposed to a physical vehicle, because it avoids the explicit commitment to physicalism.

  3. Davidson gives the example of an agent who adds spice to a stew with the intention of improving the taste, and he claims that what is required for this to be an intentional action is only that “he must have attitudes and beliefs from which, had he been aware of them and had the time, he could have reasoned that his action was desirable” (1978, p. 85).

  4. In a similar proposal, Clark (1997) introduced the notion of “action oriented representations”: representations that “simultaneously describe aspects of the world and prescribe possible action, and are poised between pure control structures and passive representations of external reality” (1997, p. 49). They are assumed to be both belief-like and desire-like, and their primary explanatory import is to explain the smooth and effortless execution of the motor skills that are characteristic of skilled coping. Others posit similar representational entities, such as “motor intentions”, “motor representations”, or “goal representations”. See Pacherie (2008), Adams (2010) and Butterfill and Sinigaglia (2012).

  5. Fodor and Pylyshyn (1988) appealed to systematicity and compositionality in order to argue for a classical symbol processing account of representationalism and for the language of thought hypothesis, in particular. My point here is much more modest: the complex hierarchical systematicity of planning agency seems to call for a representational theory of cognition and agency. No further claims about symbol processing or about a language of thought are implied.

  6. This is how I understand Clark and Toribio’s (1994) challenge. They took themselves to have identified a serious challenge, not an unassailable proof that establishes an impossibility.

  7. This is traditional behaviorism, according to which the ascription of mental states can be analyzed in terms of the ascription of behavioral dispositions. This view is untenable for well-known reasons. In this section, I argue that it is untenable for further and independent reasons concerning planning agency.

  8. I do not mean to suggest that behavioral dispositions are entirely inflexible. It must be acknowledged, on all views, that particular manifestations of behavioral dispositions can be sensitive to the particular constraints of the situation and that they can exhibit some flexibility in the expression of the type. But this does not ground the ascription of the kinds of contents under consideration here.

  9. No doubt, some anti-representationalists will deny this (in particular, enactivists such as Fuchs and De Jaegher 2009). I will not attempt here to bolster the arguments from Tomasello (and colleagues), but note instead that my main objection is the point that follows.

  10. Hutto and Myin (2013, pp. 137–138) also appeal to scaffolded abilities, but they appear to reject the view that such abilities become internalized. On their view, mental arithmetic, and other cases of mental agency, are “decoupled” and “independent of context” (pp. 152–153). It has not become clear to me why this is supposed to show that mental abilities are not internalized in a way that raises a representation-hunger challenge. But, in any case, the important point here is that denying internalization is of no help in the present context, because only the internalization of linguistic and socially scaffolded abilities has the potential to explain planning agency.

  11. Kaplan and Craver (2011) argue that dynamical system descriptions are explanatory only if they indicate how the system parameters correspond to the interacting parts of an underlying causal mechanism. If correct, this undermines the view of most proponents of the dynamical systems approach, because they usually hold that the parameters correspond to emergent properties of system-environment couplings (not to the components of an underlying mechanism). I tend to agree with Kaplan and Craver, but I assume, for the sake of argument, that dynamical system descriptions can provide explanations independently of identifying causal mechanisms.

  12. Butterfill and Sinigaglia (2012) point out that such explanations face a difficult “interface problem”: how do the propositional contents of intentions interface with the non-propositional contents of motor representations (at the sub-personal level)? They consider a solution in terms of “translation”: a sub-personal mechanism may translate the contents of intentions into the more specific format of the contents of motor representations (see also Pacherie 2008). But as we have currently no direct evidence for the existence of such a mechanism, they advance an alternative explanation in terms of “deference”: intentions refer to specific motor actions by deferring to motor representations.

  13. According to Dreyfus, “there can be two distinct kinds of intentional behavior: deliberative, planned action, and spontaneous, transparent coping” (2002b, p. 417). This raises the obvious question of how skilled coping can be in the service of planning agency, and Dreyfus realizes that he cannot allow guidance by higher intentions and plans (because this would be guidance by mental representations). Dreyfus finds himself forced to propose that higher intentions and plans “simply trigger” instances of skilled coping. But this is highly implausible. It flies in the face of common experience, which suggests that instances of skilled coping are often also guided, modulated, and constrained by higher intentions and plans during their execution. Moreover, even a mere triggering has clearly explanatory import: if skilled coping is triggered by higher intentions and plans, then it is to be explained, at least in part, in terms of mental representations.

  14. As noted (footnote 4), the appeal to action-oriented representations serves the same purpose as the appeal to motor schemata, motor programs, and the feedback-comparator system of motor control.

References

  • Adams, F. (2010). Action theory meets embodied cognition. In A. Buckareff & J. Aguilar (Eds.), Causing human action: New perspectives on the causal theory of action (pp. 229–252). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. J., & Vancouver, J. B. (1996). Goal constructs in psychology: Structure, process, and content. Psychological Bulletin, 120, 338–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (1995). A dynamical systems perspective on agent-environment interaction. Artificial Intelligence, 72, 173–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. E. (1987). Intention, plans, and practical reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. E. (2000). Reflection, planning, and temporally extended agency. Philosophical Review, 109, 35–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S. A., & Sinigaglia, C. (2012). Intention and motor representation in purposive action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 119, 119–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, T. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101, 401–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2010). Skilled activity and the causal theory of action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80, 523–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clowes, R. W., & Mendonça, D. (2016). Representation redux: Is there still a useful role for representation to play in the context of embodied, dynamicist and situated theories of mind? New Ideas in Psychology, 40, 26–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons, and causes. Reprinted in Davidson 1980 (pp. 3–20).

  • Davidson, D. (1978). Intending. Reprinted in Davidson 1980 (pp. 83–102).

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Degenaar, J., & Myin, E. (2014). Representation hunger revisited. Synthese, 191, 3639–3648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (1991). Being-in-the-world: A commentary on Heidegger’s being and time, division I. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2002a). Intelligence without representation: Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2002b). Refocusing the question: Can there be skillful action without propositional representations or brain representations. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 413–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition, 28, 3–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D., Blakemore, S., & Wolpert, D. M. (2000). Abnormalities in the awareness and control of action. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 355, 1771–1788.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T., & De Jaegher, H. (2009). Enactive intersubjectivity: Participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8, 465–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008). Are minimal representations still representations? International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 16, 351–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gollwitzer, P. M., & Sheeran, P. (2006). Implementation intentions and goal achievement: A meta-analysis of effects and processes. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 38i, 69–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1991). Representational genera. In W. Ramsey, S. Stich, & D. Rumelhart (Eds.), Philosophy and connectionist theory (pp. 61–90). New Jersey: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2014). Neural representations not needed: No more pleas, please. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 13, 241–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huys, R., Daffertshofer, A., & Beek, P. J. (2004). The evolution of coordination during skill acquisition: The dynamical systems approach. In A. M. Williams, N. J. Hodges, & M. Scott (Eds.), Skill acquisition in sport: Research, theory and practice (pp. 351–373). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (1997). The cognitive neuroscience of action. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Juarrero, A. (2010). Intentions as complex dynamical attractors. In J. H. Aguilar & A. A. Buckareff (Eds.), Causing human actions: New perspectives on the causal theory of action (pp. 253–276). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. F. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical and mathematical models in neuroscience: A mechanistic perspective. Philosophy of Science, 78, 601–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markman, A. B., & Dietrich, E. (2000). In defense of representation. Cognitive Psychology, 40, 138–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (2009). Effective intentions: The power of conscious will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. A. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbounded. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. A. (2010). Introduction to the special issue on 4E cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 459–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2008). The phenomenology of action: A conceptual framework. Cognition, 107, 179–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein, M., & Chemero, A. (2011). Dynamics, agency and intentional action. Humana Mente, 15, 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2010). Minds: Extended or scaffolded? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 465–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., & Moll, H. (2005). Understanding and sharing intentions: The origins of cultural cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 675–691.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 92, 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. (1986). Thought and language (Newly Edited by A. Kozulin). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world: The next step. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, D. M., & Kawato, M. (1998). Multiple paired forward and inverse models for motor control. Neural Networks, 11, 1317–1329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Markus E. Schlosser.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schlosser, M.E. Embodied cognition and temporally extended agency. Synthese 195, 2089–2112 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1320-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1320-4

Keywords

Navigation