Skip to main content
Log in

Behavioral economics and the Virginia school of political economy: overlaps and complementarities

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

The classical theory of omniscient rationality is strikingly simple and beautiful. Moreover, it allows us to predict (correctly or not) human behavior without stirring out of our armchairs to observe what such behavior is like. All the predictive power comes from characterizing the shape of the environment in which the behavior takes place. The environment, combined with the assumptions of perfect rationality, fully determines the behavior. Behavioral theories of rational choice - theories of bounded rationality - do not have this kind of simplicity.

Herbert Simons, Nobel Address (1978, p. X)

The rational ideal eliminates choice, as Shackle [1969] emphasizes. Choice requires the presence of uncertainty for its very meaning. But choice also implies a moral responsibility for action. To rationalize or explain choices in terms of either genetic endowments or social environment removes the elements of freedom and responsibility. “Natural man,” in the model of some behavioral responder to stimuli, akin to my dog, contradicts both the notion of individual liberty and that of individual responsibility for the consequences of the choices made. Man must bear the responsibilities for his own choices because of his artifactual nature.

James Buchanan (1978/1999, p. 257)

Abstract

A variety of complementarities and overlaps exist between the psychological strand of behavioral economics and the subjectivist strand of Virginia Political Economy. This paper provides an overview of those commonalities and places them in a common information processing framework. The framework can account for systematic mistakes, framing effects, subjectivity, individual variety, and several issues in constitutional political economy. It also reveals many commonalities between these two quite different approaches to human behavior.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I hesitate to cite specific works by these prolific scholars as typical of their research—or at least those parts that I am referring to here. The best overviews of their research is provided by Nobel lectures in cases in which a scholar has won that prize, as with Simon (1979) and Kahneman (2002). A good place start with the other two scholars is Thaler (1980) and with Tversky’s joint work with Kahneman: Tversky and Kahneman (1973, 1986).

  2. Again, it with great hesitation that I point to one or two works out of a lifetime of scholarship. For Smith, one should begin with his 2003 Nobel address; for Plott a good place to start is with his 2014 overview of the early days of experimental public choice research.

  3. There are several very lengthy compendia of the works of the Jeremy Bentham and Herbert Spencer. However, a good place to start is with Bentham (1789). Herbert Spencer’s works are also voluminous; I suggest beginning with his first successful book, Spencer (1851) and focus on the sections dealing with the evolution of the physical and social sources of utility.

  4. Information-processing models of the mind had previously played central roles in adaptive models of economics. They are also central to a strand of post-World War II psychological research. See, for example, Kahneman (2002, 2011), Pinker (1999, 2003) and Seligman et al. (2016). Informationally bounded rationality also affected economics and politics, as in Stigler (1961), Downs (1960), and Denzau and North (1994), the latter being the most encompassing of the early discussions by economists. Congleton (1978) is among the first general explorations of informationally bounded choice within the Virginia school.

  5. A useful example of the super-rational approach to political economy is Wittman’s (1995) book on the impossibility of democratic failure.

  6. The Virginia school has its roots in two centers: the Thomas Jefferson Center for the Studies in Political Economy and Social Philosophy at the University of Virginia and the Center for Study of Public Choice at the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University and George Mason University (to which it relocated in the early 1980 s).

    This essay focuses for the most part on scholars directly associated with these “Centers”, but it bears noting that the Virginia school also includes persons without long affiliations with those centers, such as Mancur Olson, Elinor Ostrom, Dennis Mueller, Charles Goetz, Charles Plott, Geoffrey Brennan, Bruno Frey, Peter Bernholz, Arye Hillman, Randall Holcombe, Gephard Kirchgässner and Michael Munger—many of whom are past visitors to the Center for Study of Public Choice, graduates of its Ph.D. programs, or regular presenters in its seminar series. I am a long-term affiliate—having variously been a student, graduate, research associate and center director during a period spanning more than four decades.

  7. For overviews, see Houser and Stratmann (2012), Plott (2014), Kamm and Schram (2018), or Tyran and Wagner (2018). For a thorough overview of tensions between mainstream rational choice models and experimental results, see Ostrom (1998).

  8. By “natural ignorance” is meant the state of individual knowledge at birth. As mentioned in the text, we are born largely ignorant of all things. Some knowledge is acquired without intent, as for example, that imparted by our parents and stumbled on by accident. Other is consciously sought and acquired. “Rational ignorance” is that part of one’s ignorance that is chosen. That is to say, it exists in cases in which one consciously decides not to pursue a type of information known to exist—such as the Chinese alphabet (for most persons not of Asian descent), quantum mechanics (for those other than professional physicists), and the color of a contemporary rock star’s eyes (for all but the most devoted fans), and so forth. These are cases in which a type or class of information is known to exist, but we (or most of us) choose to remain ignorant.

  9. Such differences would exist even if we were all perfectly rational Bayesians because our direct experiences in life provide only relatively small samples of the choice settings confronted by human beings and the phenomena that we refer to as the “real world”. If our informational systems are not fundamentally Bayesian, no such convergence would necessarily follow from even very large samples.

    For applications of the Bayesian approach to economics, see Stoneman (1981); for an early application to public choice, see Congleton (1991). More recently, Bayesian learning has played a key role in machine-learning algorithms; see Taylor and Stone (2009) or Ghavamzadeh et al. (2015). Many economists and game theorists use Baysesian updating as their reference point for rationality and the absence of long-term bias, as for example, in Charness and Chetan (2017).

  10. This expression evidently was the invention of Ralph Waldo Emerson (1849), who argues that one should not worry about consistency, but then concludes that “There will be an agreement in whatever variety of actions, so they be each honest and natural in their hour. For of one will, the actions will be harmonious, however unlike they seem.” The potential irrationality of political decisionmaking was emphasized more recently by Black (1948) and Arrow (1951), who noted that political choices may be inconsistent even if the choices of individual voters are entirely self-consistent. The consistency (or lack thereof) of collective choice captured much of the attention and imagination of public choice theorists for its first four decades.

  11. It should be acknowledged that few mainstream economists actually believe that consumers behave entirely self-consistently or that every individual behaves in a manner that can be regarded as having emerged from fully informed and consistent plans, but many do believe that models based on those assumptions provide useful insights into both individual decisionmaking and political-economic systems.

  12. Downs (1960) also implicitly used natural ignorance to suggest the possibility of biased expectations or complete ignorance about the costs and benefits of government policies. Note that this differed from Stigler’s (1961) theory of the demand for information, which is essentially a demand for sample sizes, from which unbiased estimates would always be possible, albeit with larger error terms associated with smaller samples. Congleton (2001) clarifies this distinction.

  13. My use of the term “clusters” may make it sound as if a sharp break exists among groups of individuals or researchers. Clusters of researchers or research circles are more like colors than atoms. That is to say, they are (improper) subsets along a continuum of research interests and approaches that are sufficiently similar to be identified as a category, rather than completely non-overlapping groups. In Denzau and North’s (1994) terms, members of such categories share mental models.

  14. This is not entirely a coincidence–Sunstein has long served on the editorial board of Constitutional Political Economy.

References

  • Arrow, K. J. (1951). Social choice and individual values. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, J. (1789/2013). An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. (Reprinted from Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham, Minerva Classics, Kindle Edition).

  • Black, D. (1948). On the rationale of group decision-making. Journal of Political Economy, 56(1), 23–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1985/2008). The reason of rules: Constitutional political economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1958). Public principles of public debt a defense and restatement. Homewood, IL: Irwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1978/1999). Natural and artifactual man. The collected works of James M. Buchanan, Vol 1, The logical foundations of constitutional liberty. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1979). General implications of subjectivism in economics. What Should Economists Do?. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Congleton, R. D. (1998/2006). Politics by principle, not interest: Towards nondiscriminatory democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent. Ann Arbor MI: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Vanberg, V. J. (2002). Constitutional implications of radical subjectivism. Review of Austrian Economics, 15(2–3), 121–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charness, G., & Chetan, D. (2017). Confirmation bias with motivated beliefs. Games and Economic Behavior, 104(July), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Congleton, R. D. (1978). The role of information in choice. Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University Dissertation.

  • Congleton, R. D. (1991). Ideological conviction and persuasion in the rent-seeking society. Journal of Public Economics, 44(1), 65–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Congleton, R. D. (2001). Rational ignorance, rational voter expectations, and public policy: A discrete informational foundation for fiscal illusion. Public Choice, 107(1–2), 35–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Congleton, R. D. (2019). Toward a rule-based model of human choice: On the nature of homo constitutionalus. In R. E. Wagner (Ed.), James M. Buchanan: A theorist of political economy and social philosophy. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Congleton, R. D., & Hillman, A. L. (2015). Companion to the political economy of rent seeking. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G. (1959). Theory of value: An axiomatic analysis of economic equilibrium. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Denzau, A. T., & North, D. C. (1994). Shared mental models: Ideologies and institutions. Kyklos, 47(1), 3–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs, A. (1960). Why the government budget is too small in a democracy. World Politics, 12(4), 541–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emerson, R. W. (1849). Self-reliance. (Reprinted from Emerson, Ralph Waldo. Self-Reliance and Other Essays, Kindle Edition, 2017, Seattle WA: Amazon Classics).

  • Ghavamzadeh, M., Mannor, S., Pineau, J., & Tamar, A. (2015). Bayesian reinforcement learning: A survey. Foundations and Trends in Machine Learning, 8(5–6), 359–483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heiner, R. A. (1983). The origin of predictable behavior. American Economic Review, 73(4), 560–595.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holcombe, R. (2018). Political capitalism: How political influence is made and maintained. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Houser, D., & Stratmann, T. (2012). Gordon Tullock and experimental economics. Public Choice, 152(1–2), 211–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2002). Maps of bounded rationality: A perspective on intuitive judgment and choice. Nobel prize lecture, 8, 351–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, A. & Schram, A. (2018). Experimental public choice: elections. Oxford Handbook of Public Choice (Vol. 2, Ch. 44). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Ostrom, E. (1998). A behavioral approach to the rational choice theory of collective action. Presidential Address, American Political Science Association, 1997. American Political Science Review, 92(01), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (1999). How the mind works. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 882(1), 119–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2003). The blank slate: The modern denial of human nature. New York: Penguin Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plott, C. R. (2014). Public choice and the development of modern laboratory experimental methods in economics and political science. Constitutional Political Economy, 25(4), 331–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, M. E., Railton, P., Baumeister, R. F., & Sripada, C. (2016). Homo prospectus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackle, G. L. S. (1969/2010). Decision order and time in human affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Simon, H. A. (1979). Rational decision making in business organizations. American Economic Review, 69(4), 493–513.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, V. L. (2003). Constructivist and ecological rationality in economics. American Economic Review, 93(3), 465–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, H. (1851). Social statics: Or, the conditions essential to happiness specified, and the first of them developed. London: John Chapman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stigler, G. J. (1961). The economics of information. Journal of Political Economy, 69(3), 213–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoneman, P. (1981). Intra-firm diffusion, Bayesian learning and profitability. Economic Journal, 91(362), 375–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (2014). Why nudge? The politics of libertarian paternalism. New Haven CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, M. E., & Stone, P. (2009). Transfer learning for reinforcement learning domains: A survey. Journal of Machine Learning Research, 10, 1633–1685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. (1980). Toward a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 1(1), 39–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2008). Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New York: Penguin Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5(2), 207–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1986). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. Journal of Business, 59, S251–S278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tyran, J. R. & Wagner, A. K. (2018). Experimental Evidence on Expressive Voting. Oxford Handbook of Public Choice (Vol. 2, Ch. 45). Oxford UK: Oxford University Press.

  • Vanberg, V. J. (1994). Rules and choice in economics. New York: Taylor & Francis.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, R. E. (1976). Revenue structure, fiscal illusion, and budgetary choice. Public Choice, 25(1), 45–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, R. E., & Weber, W. E. (1977). Wagner’s law, fiscal institutions, and the growth of government. National Tax Journal, 30, 59–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittman, D. A. (1995). The myth of democratic failure: Why political institutions are efficient. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roger D. Congleton.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Congleton, R.D. Behavioral economics and the Virginia school of political economy: overlaps and complementarities. Public Choice 191, 387–404 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00679-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00679-3

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation