Skip to main content
Log in

Generality

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A distinction is drawn among predicates, open sentences (or open formulas), and general terms, including general-term phrases. Attaching a copula, perhaps together with an article, to a general term yields a predicate. Predicates can also be obtained through lambda-abstraction on an open sentence. The issue of designation and semantic content for each type of general expression is investigated. It is argued that the designatum of a general term is a universal, e.g., a kind, whereas the designatum of a predicate is a class (or its characteristic function) and the designatum of an open sentence is a truth-value. Predicates and open sentences are therefore typically non-rigid designators. It is argued further that certain general terms, including phrases, are invariably rigid designators, whereas certain others (general definite descriptions) are typically non-rigid. Suitable semantic contents for predicates, open sentences, and general terms are proposed. Consequences for the thesis of compositionality are drawn.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I owe to David Kaplan the insight that the word ‘horse’ functions as a kind name rather than a predicate whereas the phrase ‘is a horse’ functions as a predicate rather than a name. Cf. his “Afterthoughts” (1988a) to “Demonstratives” (1988b).

  2. The adjectival term τ may be an adjective phrase, as for example, ‘sleepless in Seattle’.

  3. Does ‘x is a horse’ stand for anything absolutely, i.e., not relative to a value-assignment? One could say (as some do) that the open sentence stands for a function from value-assignments to truth-values. This manner of speaking is misleading at best. It is better to say that an open expression designates only under an assignment of values to variables (or at least of values to the formula’s free variables).

  4. Cf. my “Naming, Necessity, and Beyond” (2003); and “Are General Terms Rigid?” (2005).

  5. In R&E I raised the question, but remained neutral, whether kinds having the same metaphysical intension are ipso facto the same kind (p. 53, n. 9). Teresa Robertson has formulated an interesting puzzle in “A Puzzle about Kinds” (unpublished). Robertson’s observations have helped to persuade me that there are numerically distinct kinds that exactly coincide in metaphysical intension. (R&E adopted an artificial use of ‘designate’, which I do not now favor, according to which a general term, τ, designates each of the kinds, categories, etc. whose metaphysical intensions coincide with the semantic intension of the corresponding predicate is τ.).

  6. Putnam (1975).

  7. Kaplan (1973).

  8. Cf. my “Are General Terms Rigid?” at footnote 23.

  9. Cf. my “The Logic of What Might Have Been” (1989).

  10. Cf. R&E, pp. 42–48, and passim; Salmon (1986/1991).

  11. Kaplan (1978); and my “Demonstrating and Necessity” (2002); also in Davidson (2007).

  12. As should be obvious (notwithstanding modern-day attempts to assimilate the two), the demonstrative use of ‘that’ is very different from the ‘that’-clause-forming use, certainly as far as their logic is concerned.

  13. Cf. my “Demonstrating and Necessity.” It is controversial that demonstratives are directly referential, but it should not be.

  14. Cf. my “A Theory of Bondage” (2006).

  15. For reasons related to this, Alonzo Church’s lambda-abstraction operator, as it occurs in (λα)[\( \phi_{\alpha } \)] where \( \phi_{\alpha} \) is an open sentence, is susceptible of a contextual definition. The latter is defined to be just this: is-a{(θα)[\( \phi_{\alpha } \)]}. It thus emerges that the theta-abstraction operator is a more basic variable-binding operator than the predicate-abstraction lambda operator. The predicate-abstraction use of (λα)[…] amounts to is-a{(θα)[…]}. Cf. R&E, p. 51.

References

  • Davidson, M. (Ed.). (2007). On sense and direct reference (pp. 838–871). New York: McGraw-Hill.

  • Kaplan, D. (1973). Bob and Carol and Ted and Alice. In K. J. J. Hintikka, J. M. E. Moravcsik, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Approaches to natural language (pp. 490–518, at p. 518, n. 31). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  • Kaplan, D. (1978). Dthat. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics 9: Pragmatics (pp. 221–243). New York: Academic Press. (Reprinted from Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language, pp. 383–400, by P. French, T. Uehling, Jr., & H. Wettstein, Eds., 1979, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.)

  • Kaplan, D. (1988a). Afterthoughts. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–614, at pp. 580–581, n. 30). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

  • Kaplan, D. (1988b). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–614, at pp. 580–581, n. 30). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of “meaning”. In K. Gunderson (Ed.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science VII: Language, mind, and knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. (Reprinted from Putnam’s Philosophical papers II: Mind, language, and reality, pp. 215–271, 1975, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.)

  • Salmon, N. (1986/1991). Frege’s puzzle (pp. 177–178, n. 4). Atascadero, CA.: Ridgeview.

  • Salmon, N. (1989). The logic of what might have been. The Philosophical Review, 98(1), 3–34. (Reprinted from Metaphysics, Mathematics, and Meaning, Chap. 7, 2005, Oxford: Oxford University Press.)

  • Salmon, N. (2002). Demonstrating and necessity. The Philosophical Review, 111(4), 497–537 (whole no. 560). (Reprinted from Content, Cognition, and Communication, Chap. 4, New York, NY: Oxford University Press.)

  • Salmon, N. (2003). Naming, necessity, and beyond. Mind, 112(447), 475–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (2005). Are general terms rigid? Linguistics and Philosophy, 28(1), 117–134. (Reprinted from Content, Cognition, and Communication, Chap. 5, New York, NY: Oxford University Press.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (2006). A theory of bondage. The Philosophical Review, 115(4), 415–448. (Reprinted from Content, cognition, & communication, Chap. 6, New York, NY: Oxford University Press.)

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nathan Salmon.

Additional information

The present paper was delivered as a “magisterial lecture” at the XV National Congress of Philosophy in Buenos Aires, Argentina, December 2010. I am grateful to the conference hosts and for my audience’s reactions. I am especially grateful to Teresa Robertson for extremely fruitful discussion, and for much else.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Salmon, N. Generality. Philos Stud 161, 471–481 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9772-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9772-8

Keywords

Navigation