Skip to main content
Log in

Decomposing same

  • Published:
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Motivated by the cross-linguistic connection between same and scalar equatives, this paper proposes an explicit equative-like syntax and semantics of the same-construction by decomposing same into an equation head -eqtv (parameter marker) and an identity predicate ident (parameter). This move not only provides a novel way of unifying the internal and external uses of same under a compositional account, but also further sheds light on why same differs from other relational adjectives in terms of the licensing conditions for the internal use.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is not the case that all two-place predicates can be parameters, but a precise definition of a parameter will not be given in this paper and is left for future research.

  2. Since the standard phrase surfaces at the right edge of the sentence, obligatory extraposition at PF is often assumed in syntax, see similar treatments in the analyses of comparatives (Matushansky 2002; Bhatt and Pancheva 2004). I will remain agnostic about the syntactic details in terms of when the standard phrase forms a constituent with the equation head (see discussions in Bhatt and Pancheva 2004).

  3. One reviewer expresses the concern that EqP can take sentential scope with the existence of the definite article while Q-adjectives such as fewer cannot (*The fewer than 20 students have ever met Beth, see Solt 2015). The reason might be that the role of the definite article in SAME is a bit different than its typical use: ‘the same N’ can survive under existential and possessive constructions, unlike typical definite phrases, as pointed out to me by Peter Alrenga, Keny Chatain and Linmin Zhang:

    1. (i)
      figure s
    1. (ii)
      figure t
  4. I thank Keny Chatain for pointing out that the existence of MAX in my proposal is necessary in order to capture the uniqueness presupposition of same.

  5. The symmetric relation is defined as follows: If for any x and y: R(x,y)↔R(y,x), then R is a symmetric relation.

  6. Notice that each can license the internal reading of same as well (e.g. Each girl met the same boy). While Thomas and Sudo (2016) do report some experimental evidence showing that each can license cumulative readings in certain environments, this is a controversial point to make, and thus I have to leave open whether the current analysis could directly extend to the case involving each. An alternative to addressing (39) which does not rely on a particular analysis of every and can potentially extend to each, is to follow Charnavel (2015) and Dotlačil (2010) in assuming that an implicit reciprocal the others exists in those cases. I will not pursue this option here since Chatain (2020) points out some differences between a construction involving an overt reciprocal like ‘Every girl met the same boy as the others’ and one without it like (39), showing that the two might not be equivalent.

  7. The pluralization operator is represented by the superscript asterisk (see its definition in fn. 3), while the distribution operator is represented by the normal asterisk *.

  8. While my proposal relies on the assumption that every should be analyzed in a particular way because they can have cumulative readings under certain cases, I am not claiming that they can yield cumulative readings in the same-constructions in (39), which they don’t. It is well known that the distribution of the cumulative readings of every is extremely restricted (Kratzer 2000; Champollion 2010) and especially rare in the subject position.

  9. Another possibility is that since the plural internal use is not blocked for similar and identical because they do not express the identity relation like same, such a use is competing with their singular internal use without DIST as a more economical way of expressing the internal reading when the comparee and the standard are provided by the plural nominal the girls: the plural use involves Hmg but the singular use without DIST involves Hmg plus Quantifier Raising of -eqtv.

References

  • Abney, Steven P. 1987. The English noun phrase in its sentential aspect. PhD diss., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

  • Alrenga, Peter. 2006. Scalar (non-)identity and similarity. In West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL) 25, 49–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alrenga, Peter. 2007. Dimensions in the semantics of comparatives. PhD diss., University of California, Santa Cruz.

  • Anderson, Curt, and Marcin Morzycki. 2015. Degrees as kinds. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 33(3): 791–828.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, Chris. 2007. Parasitic scope. Linguistics and Philosophy 4: 407–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, Sigrid. 2000. The semantics of different: Comparison operator and relational adjective. Linguistics and Philosophy 23(2): 101–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, Sigrid. 2001. Reciprocals are definites. Natural Language Semantics 9(1): 69–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhatt, Rajesh, and Roumyana Pancheva. 2004. Late merger of degree clauses. Linguistic Inquiry 35(1): 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhatt, Rajesh, and Shoichi Takahashi. 2007. Direct comparisons: Resurrecting the direct analysis of phrasal comparatives. In Semantics and linguistic theory, Vol. 17, 19–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhatt, Rajesh, and Shoichi Takahashi. 2011. Reduced and unreduced phrasal comparatives. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 29(3): 581–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brasoveanu, Adrian. 2011. Sentence-internal different as quantifier-internal anaphora. Linguistics and Philosophy 34(2): 93–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brasoveanu, Adrian, and Jakub Dotlačil. 2012. Licensing sentence-internal readings in English. In Logic, Language and Meaning, eds. Maria Aloni, Vadim Kimmelman, Floris Roelofsen, Galit Sassoon, Katrin Schulz, and Matthijs Westera, 122–132. Berlin: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-31482-7_13.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bresnan, Joan W. 1973. Syntax of the comparative clause construction in english. Linguistic Inquiry 4(3): 275–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, Greg N. 1987. Same and different: Some consequences for syntax and semantics. Linguistics and Philosophy 10(4): 531–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Champollion, Lucas. 2010. Cumulative readings of every do not provide evidence for events and thematic roles. In Logic, language and meaning, eds. Maria Aloni, Harald Bastiaanse, Tikitu de Jager, and Katrin Schulz, 213–222. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Charnavel, Isabelle. 2015. Same, different and other as comparative adjectives–A uniform analysis based on french. Lingua 156: 129–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chatain, Keny. 2020. Reciprocalizing same. In Sinn und Bedeutung 24, eds. Michael Franke, Nikola Kompa, Mingya Liu, Jutta L. Mueller, and Juliane Schwab, 102–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, Gennaro. 2013. Logic in Grammar: Polarity, Free choice, and Intervention. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1977. On wh-movement. In Formal syntax, eds. Peter Culicover, Thomas Wasow, and Adrian Akmajian, 71–132. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dotlačil, Jakub. 2010. Anaphora and distributivity: A study of same, different, reciprocals and others. Utrecht: LOT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, David. 1985. A unified indexical analysis of same and different: A response to Stump and Carlson. Paper presented at University of Texas Workshop on Syntax and Semantics, Austin, Texas.

  • Gust, Helmar, and Carla Umbach. 2015. Making use of similarity in referential semantics. In 9th Conference on modeling and using context, eds. Henning Christiansen, Isidora Stojanovic, and George Papadopoulos, 425–439. Cham: LNCS Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hackl, Martin. 2000. Comparative quantifiers. PhD diss., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

  • Hackl, Martin. 2009. On the grammar and processing of proportional quantifiers: most versus more than half. Natural Language Semantics 17(1): 63–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanink, Emily A. 2017. Encoding equation through two types of selection. Talk at Selection Fest, ZAS Berlin.

  • Hardt, Daniel, and Line Mikkelsen. 2015. Same but different. Linguistics and Philosophy 38(4): 289–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haspelmath, Martin, and Oda Buchholz. 1998. Equative and similative constructions in the languages of Europe. In Adverbial constructions in the languages of Europe, eds. Johan van der Auwera and Dónall P. O. Baoill, 277–334. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, Irene. 1985. Notes on comparatives and related matters. Ms., University of Texas, Austin.

  • Heim, Irene. 1991. Artikel und definitheit. In Semantik: Ein internationales Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung, eds. Arnim von Stechow and Dieter Wunderlich, 487–535. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, Irene. 2000. Degree operators and scope. In 10th Semantics and Linguistic Theory conference, eds. Brendan Jackson and Tanya Matthews, 40–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keenan, Edward L. 1992. Beyond the frege boundary. Linguistics and Philosophy 15(2): 199–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Christopher. 1999. Projecting the adjective: The syntax and semantics of gradability and comparison. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Christopher, and Jason Stanley. 2009. On average. Mind 118(471): 583–646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. 2000. The event argument and the semantics of verbs. Amherst: University of Massachusetts, Chapter 2. Manuscript.

  • Krifka, Manfred. 1989. Nominalreferenz und Zeitkonstitution: Zur Semantik von Massentermen, Pluraltermen und Aspektklassen. Munich: Fink.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, Peter. 1999. Pragmatic Halos. Language 75(3): 522–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauer, Sven. 2016. On the status of ‘maximize presupposition’. In 26th Semantics and Linguistic Theory conference, eds. Mary Moroney, Carol-Rose Little, Jacob Collard, and Dan Burgdorf, 980–1001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Link, Godehard. 1983. The logical analysis of plural and mass nouns: A lattice theoretic approach. In Meaning, use and interpretation of language, eds. Rainer Bäuerle, Christoph Schwarze, and Arnim von Stechow, 302–323. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matushansky, Ora. 2002. Movement of Degree/Degree of movement. PhD diss., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

  • Matushansky, Ora. 2008. More of the same. Talk given at GLOW 31, Newcastle University, March 26-29.

  • Matushansky, Ora. 2010. Same problem, different solution. Ms., University of Utrecht.

  • Oxford, Will. 2010. Same, different, and other: The microsyntax of identity adjectives. Ms. University of Toronto.

  • Partee, B. H. 1987. Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. In Studies in discourse representation theory and the theory of generalized quantifiers, eds. Jereon Groenendijk, Dick de Jongh, and Martin Stokhof, 115–143. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pullum, Geoffrey K, and Rodney Huddleston. 2002. Comparative constructions. In The Cambridge grammar of the English language, 1097–1170. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rett, Jessica. 2013. Similatives and the argument structure of verbs. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 31(4): 1101–1137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rett, Jessica. 2014. The Semantics of evaluativity. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzchild, Roger, and Karina Wilkinson. 2002. Quantifiers in comparatives: A semantics of degree based on intervals. Natural Language Semantics 10(1): 1–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, Roger. 1996. Pluralities. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Mike. 2009. Partitives and the semantics of same. Ms., NYU.

  • Solt, Stephanie. 2009. The semantics of adjectives of quantity. PhD diss., City University of New York.

  • Solt, Stephanie. 2015. Q-adjectives and the semantics of quantity. Journal of Semantics 32(2): 221–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sternefeld, Wolfgang. 1998. Reciprocity and cumulative predication. Natural Language Semantics 6(3): 303–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, Guillaume, and Yasutada Sudo. 2016. Cumulative readings of each. Presentation at the Workshop on (Co-) Distributivity, Paris, February.

  • Zhang, Linmin. 2016. External same and internal same: A unified account motivated by attitude reports. In Sinn und Bedeutung 20, eds. Nadine Bade, Berezovskaya Polina, and Anthea Schöller, 833–850.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to my advisors of this project: Chris Kennedy and Itamar Francez. I thank Peter Alrenga, Heather Burnett, Manuel Križ, Richard Larson, Peter Lasersohn, Yimei Xiang, and the audiences at the UChicago Linguistics and Philosophy Workshop, SICOGG 20, SuB 24 for the feedback, especially Keny Chatain, Daniel Hardt, and Line Mikkelsen for the extensive discussions. Special thanks go to the three anonymous reviewers of Natural Language and Linguistic Theory and the handling editor (Roumyana Pancheva) for their helpful comments. I also thank Jackie Lai for his support. All remaining errors are my own.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yenan Sun.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sun, Y. Decomposing same. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 40, 911–931 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-021-09522-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-021-09522-1

Keywords

Navigation