Abstract
Feelings not only have a place, they also have a time. Today, one can speak of a multifaceted renaissance of feelings. This concerns philosophy itself, particularly, ethics. Every law-based morality comes up against its limits when morals cease to be only a question of legitimation and begin to be a question of motivation, since motives get no foothold without the feeling of self and feeling of the alien. As it is treated by various social theories and psychoanalysis, the self is not formed through the mere acquisition or change of roles, but rather through a process that is susceptible to crises, a process shaped by affective bonds and separations. Learning, which is the theme of pedagogy, loses its hold whenever it is confronted by disinterest and listlessness. In neurobiology, the increased significance of those zones of the brain that are connected with the realization of feelings makes the brain, accordingly, no mere apparatus that processes data, but a living organ that selects and “evaluates” what is “important.” Finally, cross-cultural comparison shows the extent to which the one-sided preference for understanding and willing, which is the mark of Western rationalism, arises from a typical, not to mention a highly masculine attitude toward the world and life, as many different studies on gender difference stress (In reference to this perspective, see Seethaler, Gefühle und Urteilskraft. Ein Plädoyer für die emotionale Vernunft, 1997). The following reflections provide a historical orientation directed toward a new determination of feelings. This new determination of feelings is phenomenological and takes the pathetic character of experience, nourished by the corporeality of experience as its point of departure.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
Hegel (1977, p. 43).
Hegel (1977, p. 43).
von Goethe (1961, p. 327).
Heine (1976, p. 446).
Husserl (1970, p. 228).
Lichtenburg (1990, p. 62).
Kant (2003, A134).
Sophocles (1991, p. 227).
See, e.g., his discussion in (1989, §36).
In addition, see my critical position: “Wertqualitäten oder Erfahrungsansprüche?” in Vom Umsturz der Werte in der modernen Gesellschaft, ed. G. Pafafferott (Bonn: Bouvier 1997).
Straus (1956, p. 372).
Straus, Vom Sinn der Sinne, 394.
See the entirely Francophonic debate that is carried out in the journal: Études Phénoménologiques, Nos. 39–40 (2004): Commencer par la phénoménologie hylétique?
Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2002. I articulate there what I can only suggest here.
Kant (2004, p. 373, n 125).
See the definition that Hinrich Fink-Eitel suggests: “Affects are inner states that are shaped in a propositional-cognitive manner, that are mediated in a life-historical and psychical manner, and are founded in a bodily manner; moreover, they are subject to super-individual relations of social and cultural determinants.” See Fink-Eitel and Lohmann (1994, p. 57).
See more recently: Grüny (2004).
The polarity of immediate emotion and habitual attitudes of feeling belongs to the basic tenets of the classical doctrine of affect. Paul Ricœur accordingly differentiates between emotion as surprise, emotion as shock, and emotion as passion in Freedom and Nature: The Voluntary and the Involuntary, trans. Erazim V. Kohák (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2007, pp. 250–280).
Husserl (2001, p. 216).
Heidegger (1962, p. 178).
For more detail see Waldenfels and Giuliani (2000).
In addition, see Roth (1997, p. 194). However if meanings and evaluative activities are attributed to the brain directly, we end up with a neurological homunculus.
Descartes (1951, p. 72).
Nietzsche (1989a, p. 100).
I refer to my recent work Phänomenologie der Aufmerksamkeit (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2004), that is based entirely on the resonance between the process of something becoming noticed [Auffallen] and the process of taking notice of something [Aufmerken].
Lichtenburg (1990, p. 24).
Benjamin Libet, a convinced Neocartesian, is decidedly more careful in his conclusions. See his recent account in (2004).
Nietzsche (1989b, p. 61).
Scheler (1979, p. 242).
Translator’s note: Hospitalism is a pediatric diagnosis that describes infants who wasted away while in the hospital. It is now thought that this wasting away was due to a lack of social contact since those infants in poorer hospitals that could not afford incubators did not die as often since they were held by the staff.
See Emde (1983). Not only Sigmund Freud, but also the trained author Anna Freud regards the affective experiences from the early childhood period as “a pioneer” for the development within all other ranges.
I refer here to the remarks of Guy van Kerckhoven, who follows Hans Lipps, in “In Verlegenheit geraten. Die Befangenheit des Menschen als anthropologischer Leitfaden in Hans Lipps’ ‘Die menschliche Natur,’” Revista de filosofía 26 (2001): 55–84.
I am reminded of Merleau-Ponty’s idea of intercorporéité, a chiasmatic network, which is called also following Husserl interpenetration or intertwining [Ineinander]. This interpenetration would not only be characterized as “intentional interpenetration” (see for instance Husserl 1970, pp. 255–257), but also as a co-affective interpenetration. [Editor’s note: See Beata Stawarska’s article, “Feeling good vibrations in dialogical relations,” in this issue for further elaboration on the affective features of infant bodily “dialogicality” and its ties to the structural dynamics of adult conversation.]
Kleist (1952, p. 837).
Thoma (1962, p. 153).
Thoma (1962, p. 153).
Let me refer here to my critical remarks in Grenzen der Normalisierung (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1998b), 112 and 247, or to my Bruchlinien der Erfahrung, 55, 382.
Husserl (1999, pp. 38–39); translation modified.
I refer to my study “Der beunruhigte Blick,” in Sinnesschwellen (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1998a).
I count such a responsive epoché among the apparatus of a responsive phenomenology. See my Antwortregister (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1994), 195–197.
References
Descartes, René. 1951. Meditations on first philosophy (trans: Lafleur, L.J.). New Jersey: Prentice Hall.
Emde, Robert N. ed. 1983. René A. Spitz: Dialogues from infancy, selected papers. New York: International Universities Press.
Fink-Eitel, H., and G. Lohmann. ed. 1994. Zur Philosophie der Gefühle. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
von Goethe, Johann Wolfgang. 1961. Faust (trans: Kaufmann, W.). New York: Anchor Books.
Goldstein, Kurt. 1934. Der Aufbau des Organismus. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.
Grüny, Christian. 2004. Zerstörung der Erfahrung. Eine Phänomenologie des Schmerzes. Würzburg: Verlag Königshausen und Neumann.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1977. Phenomenology of spirit (trans: Miller, A.V.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and time (trans: Macquarrie, J., and E. Robinson). New York: Harper and Row Publishers.
Heine, Heinrich. 1976. Vorwort zu Geständnisse. In Sämtliche Schriften, Vol. 6/I. Carl Hanser: Munich.
Husserl, Edmund. 1970. The crisis of European Sciences and transcendental phenomenology (trans: Carr, D.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Husserl, Edmund. 1989. Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, second book (trans: Rojcewicz, R., and A. Schuwer). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Husserl, Edmund. 1999. Cartesian meditations (trans: Cairns, D.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Husserl, Edmund. 2001. Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental logic (trans: Steinbock, A.J.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Kant, Immanuel. 2003. The critique of pure reason (trans: Smith, N.K.). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Kant, Immanuel. 2004. Prolegomena to any future metaphysics (translated and edited: Hatfield, G.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
van Kerckhoven, Guy. 2001. In Verlegenheit geraten. Die Befangenheit des Menschen als anthropologischer Leitfaden in Hans Lipps’ ‘Die menschliche Natur.’ In Revista de filosofía 26: 55–84.
Kleist, Heinrich. 1952. Über die allmähliche Verfertigung der Gedanken beim Reden. In Sämtliche Werke. Munich: Helmut Sembdner.
Libet, Benjamin. 2004. Mind time: The temporal factor in consciousness. Boston: Harvard University Press.
Lichtenburg, Georg Christoph. 1990. Aphorisms (trans: Hollingdale, R.J.). London: Penguin.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1962. Phenomenology of perception (trans: Smith, C.). New York. Routledge.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1989a. Beyond good and evil (trans: Kaufmann, W.). New York: Vintage Books.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1989b. On the genealogy of morals (trans: Kaufmann, W.). New York: Vintage Books.
Ricœur, Paul. 2007. Freedom and nature: The voluntary and the involuntary (trans: Kohák, E.V.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Roth, Gerhard. 1997. Das Gehirn und seine Wirklichkeit. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Scheler, Max. 1976. Stellung des Menschen im Kosmos. In Späte Schriften, Gesammelte Werke, Vol. 9. Bern/München: Francke Verlag.
Scheler, Max. 1979. The nature of sympathy (trans: Heath, P.). London: Routledge and K. Paul.
Scheler, Max. 2008. The human place in the Cosmos (trans: Frings, M.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press (in press).
Seethaler, Carola Meier. 1997. Gefühle und Urteilskraft. Ein Plädoyer für die emotionale Vernunft. Munich: C.H. Beck.
Sophocles. 1991. Antigone. In The oedipus plays of sophocles (trans: Roche, P.). New York: Mentor.
Straus, Erwin. 1956. Vom Sinn der Sinne. Berlin/Göttingen/Heidelberg: Springer.
Thoma, Ludwig. 1962. Onkel Peppi und andere Erzählen. Munich: Paul List Verlag.
Waldenfels, Bernhard. 1994. Antwortregister. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Waldenfels, Bernhard. 1997. Wertqualitäten oder Erfahrungsansprüche? In Vom Umsturz der Werte in der modernen Gesellschaft, ed., G. Pafafferott. Bonn: Bouvier.
Waldenfels, Bernhard. 1998a. Der beunruhigte Blick. In Sinnesschwellen. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Waldenfels, Bernhard. 1998b. Grenzen der Normalisierung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Waldenfels, Bernhard. 2002. Bruchlinen der Erfahrung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Waldenfels, Bernhard. 2004. Phänomenologie der Aufmerksamkeit. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Waldenfels, Bernhard, and Regula Giuliani. 2000. Das leibliche Selbst. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Translator’s Acknowledgements
I wish to express my deepest gratitude to Dr. Anthony Steinbock for all of his help in revising this translation. I would also like to thank Dr. Douglas Berger for his comments on an earlier draft of this translation.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Additional information
Translated by Christina M. Gould (
)
Department of Philosophy, Southern Illinois University at Carbondale, Carbondale, IL 62901, USA
e-mail: cgould@siu.edu
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Waldenfels, B. The role of the lived-body in feeling. Cont Philos Rev 41, 127–142 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-008-9077-6
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-008-9077-6