1 Introduction

An idea which has guided the study of natural language is that syntax is autonomous. Specifically, a difference in syntactic category does not have to correlate with a difference in meaning. For example, the verb refuse in he refuses the offer and the noun refusal in his refusal of the offer express the same relation and project the same argument structure. The fact that the subject of the verb is he and the subject of the noun is his, and the fact that the verb combines directly with its object while the noun requires the mediation of the preposition of, are explained in terms of such concepts as Case and Government, or concepts that refine or replace them, which have no semantic import (Chomsky, 1970, 1981).

A comparable situation seems to obtain with respect to the adjectival modals certain and possible and their adverbial counterparts certainly and possibly. Consider the sentences in 1.

figure a

Let p stand for the proposition that John passed the exam. There is a sense in which both sentences in express \(\square p\), a universal modal statement, and both sentences in 1(b) express \(\Diamond p\), an existential modal statement which is entailed by \(\square p\). The intuition, which is clear but which, to the best of our knowledge, has not been spotlighted in the literature, is that every sentence in 1(a) guarantees the truth of every sentence in 1(b) but no sentence in 1(b) guarantees the truth of any sentence in 1(a). Thus, sequences such as those in 2 might sound a bit affected or pedantic, but to the extent that a reasonable context of use can be construed, say one of a logic class, in which they are uttered, we would have to accept them, in that context, as expressing valid arguments, i.e. those in which the sentence after therefore must be true if the sentence before therefore is true.

figure b

On the other hand, sequences such as those in 3 would not be accepted as valid arguments in this sense, no matter what the hypothetical context is.Footnote 1

figure c

This contrast confirms our basic intuition about these items: the logical relationship which obtains between certain p and certainly p on the one hand and possible p and possibly p on the other is the same one which obtains between \(\square p\) and \(\Diamond p\).

figure d

We are therefore tempted to say that there is no semantic difference between an adjectival modal and its adverbial counterpart. The difference is purely syntactic: certain and possible head XPs which are sister to the verb be while certainly and possibly are sentential adjuncts, but both certain and certainly express the universal modal \(\square \) and both possible and possibly express the existential modal \(\Diamond \) (see e.g. Kratzer, 1981: 41; Yalcin, 2007: 984, footnote 1).

This paper is about the adjectival modals certain and possible and the adverbial modals certainly and possibly. Our central claim will be that the difference between an adjectival modal and its adverbial counterpart is not only syntactic but also semantic. Specifically, we will defend the hypothesis that the adjectives quantify over knowledge while adverbs quantify over belief. Our analysis will derive not only the entailment patterns presented in 2 and 3 but also other observations including, for example, the fact that a change in category from adjective to adverb weakens the universal but strengthens the existential modal, or the fact that the adverbs, but not the adjectives, give rise to infelicity in environment which induce “ignorance” on the part of the relevant epistemic agent. Two differences between knowledge and belief will be crucial for the account: (i) knowledge implies belief, which means the set of knowledge worlds is a subset of the set of belief worlds; (ii) introspective access is guaranteed for belief but not for knowledge, which means one is necessarily opinionated about what one believes but not necessarily opinionated about what one knows.

The paper is structured as follows. Section 2 discusses observations made by Nilsen (2004) and Lassiter (2016) which suggest that an adjectival modal is not semantically equivalent to its adverbial counterpart, or more specifically, that an existential adjectival modal is weaker, while a universal adjectival modal is stronger, than its adverbial counterpart. Section 3 introduces the hypothesis that adjectival modals quantify over knowledge while adverbial modals quantify over belief and derives the facts discussed in Sect. 2 from this hypothesis plus the assumption that knowledge implies belief. Section 4 discusses the distribution of adjectival and adverbial modals in conditionals and want sentences, and derives it from the assumption that agents have epistemic access to their belief. Section 5 discusses the differences between adjectival and adverbial modals with respect to answerhood and negation, and derives them from the assumption that relevance is closed under speakers’ belief and the assumption that commitment is pragmatically inconsistent with the explicit denial of belief. Section 6 discusses some open issues. Section 7 comments on some previous works. Section 8 concludes.

2 Differences in strength

In this section we argue that the adjectival modals differ from their adverbial counterparts with respect to logical strength. Two observations are presented. The first, nilsen’s observation, is discussed in Sect. 2.1. The second, lassiter’s observation, is discussed in Sect. 2.2.

2.1 Nilsen’s observation

We begin with the contrast between (5a) and (5b), which is noted by Nilsen (2004: 823). While (5a) sounds quite natural, (5b) sounds contradictory. We add (5c), which sounds as contradictory as (5b).Footnote 2

figure e

The contrast between (5a) and (5b), which are a mininal pair, indicates that possible and possibly are not equivalent. The contrast between (5a) and (5c), which are also a minimal pair, indicates that certain and certainly are not equivalent either.

figure f

Note that the contrast in (5), in addition to establishing nilsen’s observation, also raises the question why (5a) is acceptable while (5b) and (5c) are not. Let us start with the oddness of (5b) and (5c). One plausible explanation for it is that possible is the dual of certain and possibly is the dual of certainly, i.e. that certain p \(\Leftrightarrow \) \(\lnot \)possible \(\lnot p\) and certainly p \(\Leftrightarrow \) \(\lnot \)possibly \(\lnot p\). Sentence (5b), which is of the form possibly p \(\wedge \) certainly \(\lnot p\), would then be equivalent to possibly p \(\wedge \) \(\lnot \) possibly p, a contradiction. Sentence (5c), which is of the form possible p \(\wedge \) certain \(\lnot p\), would be equivalent to possible p \(\wedge \) \(\lnot \)possible p, also a contradiction. Thus, (5b) and (5c) would be contradictory, which accounts for their oddness.

What about the acceptability of (5a)? This sentence is of the form possible p \(\wedge \) certainly \(\lnot p\). Under the assumption that possibly is the dual of certainly, (5a) would be equivalent to possible p \(\wedge \) \(\lnot \)possibly p. Since (5a) is acceptable, possible p \(\wedge \) \(\lnot \)possibly p should not be a contradiction. This means that possible p should not entail possibly p. Logically, there are two ways for possible p not to entail possibly p.

figure g

The paradigm in (5) does not adjudicate between (7b) and (7c). However, we have evidence for (7c) and against (7b). Let us discuss it now.

2.2 Lassiter’s observation

We start with the fact that (8) sounds contradictory.

figure h

This fact would be puzzling if possible p and possibly p are logically independent, but would be expected if possibly p is stronger than possible p. Thus, the deviance of (8) suggests that (7b) is true. It then follows, from (7b), that certainly p, the dual of possibly p, is weaker than certain p, the dual of possible p. We thus expect certain p \(\wedge \) \(\lnot \)certainly p to be contradictory. And since \(\lnot \) certainly p \(\Leftrightarrow \) possibly \(\lnot p\), the prediction would be that certain p \(\wedge \) possibly \(\lnot p\) is contradictory, hence deviant. This prediction is borne out, as evidenced by the deviance of (9).Footnote 3

figure i

Interesting independent evidence for (7b) is provided by Lassiter (2016). In this study, an experiment is conducted in which participants are presented with a scenario where Bill bought a single ticket in a raffle with 1000 total tickets. The participants are then shown a sentence and asked to indicate whether they “agree” or “disagree” with it. Among the sentences are those in (10) (Lassiter, 2016: 130–131).

figure j

Let p be the proposition that Bill won the raffle and q be the proposition that Bill did not win the raffle. Lassiter’s sentences, then, are of the form possible p and possibly p, with p having a 0.1 percent chance of being true, and certain q and certainly q, with q having a 99.9 percent chance of being true.

What Lassiter observes is that people find possible p easier to accept than possibly p, and find certainly q easier to accept than certain q. We quote from the paper.

Participants were much more willing to reject Bill possibly won than It is possible that Bill won (0.26 vs. 0.8, \(p < 0.01\)), and they were much more willing to accept Bill certainly did not win than It is certain that Bill did not win (0.54 vs. 0.25, \(p < 0.001\)). (Lassiter, 2016: 135–136)

Lassiter assumes “a simple linking theory to bridge semantic theories with the behavioral data” which says that “if p entails q, then q should be at least as acceptable as p” (Lassiter, 2016: 131). Logically speaking, then, differences in acceptability are not proof of differences in logical strength.Footnote 4 It is clear, however, that Lassiter takes differences in acceptability, given his experimental set-up, to be evidence of differences in logical strength. For example, he considers the fact that might p is harder to accept than possible p to be “evidence that possible is weaker than might” (Lassiter, 2016: 129). We will thus take Lassiter’s experimental result to be additional evidence supporting the claim that possibly p is stronger than possible p and certain q is stronger than certainly q, which was argued for on the basis of (5), (8) and (9).Footnote 5 In other words, a change in category from adjective to adverb is weakening for certain and strengthening for possible.

figure k

To the extent that lassiter’s observation is correct, it implies that nielsen’s observation is correct and, moreover, implies that it is correct because (7b) is correct.

Another piece of supporting evidence for lassiter’s observation is the contrast in (12), which is admittedly quite subtle but has been confirmed by native speakers we consulted.

figure l

The difference between (12a) and (12b) seems to be this. In (12a), the speaker is not conveying anything new with the second sentence. The sequence has a “redundant” feel to it, similar to it’s raining and snowing, therefore it’s raining. In (12b), on the other hand, the speaker appears to be making some sort of a guess. A step of reasoning seems to be required to go from the claim that John bought one ticket to the claim that he “possibly won.” As the speaker does not disclose what justifies this step, the word therefore feels a bit odd. This intuition is corroborated by the fact that the question Why do you say that? seems more natural as a follow-up to (12b) than as a follow-up to (12a). This indicates that inferring certainly p from certain p is logical but inferring possibly p from possible p is not, which is predicted by lassiter’s observation.

3 The main hypothesis

This section introduces the main hypothesis of the paper and derives the observations we have just discussed from it.

3.1 Domain reduction

Let us make the following claim, which is the main hypothesis of this paper.

figure m

According to the main hypothesis, then, a change in category from adjective to adverb has the effect of shifting the domain from knowledge to belief.

We assume that knowledge implies belief, i.e. that every proposition which is known is also believed but not vice versa Stalnaker (2006).Footnote 6 We state this assumption in (14), writing “\({\mathcal {K}}_a p\)” to mean p is true in every world compatible with what a knows and “\({\mathcal {B}}_a p\)” to mean p is true in every world compatible with what a believes, where a is the relevant epistemic agent.Footnote 7

figure n

The set of known propositions, then, is a subset of the set of believed propositions, which means the set of knowledge worlds is a superset of the set of belief worlds. Thus, the main hypothesis amounts to the claim that affixation of -ly reduces the set of worlds over which the modals quantify. A visualization is given below, where \({\mathcal {K}}_a\) is the set of worlds compatible with what a knows and \({\mathcal {B}}_a\) the set of worlds compatible with what a believes.

figure o

Assuming certain is a universal quantifier and possible its existential dual, certain p is true iff p is true in every \({\mathcal {K}}_a\)-world (\({\mathcal {K}}_a p\)), possible p is true iff p is true in some \({\mathcal {K}}_a\)-world (\(\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a \lnot p\)), certainly p is true iff p is true in every \({\mathcal {B}}_a\)-world (\({\mathcal {B}}_a p\)), and possibly p is true iff p is true is some \({\mathcal {B}}_a\)-world (\(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a \lnot p\)).

3.2 Deriving the BASIC INTUITION, NILSEN’S OBSERVATION, and LASSITER’S OBSERVATION

Let us now derive the basic intuition, repeated in (16).

figure p

Looking at (15), we can see that if p is true in every \({\mathcal {K}}_a\)-world, then p is true in some \({\mathcal {K}}_a\)-world and true in some \({\mathcal {B}}_a\)-world, which means certain p entails both possible p and possibly p. If p is true in every \({\mathcal {B}}_a\)-world then p is also true in some \({\mathcal {K}}_a\)-world and true in some \({\mathcal {B}}_a\)-world, which means certainly p also entails both possible p and possibly p. Now suppose p is true in some \({\mathcal {B}}_a\)-world and false in some other \({\mathcal {B}}_a\)-world. Then both possible p and possibly p are true while both certain p and certainly p are false. This means neither possible p nor possibly p entails certain p or certainly p. Thus, certain p is stronger than both possible p and possibly p, and certainly p is also stronger than both possible p and possibly p.

We also account for nilsen’s observation, repeated in (17).

figure q

The adjectives are not equivalent to their adverbial counterparts because they quantify over different domains.

Finally, we derive lassiter’s observation, repeated in (18).

figure r

If p is true in every \({\mathcal {K}}_a\)-world then p is true in every \({\mathcal {B}}_a\)-world but not vice versa, which means certain p is stronger than certainly p. And if p is true in some \({\mathcal {B}}_a\)-world then p is true in some \({\mathcal {K}}_a\)-world but not vice versa, which means possibly p is stronger than possible p.

The question now is whether the main hypothesis helps explain anything beyond the facts discussed in Sect. 1. In other words, are there properties of adjectival and adverbial modals other than those described by the basic intuition, nilsen’s observation, and lassiter’s observation which can be accounted for in terms of of how knowledge and belief are related? We will argue below that the answer is yes.

4 Introspection

This section will be devoted to showing how facts about certain/certainly and possible/possibly other than those we just discussed can be derived from the main hypothesis which says that the adjectival modals certain and possible quantify over knowledge while the adverbial modals certainly and possibly quantify over belief. Section 4.1 introduces the auxiliary hypothesis we need for our account. Section 4.2 discusses the observation that the adjectives are felicitous in the complement of want but the adverbs are not. Section 4.3 discusses a parallel difference with respect to if-clauses. Section 4.4 discuss cases where the constraint against adverbial modals in the complement of want and in if-clauses is obviated, and show that they are predicted by the analysis. Finally, a puzzle about disjunction is discussed in Sect. 4.5.

4.1 Opinionatedness

Let us start with a quote from Stalnaker, (2006: 179): “It seems reasonable to assume [...] that agents have introspective access to their beliefs: if they believe that \(\phi \), then they know that they do, and if they do not, then they know that they do not” (cf. also Hintikka, 1962, Lewis, 1969, Boghossian, 1994; Stalnaker, 2002, 2008).Footnote 8 We state this assumption in (19).

figure s

A consequence of introspection is that for any proposition p, a either believes that a believes that p or believes that a does not believe that p. Let us say a is “opinionated” about p iff a either believes p or believes \(\lnot p\), i.e. iff \({\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\vee \) \({\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot p\). We can then say that a consequence of introspection is that a is opinionated about her own belief.Footnote 9

figure t

Here is how belief opinionatedness is derived from introspection. Suppose that \({\mathcal {B}}_a p\). By positive introspection, it follows that \({\mathcal {K}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a p\), and by knowledge implies belief, that \({\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a p\), hence that \({\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\vee \) \({\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\). Now suppose that \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\). By negative introspection it follows that \({\mathcal {K}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\), and by knowledge implies belief, that \({\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\), hence that \({\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\vee \) \({\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\). Thus, \({\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\vee \) \({\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\) follows from both \({\mathcal {B}}_a p\) and its negation \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\), given introspection.

Note, importantly, that introspection claims epistemic access to belief but does not claim epistemic access to knowledge. Stalnaker (2006), following Hintikka (1962), submits that positive introspection holds for knowledge but negative introspection does not, i.e. that it holds generally that \({\mathcal {K}}_a p \rightarrow {\mathcal {K}}_a{\mathcal {K}}_a p\) but it does not hold generally that \(\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a p \rightarrow {\mathcal {K}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a p\).Footnote 10 Thus, it does not follow from introspection that speakers are opinionated about their knowledge. In other words, it does not hold generally that \({\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {K}}_a p\) \(\vee \) \({\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a p\).

Assuming that inferences which contradict introspection give rise to deviance, we predict that inferences which contradict belief opinionatedness, i.e. inferences of the form \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\), will give rise to deviance. On the other hand, inferences of the form \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {K}}_a p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a p\) do not contradict introspection and are therefore not predicted to give rise to deviance.

How do we translate these rather abstract predictions into more concrete predictions about sentences containing adjectival and adverbial modals? Let us say a is “ignorant” about p iff a is not opinionated about p, i.e. iff \(\lnot ({\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\vee \) \({\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot p)\), or equivalently, \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot p\). Now suppose we derive the inference that a is ignorant about certain p. As certain p means \({\mathcal {K}}_a p\), this inference would be \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {K}}_a p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a p\), which does not contradict introspection and hence is not expected to give rise to deviance. Now suppose the inference is that a is ignorant about possible p. As possible p means \(\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a \lnot p\), this inference would be \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a \lnot p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot \lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a \lnot p\), or equivalently, \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {K}}_a q\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a q\), where q stands for \(\lnot p\). Again, we see that this inference does not contradict introspection and hence is not expected to give rise to deviance.

Let us now turn to adverbial modals. Suppose the inference is that a is ignorant about certainly p. As certainly p means \({\mathcal {B}}_a p\), this inference would be \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\), which contradicts introspection and is expected to give rise to deviance. Now suppose the inference is that a is ignorant about possibly p. As possibly p means \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a \lnot p\), this inference would be \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a \lnot p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot \lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a \lnot p\), or equivalently, \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a q\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a q\), where q stands for \(\lnot p\). We see that this inference contradicts introspection and hence is expected to give rise to deviance.

Thus, the prediction is that in contexts of ignorance, possible and certain are acceptable but possibly and certainly will lead to deviance. Note that we assume grammatical deviance can arise from a conflict which pertains to the semantics and not the syntax of the sentence. While this assumption is not obvious, it has been proposed and defended

(Barwise & Cooper, 1981; Krifka, 1995; von Fintel, 1997; Gajewski, 2002; Abrusán, 2007; Fox & Hackl, 2006). It is, however, beyond the scope of this paper to discuss this issue, and we will now turn to arguments that the prediction mentioned above is borne out by facts.

4.2 Embedding under want

4.2.1 Observation

Embedding certainly p and possibly p under the verb want gives rise to deviance, while embedding certain p and possible p under want does not. This is evidenced by the contrast in (21).Footnote 11

figure u

4.2.2 Explanation

Ignorance inference of want

It has been noted that the meaning of want is related to belief Karttunen (1974: 188–189). A well-known analysis of want is proposed in Heim (1992). For present purposes, we can paraphrase it as in (22).

figure v

The idea is that worlds which are excluded from a’s belief are not relevant in evaluating what a wants. We quote from Heim (1992).

Suppose [the sentence I want to teach Tuesday and Thursday next semester] is intuitively true as spoken by me today. Is it therefore the case [...] that I teach Tuesdays and Thursdays next semester in all the worlds that are compatible with everything I desire? No. In worlds that are compatible with everything I desire I actually don’t teach at all [...] [A]s it happens, I believe that I will teach (a regular course load) next semester. This means there are no doxastically accessible worlds in which I don’t teach at all. In all doxastically accessible worlds, I either teach Tuesdays and Thursdays, or else I teach the same load on different weekdays. Among these, the former are more desirable than the latter, and this makes [the sentence] true. (Heim, 1992:195)

Another analysis of want which also restricts the set of relevant worlds to the agent’s belief is proposed by von Fintel (2011: 117–118).

figure w

The problem with both of these analyses, as pointed out by Heim and von Fintel themselves, is that they make the wrong prediction for cases where a is opinionated about p. Suppose that a believes p. Then (22) predicts, incorrectly, that a wants p is true: if there is no \(\lnot p\)-world in a’s belief, then trivially every p-world in a’s belief is better for a than every \(\lnot p\)-world in a’s belief. The same incorrect prediction is made by (23): if p is true in all worlds in a’s belief, then trivially p is true in all of the worlds in a’s belief which are most desired by a. Now suppose that a believes \(\lnot p\). Then (22) predicts, again incorrectly, that a wants p is true: if there is no p-world in a’s belief, then trivially every p-world in a’s belief is better for a than every \(\lnot p\)-world in a’s belief. The prediction made by (23) in this scenario, however, is that a wants p is false: if p is true in no world in a’s belief, then trivially p is not true in all of the worlds in a’s belief which are most desired by a. Of course, this prediction is also incorrect.

To solve this problem, Heim and von Fintel add to their semantics of want a definedness condition which requires that the subject of want neither believe the complement nor believe its negation.

figure x

Thus, a wants p licenses the inference \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a \lnot p\) as a presupposition.Footnote 12

Deriving the observation

Let us come back to (21), repeated in (25).Footnote 13

figure y

Let p stand for the proposition that Mary is guilty and q for \(\lnot p\). Assuming the embedded modals are anchored to John (j), the subject of the embedding verb (Hacquard, 2006), (25a) triggers the presupposition \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_j{\mathcal {K}}_j p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_j\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_j p\) when the modal is certain and \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_j{\mathcal {K}}_j q\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_j\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_j q\) when the modal is possible. Neither of these inferences contradicts introspection. On the other hand, (25b) triggers the presupposition that \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_j{\mathcal {B}}_j p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_j\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_j p\) when the modal is certainly and \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_j{\mathcal {B}}_j q\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_j\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_j q\) when the modal is possibly. Both of these inferences contradict introspection.Footnote 14

4.3 Conditionals

4.3.1 Observation

It has been observed that the distribution of adverbial modals in conditionals is restricted: they can occur in the main clause but not in the if-clause (cf. Piñon, 2006; Wolf, 2014; Greenberg & Wolf, 2018; Herbstritt, 2020; Krifka, 2020a, b). This is evidenced by the contrast between (26a) and (26b).

figure z

It has also been observed that no such restriction holds for adjectival modals (Krifka, 2019b). This is evidenced by the acceptability of both (27a) and (27b).

figure aa

4.3.2 Explanation

The restrictor analysis of conditionals and Gazdar’s generalization

We adopt the “restrictor” analysis of conditionals, according to which the if-clause restricts the modal in the main clause (Quine, 1950; Stalnaker, 1968; Lewis, 1973, 1975; Stalnaker, 1975; Heim, 1982; Kratzer, 1986, 1991; von Fintel & Heim, 2011; Krifka, 2019b; Goldstein & Santorio, 2021). The logical form of (28a), for example, would then be (28b), where is not interpreted.

figure ac

In the case of “plain” conditionals, i.e. those in which the main clause contains no overt modal, we assume that there is a covert MUST (Heim, 1982; von Fintel & Heim, 2011). Thus, the logical form of (29a) is (29b).

figure ad

Let us call the restrictor of the modal the “antecedent” and its scope the “consequent”.Footnote 15

It has been observed that a conditional, by default, licenses ignorance inferences about both the antecedent and the consequent (Gazdar, 1979). Thus, (28) and (29), by default, licenses the inference that the relevant epistemic agent (a) is ignorant about \(\gamma \) and ignorant about \(\delta \), i.e. that \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a \gamma \) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot \gamma \) and \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a \delta \) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot \delta \). In other words, (28) and (29), by default, licenses the inference that a does not believe John is sick, does not believe John is not sick, does not believe John is at home, and does not believe John is not at home.Footnote 16 For the purpose of this discussion, we will take this fact about conditionals to be basic and name it gazdar’s generalization, as it was Gazdar who, to the best of our knowledge, first stated it explicitly.Footnote 17

figure ae

Deriving the observation

Let us come back to (26), repeated in (31). The logical forms of the sentences, according to the restrictor analysis of conditionals discussed above, are added below them, where p stands for the proposition that John is sick and q for the proposition that John is at home.

figure af

Given gazdar’s generalization, the ignorance inferences licensed by (31a) are \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot p\) and \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a q\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot q\). None of these inferences contradicts introspection, and the sentence is felicitous, as expected.

Now consider (31b). Just like (31a), this sentence has q as the consequent, and thus licenses the inference \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a q\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot q\), which does not contradict introspection. However, the antecedent of (31b) is not p but certainly/possibly p. Assuming the adverbial modal is evaluated with respect to the same epistemic agent as the whole conditional (a), the associated ignorance inference would be \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\), when the modal is certainly. When the modal is possibly, the inference would be \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a q\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a q\), where q stands for \(\lnot p\). Both of these inferences contradict introspection, and the sentence is deviant, as expected.

What about (27)? We repeat the examples in (32), again with the logical forms added below the sentences?

figure ag

The only difference between (32) and (31) is that the antecedent of (31a) is certainly/possibly p while the antecedent of (32b) is certain/possible p. The ignorance inference associated with the antecedent in (32b) is thus \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {K}}_a p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a p\), when the modal is certain. When the modal is possible, it would be \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {K}}_a q\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {K}}_a q\), where q stands for \(\lnot p\). None of these inferences contradicts introspection, and the sentence is felicitous, as expected.

4.4 Obviating violation of INTROSPECTION

In the last two Sects. 4.2 and 4.3 we argue that adverbial modals give rise to deviance in environments which license the inference that the epistemic agent is ignorant about her own belief. In this subsection, we show that when these environments are modified as to no longer license this inference, the deviance caused by adverbial modals is alleviated.

4.4.1 Replacing the relevant lexical item

Note that a wants p licenses the inference that a is ignorant about p, but a believes p, for example, does not license this inference. We expect, then, that replacing want with believe will alleviate the deviance caused by adverbial modals in the embedded clause. This expectation is borne out.

figure ah

A similar effect is observed when the complementizer if is replaced with because. Thus, (34b) sounds much better than (34a).

figure ai

This is, again, expected, as because p presupposes p, hence surely does not license ignorance inferences about p.Footnote 18

4.4.2 Shifting the epistemic agent

It follows from introspection that epistemic agents are opinionated about their own belief. However, this principle does not require that agents be opinionated about others’ belief. Thus, while inferences of the form \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\) give rise to deviance, those of the form \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_b p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_b p\), with \(a \ne b\), should not. This expectation is borne out. Consider (35) and (36).

figure aj
figure ak

A contrast can be observed between the a-sentences and the b-sentences. Specifically, the former are better than the latter. Suppose the modifier according to x shifts the relevant epistemic agent to x, the ignorance inference of the b-sentences would be of the form \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_{a}{\mathcal {B}}_b p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_{a}\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_b p\), where \(a \ne b\).Footnote 19 In (35), a is John and b is the police. In (35), a is the speaker and b is Mary.Footnote 20

4.4.3 Inserting material between the two belief operators

It follows from introspection that agents are not ignorant about their own belief. However, this principle allows them to be ignorant about something which involves, but is not identical to, their own belief. Thus, inferences of the form \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_{a}(...{\mathcal {B}}_{a} p...)\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_{a}\lnot (...{\mathcal {B}}_{a} p...)\), where \((...{\mathcal {B}}_{a} p...)\) is not equivalent to a proposition of the form \({\mathcal {B}}_{a} q\) or the form \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_{a} q\) for some q, do not contradict introspection, and therefore are expected not to give rise to deviance. This expectation is borne out. Consider (37) and (38).Footnote 21

figure al
figure am

The meaning of \(\alpha \), i.e. the complement of want in (37b) and the if-clause in (38b), is (39).

figure an

It is clear that (39) is not equivalent to any proposition of the form \({\mathcal {B}}_{a} p\) or the form \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_{a} p\).Footnote 22 Thus, the ignorance inferences associated with (37b) and (38b) are not of the form \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_{a}{\mathcal {B}}_{a} p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_{a}\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_{a} p\). The sentences are felicitous, as expected.

Turning now to the meaning of \(\beta \) in (37c) and (38c), we see a similar situation. This meaning is \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot p \wedge {\mathcal {B}}_a q\), where p stands for the proposition that Mary is away and q for the proposition that Mary is not in the shower. The ignorance inferences generated would be (40).

figure ao

This inference, of course, does not contradict introspection. Note, importantly, that ignorance does not distribute over conjunction, i.e. \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a(p \wedge q)\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot (p \wedge q)\) does not entail \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot p\).Footnote 23 Thus, it does not follow from (40) that \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a{\mathcal {B}}_a q\) \(\wedge \) \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot q\). The sentences are felicitous, as expected.

4.4.4 Cancelling the ignorance inference

It turns out that the ignorance inference of want and if can sometimes be cancelled. Consider want first. It seems that in some contexts, the semantics of want can be modulated in such a way that a wants p is consistent with a being opinionated about p.Footnote 24 One such context is (41), for example. It is clear that the speaker is convinced that she lives in Paris.Footnote 25

figure ap

Regardless of how the relevant semantic modulation is to be analyzed, we predict that in contexts of this kind, embedding adverbial modals under want is felicitous. This prediction is borne out, as evidenced by the contrast in (42).Footnote 26

figure aq

A similar observation can be made for if. Consider the exchange in (43).Footnote 27

figure ar

There is definitely a reading of B’s response in which B has accepted A’s assertion as true. Thus, this is a context where gazdar’s generalization is suspended.Footnote 28 We predict that such contexts would alleviate the deviance caused by adverbial modals occuring in the if-clause. This prediction is borne out, as evidenced by the acceptability of B’s response in (44).Footnote 29

figure as

4.5 A puzzle about disjunctions

A well-known property of disjunctions is that they express, by default, the agent’s ignorance about the individual disjuncts. A sentence such as John talked to Mary or Sue, for example, implicates that the speaker’s belief does not entail John talked to Mary, does not entail John did not talk to Mary, does not entail John talked to Sue, and does not entail John did not talk to Sue (cf. e.g. Gazdar, 1979; Fox, 2007; Geurts, 2009; Fox, 2014). We expect, therefore, that occurence of adverbial modals in disjuncts would lead to deviance. This expectation is only partially fulfilled. Specifically, while adverbial modals in the first disjunct degrade the sentence, adverbial modals in the second disjunct seem not to have that effect, as evidenced by the contrast between (45a) and (45b).Footnote 30

figure at

We can observe, then, that with respect to the distribution of adverbial modals, first disjuncts are similar to if-clauses and second disjuncts similar to main clauses of conditionals. At the moment, we have nothing to offer beyond this descriptive statement, and will have to leave an explanation of (45) to future research. We would just note here that deviance caused by adverbial modals in the first disjuct can be alleviated in the ways discussed in the Sect. 4.4. For example, changing or to and would, of course, eliminate the relevant ignorance inferences and, consequently, improve the sentence.Footnote 31

figure au

Similarly, the sentences in (47) are all better than (45a).Footnote 32

figure av

In (47a), the epistemic agent is shifted. In (47b), the adverb is embedded inside a relative clause. In (47c), the linguistic context is set up in such a way that the relevant ignorance inference is cancelled.

5 Beyond KNOWLEDGE IMPLIES BELIEF and INTROSPECTION

Let us briefly recap. Our main hypothesis is that the adjectival modals certain and possible quantify over knowledge and the adverbial modals certainly and possibly quantify over belief. Several facts about these expressions have been argued to follow from two basic assumptions about knowledge and belief. The first is that knowledge implies belief: if a knows that p then a believes that p but not vice versa. The second is that agents have introspection into their belief: if a believes that p then a knows that a does and if a does not believe that p then a knows that a does not.

There are other differences between adjectival and adverbial modals that have not been discussed. The purpose of the present section is to present them and propose to derive them from assumptions about knowledge and belief other than knowledge implies belief and introspection. These additional assumptions pertain to the notions of relevance and commitment, and are not as obvious and uncontroversial as knowledge implies belief and introspection. The discussion, therefore, will be more speculative and tentative.

5.1 Relevance

5.1.1 Observation

It has been observed in the literature that the question whether p can be more naturally responded to with certainly/possibly p than with certain/possible p (Piñon, 2006; Wolf, 2014). Thus, there is a contrast between (48a) and (48b) as answer to (48).Footnote 33

figure aw

5.1.2 Explanation

The closure condition on relevance

Our account of this observation will turn on the notion of relevance. Intuitively, a proposition p is “relevant” if we are interested in finding out what its truth value is. This informal understanding of relevance suffices to motivate some “closure conditions” on the concept. We will assume the following.

figure ax

Closure of relevance under negation and conjunction is uncontroversial (Groenendijk & Stokhof, 1984; Lewis, 1988; von Fintel & Heim, 2011; Fox, 2007; Fox & Katzir, 2011).Footnote 34 It is also intuitively plausible. Knowing the truth value of p is just knowing the truth value of \(\lnot p\). Thus, if we are interested in the former then of course we are also interested in the latter. And it also seems intuitively plausible that if we are interested in knowing whether p and knowing whether q, then we are interested in knowing whether \(p \wedge q\).Footnote 35 The second condition, (49b), which states that relevance is closed under speakers’ belief, is less well-known (Fox, 2016; Buccola & Haida, 2019, 2020). To the best of our knowledge, it is first proposed in Fox (2016) to account for an ubiquitous fact about linguistic communication, namely that “silence is uncooperative” (Fox, 2016: 5). The scenario Fox used to illustrate this fact is that of a criminal court in which a witness w is asked by the lawyer where John was at the time of the murder. As Fox correctly observes, “if w believes something that bears on John’s whereabouts at the time of the murder, w is required to say so. If not, w is required to reveal this lack of opinion” (Fox, 2016: 5). What is clear is that w cannot just look the lawyer in the eye and remain silent. Note that the Gricean maxims, specifically the maxims of Quality, Quantity, and Relation, require us to provide all relevant information which we believe to be true (Fox, 1967: 5). If relevance is not closed under speaker’s belief, it would be cooperative for w to not say anything in the given scenario if w has no opinion about where John was at the time of the murder.Footnote 36

Deriving the observation

Given the closure conditions on relevance, the contrast in (48) follows from Grice’s maxim of Relation which states, specifically, that speakers assert only relevant propositions (Grice, 1967). To see this, let p stand for the proposition that John is at home. A’s question in (48) would then be whether p. By definition, whether p makes p relevant (Roberts, 1996; Büring, 2003; Roberts, 2017). As relevance is closed under negation and speakers’ belief, the following propositions will all be relevant given that p is relevant.

figure ay

We can now say why the sentences in (48a) are felicitous in the context of the question in (48): they are all relevant, hence adhere to the maxim of Relation. Now let us turn to the sentences in 48b. Given our main hypothesis, these express the following propositions.

figure az

Note, crucially, that relevance is not closed under knowledge: p being relevant does not make \({\mathcal {K}}_a p\) relevant. This means from the fact that p is made relevant by A’s question it does not follow that any of the propositions in (51) is relevant. All things being equal, then, they are not relevant, which means responding to A’s question with them constitutes a violation of Relation. We take this to be the reason for the contrast in (48).Footnote 37

5.2 Commitment

5.2.1 Observations

The inability of adverbial modals to scope under negation

It has been pointed out that adjectival modals can scope under negation while adverbial modals cannot, as indicated by the contrast in between (52a) and (52a) (cf. Piñon 2006; Wolf 2014; Herbstritt 2020; Krifka 2020a, b).Footnote 38

figure ba

The inability of adverbial modals to scope under negation generalizes beyond syntax to morphology: adjectival modals have antonyms derived by prefixation of in– and un– while adverbial modals do not. Thus, the lexicon contains uncertain and impossible as antonyms of certain and possible, but does not contain *uncertainly and *impossibly as antonyms of certainly and possibly (cf. Bellert, 1977: 343; Hengeveld, 1988: 237; Drubig, 2001: 10).Footnote 39

figure bb

The deviance ofpossibly p \(\varvec{\wedge }\) possibly \(\varvec{\lnot } {\varvec{p}}\)  A contrast which, to the best of our knowledge, has not been noted in the literarure is that between (54a) and (54b).Footnote 40

figure bc

The intuition is that (54a) is perfectly normal while (54b) gives the impression of a somewhat incoherent speaker. Specifically, (54b) feels like the speaker is expressing two conflicting belief states, thereby conveying two inconsistent takeaway messages.Footnote 41 The observation can be stated informally as follows.Footnote 42

figure bd

We predict, then, that possible p \(\wedge \) possible \(\lnot p\) is natural but possibly p \(\wedge \) possibly \(\lnot p\) is odd. This prediction, we believe, is borne out. Consider the contrast in (56), assuming that one fails an exam if and only if one does not pass it.Footnote 43

figure be

Let us rule out, right away, a hypothesis for (55) which might seem plausible. This hypothesis says that affixation of -ly strengthens possible to something like likely or probably. Suppose that possible p means p has a non-zero chance of being true while possibly p means p has a more than 50 percent chance of being true. It would follow that (54a) is consistent, hence natural, while (54b) is contradictory, hence odd, and the contrast between (54a) and (54b) would have the same explanation as that between (57a) and (57b) below.

figure bf

However, the hypothesis cannot be correct. If possibly p means p has a more than 50 percent chance of being true, then there should be no contrast between (58a) and (58b) below. But there clearly is one.

figure bg

There is no denial that (58b) is consistent. It might be perceived as a wild or as a reasonable guess, depending on how we feel about raffles and luck. The sentence, however, is definitely not contradictory. On the other hand, (58a) is hopeless. There is just no way to construe any context in which it can be uttered sincerely by a rational speaker. This shows that possibly p does not mean p has a more than 50 percent chance of being true.

5.2.2 Explanation

Commitment    Our account for the observations in Sect. 5.2.1 will be more of an engineering nature and thus less explanatory than the account we gave for the other facts. It is basically an attempt to reformulate the observations in theoretical terms and will involve the use of a concept which has featured in several works on the semantics-pragmatics interface, namely the concept of commitment. The term “commitment” has been variously explicated in the literature. In one interpretation, for instance, a speaker a is committed to a proposition p if a makes it public that a believes p (Gunlogson, 2001, 2002, 2003). In another interpretation, a speaker a is committed to a proposition p only if a is prepared to receive social sanctions in case p turns out to be false (Krifka, 2015, 2019a). Commitment has also been conceived of as a three-place relation which obtains between a speaker a, a hearer b, and a proposition p only if a is bound to act towards b in a way consistent with the truth of p (Geurts, 2019a, b). And so on.Footnote 44 We could say of the different attempts at explicating the notion of commitment that they are attempts to identify various pragmatic relations relevant for explaining linguistic intuitions. The fact that these relations are all named “commitment” reflects a family resemblance between them, but nothing deeper. The pragmatic relation we identify for our derivation of the observations discussed in Sect. 5.2.1 is also called “commitment” for this reason. We should therefore not put too much weight on the label. The relation could be called “\({\mathcal {R}}\)” and serve our purposes just as well. What counts is the properties we attribute to it, which are the following.

figure bh

The first condition requires commitments to be consistent. As far as we know, something akin to this is assumed in all interpretations of commitment. The second condition is more interesting. It is, crucially, a pragmatic condition. Violation of it does not lead to logical inconsistency. One may have the thought that a is committed to p and, at the same time, that a’s belief does not guarantee the truth of p. This thought is perfectly coherent. One may even communicate it in some way. What the second condition of commitment claims is only that expressing such a thought verbally would be an odd move in the language game.

Given the conditions on commitment, we propose the following hypothesis.Footnote 45

figure bi

Deriving the observations Let us start with the inability of adverbial modals to scope under negation. Suppose we embed certainly/possibly p under negation, generating the structure in (61).

figure bj

As negation is a hole (Karttunen, 1973; Heim, 1983), the presupposition of \(\beta \) is inherited by \(\alpha \), which means the whole sentence presupposes that the agent, a, is committed to p. If \(\beta \) is certainly p, the sentence would assert \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\). If \(\beta \) is possibly p, the sentence would assert \({\mathcal {B}}_a\lnot p\) which entails \(\lnot {\mathcal {B}}_a p\). In both cases, the presuppositional content says that a is committed to p and the assertive content denies that a believes that p. Thus, the sentence violates the second condition of commitment, hence is pragmatically odd. However, if we embed certain/possible p under negation, there would be no commitment presupposition, so there is no oddness.

Let us now turn to the deviance of possibly p \({\wedge }\) possibly \({\lnot } \textit{q}.\) From the commitment presupposition of adverbial modals it follows that the sentence possibly p \(\wedge \) possibly q presupposes the agent is committed to p and committed to q. If \(p \wedge q\) is a contradiction, this presupposition would contradict the first condition of commitment, causing oddness. In contrast, the sentence possible p \(\wedge \) possible q does not license any inference about commitment. Hence, there is nothing which makes it odd if \(p \wedge q\) is a contradiction.

5.3 A note on scalar implicatures

A question arises at this point about scalar implicatures. It seems natural to assume that possible, possibly, certain, and certainly alternate, i.e. are scale mates of each other. The scale, according to the proposal made here, is then possible p < possibly p < certainly p < certain p, with possible p being the weakest and certain p the strongest. Shouldn’t possibly p, then, implicate \(\lnot \)certainly p, and possible p implicate \(\lnot \)possibly p? But we have just claimed that \(\lnot \)certainly p and \(\lnot \)possibly p are infelicitous. If scalar implicatures are mandatory and sentences with infelicitous implicatures are infelicitous, as many have, we believe, convincingly argued (cf. e.g. Fox & Hackl, 2006; Magri, 2009; Crnič, 2012), shouldn’t possible p and possibly p be infelicitous by virtue of licensing implicatures that are infelicitous?

There are, we believe, two possible responses to this question. Let us represent the strengthened meaning of p, i.e. the conjunction of p and its scalar implicatures, as exh(C)(p), where C is the set of scalar alternatives of p. For present purposes, we can take the interpretation of exh(C)(p) to be (62).Footnote 46

figure bk

The first response, then, is to assume a trivalent semantics and say that “not true” in (62b) means ‘false or undefined’ (Spector & Sudo, 2017). Let \(\lnot q\) be true iff q is false and \(-q\) be true iff q is undefined. Given that \(\lnot \)certainly p and \(\lnot \)possibly p are infelicitous, we end up with the following strengthened meanings.Footnote 47

figure bl

Thus, possibly p would not implicate \(\lnot \)certainly p, i.e. that certainly p is false, but would implicate −certainly p, i.e. that certainly p is undefined, meaning the epistemic agent is not committed to p. Similarly, possible p would implicate that possibly p is undefined, which also means that the epistemic agent is not committed to p. There is, of course, nothing infelicitous about this inference.

The second response is to keep to bivalent semantics and appeal to the fact that C, the set of alternatives, can be adjusted (Chierchia et al., 2012; Crnič et al., 2015; Buccola & Haida, 2019, 2020). Specifically, C can be construed as a proper subset of the total set of alternatives. Certain alternatives can be “pruned” from the computation of strengthened meaning, where the condition for pruning a proposition is that it is not in the Boolean closure of the remaining propositions (Fox & Katzir, 2011; Trinh & Haida, 2015; Trinh, 2018). This approach would give us the following strengthened meanings. We indicate the pruning by .Footnote 48

figure bn

We will not attempt to adjudicate between the trivalent and the bivalent approach. The point we are making here is only that semantic strengthening by scalar implicatures should not pose a problem for our explanation of the facts in 5.2.1 and 5.2.1 in terms of the commitment presupposition of adverbial modals. We do want to note, however, that both approaches converge on the following prediction.

figure bo

The prediction is interesting insofar as it might give us a clue as to how to explain a puzzling contrast, namely that between (66a) and (66b).Footnote 49

figure bp

Let us entertain the following hypothesis: the locution p, in fact q is natural to the extent that \(\lnot q\) could in principle be an implicature of p. Given this hypothesis, the contrast in (66) would follow from the prediction about implicatures. The hypothesis would also make sense of the contrast between (67a) and (67b).

figure bq

As hot is an alternative of warm but warm and not hot is not, \(\lnot \)hot is a possible implicature of warm but \(\lnot \)(warm and not hot) is not.Footnote 50

6 Open issues

There are several issues left open in the discussion above. We briefly mention some of them in this section.

6.1 Syntactic versus morphological negation

First, we did not address the difference in degrees of acceptability as observed in a number of cases. Specifically, the theory we propose would predict both of the sentences in (68a) and (68b) to be equally deviant. However, they obviously are not.

figure br

We believe the contrast between (68a) and (68b) has to do with the fact that syntax is more productive than morphology. The linguistic system seems to treat words as “permanent” and syntactic phrases as more “transient”. Consequently, it seems to resist generating words which cause pragmatic oddness more strongly than it resists generating phrases which cause pragmatic oddness.

6.2 Other lexical items and languages

In this paper we concentrate on English certain/certainly and possible/possibly. It is, of course, plausible that our analysis can extend to other items in English as well as to other languages. A cursory look at probable and probably suggests that these modals behave as expected. For example, probable can occur in if-clauses while probably cannot.Footnote 51

figure bs

Also, the German counterparts of certain/certainly and possible/possibly seem to behave as predicted as well. For example, sicher ‘certain’ can combine with the negative prefix un–, but not sicherlich (Krifka, b).

figure bt

We must leave the task of looking at other items and other languages for another occasion.

6.3 Certainly versus believe

Another contrast we did not address is that in (71).

figure bu

Let p be the proposition that John is guilty and a be the speaker. According to our proposal, the first sentence of (71b) means \({\mathcal {B}}_a p\), i.e. that p is true in all worlds compatible with a’s belief, and the second sentence of (71b) means \({\mathcal {K}}_a p\), i.e. that p is true in all worlds compatible with a’s knowledge. But doesn’t that mean (71b) says exactly what (71a) says? Why, then, should there be a contrast between these two sentences?

A related contrast is that in (72).

figure bv

We do not have an explanation for (71) and (72).Footnote 52 However, we do have a hunch as to what an explanation may involve. Our hunch is that the contrasts are due, in part, to the difference between believe and certainly. Thus, it has been observed that believe does not really express belief in the sense of truth in all doxastic alternatives, which is what we take certainly to express, but something weaker (Hawthorne et al., 2016; Rothschild, 2020). This is evidenced by the contrast in (73).Footnote 53

figure bw

We stress, again, that this is not an explanation of the contrast in (71), but just a hunch as to what direction such an explanation may go.

6.4 Certain versus know

We have explained several facts about adverbial modals in terms of positive assumptions about belief, e.g. that agents have introspective access to their belief (introspection) and that commitment is pragmatically incompatible with explicit denial of belief (commitment). However, the reader will have noticed that facts about adjectival modals are explained “negatively”, so to speak. Specifically, all we need to say about these items to account for the facts is really that they quantify over a domain which is larger than belief and which is not subject to the such conditions as imposed by introspection and commitment on belief. That knowledge happens to fit the description of such a domain is the reason we hypothesize that adjectival modals quantify over knowledge.

But this move, of course, raises the question to what extent certain resembles the verb know.Footnote 54 We think that in this connection there are some intriguing observations which we cannot yet explain but which we will present here as stimuli for further thought. First, we observe that when the epistemic agent is implicit, certain can be said to license the “factive” inference that the prejacent proposition is true, just as is the case with know.

figure bx

When the epistemic agent is expressed in form of a modifier, the factive inference seems to disappear with both know and certain.

figure by

When the epistemic agent is expressed in form of a nominative subject, however, only know remains factive.

figure bz

So far we have not discussed sentences such as (76b), where certain has the syntax of an attitude predicate.Footnote 55 We are open to the possibility that this use of certain may involve a different lexical item from the one we have been talking about. However, it would be interesting if the same semantics underlies both uses. Whether this is the case, and what accounts for the observations above, are questions we will have to leave to future research.

7 Comments on previous works

Adjectival and adverbial modals have been the focus of a relatively small subset of works on modality. A common theme which runs through several of these analyses is that the distinction between adjectival and the adverbial modals align more or less with the distinction between “objective” and “subjective” modality, respectively (cf. e.g. Hengeveld, 1988, 1989; Nuyts, 1993, 2001; Krifka, 2020a, b). To the best of our knowledge, Lyons (1977) was the first to point out and discuss this subdivision among epistemic modals, and his elaboration on the terms “subjective” and “objective” remains the basis for a kind of family resemblance among many proposals that have since been made. Here is one relevant passage.

Subjective epistemic modality can be accounted for [...] in terms of the speaker’s qualification of the I-say-so component of his utterance. Objectively modalized utterances [...] can be described as having an unqualified I-say-so component, but an it-is-so component that is qualified [...]. (Lyons, 1977: 800)

What Lyons called the “I-say-so component” and the “it-is-so component” are what many would call the speech act level and the propositional level of meaning representation. Lyons held the view that the speech act level is hierarchically higher than the propositional level, as he stated, at one point, that “subjective modality always has higher scope than objective modality” (Lyons, 1977: 808). This view of how the meaning of an utterance is organized has a long tradition and is still subscribed to in recent works (Frege, 1879; Stenius, 1967; Ross, 1970; Lakoff, 1970; Sadock, 1974; Gazdar, 1979; Cinque, 1999; Krifka, 2001, 2015, 2017; Sauerland & Yatsushiro, 2017). It leads to syntactic analyses of the following sort.

figure ca

In (77), \(\phi \) represents a proposition whereas \(\beta \) represents a speech act. The two remaining nodes \(\gamma \) and \(\alpha \) represent a qualified proposition and a qualified speech act, respectively. Thus, the adjectival and the adverbial modals compose with semantic objects of different kinds. The prejacent of possibly in John possibly passed the exam and the prejacent of possible in it is possible that John passed the exam, for example, are in fact not semantically identical. The illusion that they are is due to the silence of the speech act operator(s). This, we believe, is the basic idea underlying the analyses proposed in Bellert (1977), Piñon (2006, 2009), Wolf (2014, 2015), and Krifka (2020a, b).

With respect to the facts discussed in the previous sections, these analyses have some advantages and some disadvantages. The advantages, we believe, would pertain most clearly to the non-equivalence of adjectival modals and their adverbial counterparts, and the inability of adverbial modals to be embedded under if and negation. It seems natural for certainly \(\phi \) and certain \(\psi \), for example, to not be equivalent, given that \(\phi \) represents a speech act and \(\psi \) represents a proposition. It also seems natural for speech acts to be unembeddable under linguistic operators such as negation, and for if-clauses to not constitute speech acts. The disadvantages, we believe, would pertain most clearly to lassiter’s observation and the facts discussed in 4.4.3. Why, and how, do the speech act operators reverse the relative strength of the items? And why should the sentence become better when speech act operators are more deeply embedded? For the other facts, it is not clear to us how the structure in (77) would be of help, but neither it is clear to us that it would pose a problem. We should stress, in this connection, that our purpose here is not to dismiss the speech act analysis of adverbial modals, but to explore another kind of analysis and unify under it some seemingly unrelated phenomena.

Nilsen (2004) proposes an analysis which contains two ideas that make it similar to ours and different from the speech act analysis. The first is that both the adjectival and the adverbial modals compose with propositions. The second is that domain reduction is involved. Nilsen’s empirical focus is on the adverbial modals’ inability to occur in if-clauses and under negation. He takes these facts to show that adverbial modals are “excluded from the same type of environments that license NPIs” (Nilsen, 2004: 811), and that they are mirror images of NPIs in the sense that whereas NPIs require strengthening by way of domain expansion (Kadmon & Landman, 1993; Krifka, 1995; Chierchia, 2004), adverbial modals require strengthening by way of domain reduction. The semantics Nilsen proposes is based on the notion of “degree of plausibility” and is quite different from ours (Wolf, 2014; Nilsen, 2004: 830). Without going into the details of Nilsen’s analysis, we will just mention two major problems that we see with it. First, Nilsen’s theory requires that domain reduction be strengthening for both universal and existential modals. This, as we saw, is logically not possible. The result is that Nilsen’s theory works for possible and possibly but does not work for certain and certainly. This problem is recognized by Nilsen himself, who notes that the prediction made for certain and certainly by the theory is “plainly wrong” (Nilsen, 2004: 827). In the end, Nilsen is forced to stipulate a semantics for certainly while leaving certain out of consideration entirely and conceding that the paper is really just about possible and possibly (Nilsen, 2004: 830, 809). This discrepancy in Nilsen’s theory has been criticized by Wolf (2014: 123–124) and, before that, by Wolf (2006: 4), who notes that “[f]or consistency, Nilsen should extend his strategy to all modal adverbs, though he does not actually do this for certain versus certainly.”

The second problem with Nilsen’s theory, as we can see, is that it would not account for the many other facts that we discussed. Moreover, we do not think that his claim that adverbial modals are “excluded from the same type of environments that license NPIs” is correct. It has been pointed out, for instance, that possibly can occur in questions (cf. Ernst, 2009: 521; Herbstritt, 2020: 41; Giannakidou & Mari, 2021), as evidenced by the acceptability of (78a), an example taken from Giannakidou and Mari (2021). In addition, all of the other sentences in (78) are fine too, which show that adverbial modals can occur in the restriction of every and no and in the scope of only. These, however, are environments that license NPIs.

figure cb

8 Conclusion

The initial intuition about the adjectival modals certain and possible on the one hand and their adverbial counterparts certainly and possibly on the other is that they are syntactically different but semantically identical. While this intuition is grounded in some facts, there are other facts about these items which show that it cannot be entirely correct. We present several such facts and propose an account for them. At the center of our account is the hypothesis that the adjectival modals quantify over knowledge while the adverbial modals quantify over belief. The facts are then derived from claims about knowledge and belief, some of which are basic and non-controversial, others are less so. The former are (i) that everything that is known is also believed, and (ii) that people know whether they believe something or not. The latter are (i) that if something is relevant then whether it is believed is also relevant, and (ii) that it is odd to be committed to something and at the same time say that you do not believe it.