Skip to main content
Log in

Well-being Monism Defended

  • Research Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Happiness Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In “Well-Being and Pluralism” (2021), Polly Mitchell and Anna Alexandrova defend conceptual pluralism about well-being. Conceptual pluralism about well-being holds that there are multiple, irreducible concepts of well-being that are employed in different contexts, all equally legitimate as concepts of well-being. Moreover, "Conceptual pluralism about well-being entails that there is no single essence which characterises all and only instances of well-being” (Mitchell and Alexandrova in J Happiness Stud 22:2411–2433, 2021). Conceptual monism about well-being, on the other hand, holds, at a minimum, that there is some essence that unites all legitimate uses of 'well-being'. In this paper, I will argue that there is a version of conceptual monism about well-being, the network theory of well-being defended by Michael Bishop in his book The Good Life (2015), that can secure all of the benefits of Mitchell and Alexandrova's conceptual pluralism, namely accommodating the wide range of uses of “well-being” in the sciences of well-being and in ordinary language. Mitchell and Alexandrova’s argument for pluralism depends on the inability of a monistic theory of well-being to account for this diversity of conceptions of well-being and the diversity of instruments used to measure well-being in the sciences. Bishop’s network theory, like Mitchell and Alexandrova’s pluralism, is designed to accommodate the scientific study of well-being. Because of this, it avoids the pitfalls of traditional, monistic conceptions of well-being despite its monistic credentials. I conclude with two novel arguments for the network theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Mitchell and Alexandrova (2021, p. 2424). Conceptual pluralism about well-being is often defended under the banner of “contextualism.” Mitchell and Alexandrova cite Darwall (2002), Campbell (2016), Alexandrova (2017), and Mitchell (2018) as examples of contextualists about well-being. I will stick with “conceptual pluralism” or “conceptual pluralism about well-being” for the sake of clarity.

  2. Constitutive pluralism is the view that “well-being refers to a particular, identifiable state [that] can be constituted by different properties or objects” (Mitchell & Alexandrova, 2021, p. 2422). Contrast this with conceptual pluralism, according to which there is no single state that can be identified across all instances of well-being.

  3. This was pointed out by an anonymous reviewer.

  4. More on PCN fragments below. For now, let it suffice that they are potential causal contributors to PCNs.

  5. Bishop (2015, p. 41). Bishop does not defend a network theory of ill-being, but he does suggest that some instances of ill-being can be profitably understood as negative or vicious causal networks. (2015, pp. 96-101).

  6. Bishop (2015, p. 42). See Csikszentmihalyi (2008) for more on the state of flow.

  7. Mitchell and Alexandrova (2021, p. 2413, Tables 1 and 2).

  8. Reproduction of Bishop (2015, Fig. 4.1) Reproduced with permission of the Licensor through PLSclear.

  9. See Sect. 3.2.1 above for the quote from DeNeve and Cooper (1998).

  10. See, for example, (Kern et al., 2019) and (Arnold & Wade, 2015).

  11. Wissing argues that the “‘third wave of Positive Psychology’ was actually the beginning of a new scientific domain of well-being studies” (Wissing, 2022, p. 15). I take no stand on the issue of dividing Positive Psychology from the newly emerging well-being sciences in this manuscript.

References

  • Alexandrova, A. (2017). A philosophy for the science of well-being. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anto, J. M., Martí, J. L., Casals, J., Bou-Habib, P., Casal, P., Fleurbaey, M., et al. (2021). The planetary wellbeing initiative: Pursuing the sustainable development goals in higher education. Sustainability, 13, 3372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, R. D., & Wade, J. P. (2015). A definition of systems thinking: A systems approach. Procedia Computer Science, 44(2015), 669–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, R. (1987). Mood interviewer and the evaluation of job candidates. Journal of Applied Psychology, 69, 911–926.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berry, D., & Hansen, J. S. (1996). Positive affect, negative affect, and social interaction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71, 796–809.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, M. (2015). The good life. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1972). Determinism, laws and predictability in principle. Philosophy of Science, 39, 431–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1979). Metaphor and theory change. In A. Ortony (Ed.), Metaphor and thought. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1982). Scientific realism and naturalistic epistemology. In P. D. Asquith & R. N. Giere (Eds.), PSA 1980. (Vol. 2). Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1983). On the current status of the issue of scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 19, 45–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1985a). Lex orendi est lex credendi. In P. Churchland & C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Scientific realism versus constructive empiricism. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1985b). Observations, explanatory power, and simplicity. In P. Achinstein & O. Hannaway (Eds.), Observation, experiment, and hypothesis in modern physical science. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1985c). The logician’s dilemma: Deductive logic, inductive inference and logical empiricism. Erkenntnis, 22, 197–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1988). How to be a moral realist. In G. Sayre-McCord (Ed.), Essays on moral realism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, S. M. (2016). The concept of well-being. In G. Fletcher (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of well-being. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, C., Plumb, E., Hawley, K., Spaventa-Vancil, K., & Hernández, R. (2015). Integrating positive psychology into family therapy: Positive family therapy. The Counseling Psychologist, 43(5), 703–733.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csikszentmihalyi, M. (2008). Flow: The psychology of optimal experience. Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, M. (1988). Does happiness mean friendliness? Induced mood and heterosexual self-disclosure. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 14, 283–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2002). Welfare and rational care. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Delle Fave, A. (2018). “The heuristic potential of interconnectedness models in well-being research,” In Keynote presented at the First Africa Conference on Positive Psychology , Potchefstroom, South Africa, (Potchefstroom: ACPP).

  • Delle Fave, A., & Massimini, F. (2015). Cultural change and human behavior: Evolution or development? Crossing Border. International Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies, 3, 41–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeNeve, K. M., & Cooper, H. (1998). The happy personality: A meta-analysis of 137 personality traits and subjective well-being. Psychological Bulletin, 124, 197–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutton, J. E., & Workman, K. M. (2012). Compassion as a generative force. Journal of Management Inquiry, 20(4), 401–406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutton, J. E., Workman, K. M., & Hardin, A. E. (2014). Compassion at work. The Annual Review of Organizational Psychology and Organizational Behavior, 1(1), 277–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engel, G. L. (1978). The biopsychosocial model and the education of health professionals. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 310, 169–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, H. (1956). Some major issues and developments in the philosophy of science of logical empiricism. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins, J. (2019). Diversity of meaning and the value of a concept: Comments on Anna Alexandrova’s A philosophy for the science of well-being. Res Philosophica, 96(4), 529–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Judge, T., & Higgins, C. (1998). Affective disposition and the letter of reference. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 75(3), 207–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kern, M. L., Williams, P., Spong, C., Colla, R., Sharma, K., Downie, A., et al. (2019). Systems informed positive psychology. Journal of Positive Psychology., 15(6), 705–715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1972). Naming and necessity. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), The semantics of natural language. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lerner, H., & Berg, C. (2017). A comparison of three holistic approaches to health: One health, ecohealth, and planetary health. Frontiers in Veterinary Science, 4, 163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lomas, T., Waters, L., Williams, P., Oades, L. G., & Kern, M. L. (2021). Third wave positive psychology: Broadening towards complexity. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 16(5), 660–674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lueddeke, G. (2019). Survival: One health, one planet, one future. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyubomirsky, K., & Diener. (2005). The benefits of frequent positive affect: Does happiness lead to success. Psychological Bulletin, 131(6), 803–855.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyubomirsky, S., & Tucker, K. (1998). Implications of individual differences in subjective happiness for perceiving, interpreting, and thinking about life events. Motivation and Emotion, 22(2), 155–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Massimini, F., & Delle Fave, A. (2000). Individual development in a bio-cultural perspective. American Psychologist, 55, 24–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mead, J., Fisher, Z., & Kemp, A. H. (2021). Moving beyond disciplinary silos towards a transdisciplinary model of wellbeing: An invited review. Frontiers in Psychology, 12, 642093.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, P. (2018). The construction of well-being. Ph.D. Thesis. University College London.

  • Mitchell, P., & Alexandrova, A. (2021). Well-being and pluralism. Journal of Happiness Studies, 22, 2411–2433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and Utopia. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Mind, language and reality. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rabinowitz, P. M., Pappaioanou, M., Bardosh, K. L., & Conti, L. (2018). A planetary vision for one health. BMJ Global Health, 3, e001137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheridan, S. M., Warnes, E. D., Cowan, R. J., Schemm, A. V., & Clarke, B. L. (2004). Family-centered positive psychology: Focusing on strengths to build student success. Psychology in the Schools, 41(1), 7–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sumner, L. W. (1996). Welfare, happiness, and ethics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, L. (2020). Using positive psychology interventions to strengthen family happiness: A family systems approach. Journal of Positive Psychology., 15(5), 645–652.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wissing, M. P. (2022). Beyond the “third wave of Positive Psychology”: Challenges and opportunities for future research. Frontiers in Psychology, 12, 795067.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

No funding was provided by any organization for the research, writing, or publication of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emelia Miller.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

I, the author, have no financial or non-financial interests relevant to this paper.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Miller, E. Well-being Monism Defended. J Happiness Stud 23, 3407–3427 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-022-00551-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-022-00551-0

Keywords

Navigation