Skip to main content
Log in

New Data on the Linguistic Diversity of Authorship in Philosophy Journals

  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper investigates the representation of authors with different linguistic backgrounds in academic publishing. We first review some common rebuttals of concerns about linguistic injustice. We then analyze 1039 authors of philosophy journals, primarily selected from the 2015 Leiter Report. While our data show that Anglophones dominate the output of philosophy papers, this unequal distribution cannot be solely attributed to language capacities. We also discover that ethics journals have more Anglophone authors than logic journals and that most authors (73.40%) are affiliated with English-speaking universities, suggesting other factors (e.g. philosophical areas and academic resources) may also play significant roles. Moreover, some interesting results are revealed when we combine the factor of sex with place of affiliation and linguistic background. It indicates that while certain linguistic injustice is inevitable in academic publishing, it may be more complex than thought. We next introduce Broadbent’s (Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 40:302–311, 2009a, Legal Theory 15:173–191, 2009b, Philos Stud 158(3):457–476, 2012, Philosophy of epidemiology, Palgrave Macmillan, New York, 2013, Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 48:250–257, 2014) contrastive account of causation to give a causal explanation of our findings. Broadbent’s account not only well characterizes the multifaceted causality in academic publishing but also provides a methodological guideline for further investigation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The meaning of “Anglophone” can be ambiguous sometimes. For example, while Oxford English Dictionary defines it as an English-speaking person, Cambridge English Dictionary and Merriam-Webster Dictionary define it as a person who speaks English, especially in countries where other languages are also spoken. In this study, the term is used to refer to linguistic communities whose members speak English as their native or first language regardless of the location of these communities. This interpretation allows us to make a distinction between one’s linguistic background and one’s geographical location and to compare all the possible combinations of pairs of groups on the two variables.

  2. Likewise situations are rather common in the area of chronic diseases, primarily cancer and cardiovascular disease. There is usually a large number of factors involved in the development of these diseases, but presence of those factors might not always result in the expected disease.

  3. They are consistency, strength, specificity, temporal relation, and coherence of the association.

  4. For examples of the causal criteria in Epidemiology, see Hill (1965) and Susser (1991).

  5. In this study, Anglosphere refers to English-speaking nations including the US, the UK, Australia, Canada, Ireland, Singapore, and New Zealand. All have similar cultural roots back to the British Empire.

  6. These clues include names, other languages of research, the match between the place of birth and that of receiving first degree, etc.

  7. As estimated in 2017, only about 5% of the global population (estimated 7.5 billions) are native English speakers (estimated 372 millions).

  8. Examples include insufficient funding and peers to discuss with, unable to attend conferences, disconnect to the previous academic networks, or unfamiliar with journals’ rules of game. The scholars may be isolated from the mainstream of professional community and resources, affecting the quality and quantity of their research (Hyland 2016a; Ferguson 2007).

  9. Beyond that, current evidence for gender bias in journal peer review is weak (Lee et al. 2012; Resnik and Elmore 2016).

  10. Take cigarette smoking and lung cancer for example. On the one hand, there is a significant positive association between the two. On the other hand, such measure of strength of association is causally neutral. When it is used to make about some causal claim, we need to give an account of how a causal interpretation of the measure of association works. See Broadbent (2013, pp. 34–50) for his diagnosis of how the rival approaches, the probabilistic approach and the counterfactual approach, fail the task.

  11. See also Schaffer (2005, pp. 327–329, 2010). He too also holds a contrastive view of causation but with a contrast for both cause and effect.

  12. That is, it is more challenging for p to disseminate her work due to the difficulty getting her work published.

  13. A SYMPTOM is a difference between p and a contrast class.

  14. These factors are chosen based on our data in Sect. 3. They are the explanatory causes of one’s being in an underprivileged position in publication.

  15. So the controls may include, say, native English speakers who are also novices in academia and do not have to make an extra effort (as p does) to disseminate their work, senior non-native English scholars who do not have to make an extra effort (as p does) to disseminate their work, and so forth. People who have to make an extra effort (as p does) to disseminate their work are excluded from the controls due to the first condition. People who are with every cause listed in the second condition are excluded from the controls too. On this approach, the exclusion of cases from the controls can itself be analyzed contrastively further. See Broadbent (2013, pp. 158–159, 2014).

  16. For a review of this literature, see Jost et al. (2009).

  17. While the discrimination led by implicit biases is often unintentional, unendorsed, and perpetrated without the agent’s awareness, it does not follow that the agent is without control of it (Suhler and Churchland 2009).

  18. In an earlier version of this paper, we used Chen’s (2013, 2014) account of structural causation, instead of Broadbent’s contrastive account of causation, to interpret our data. While Chen’s theory is a pertinent one, his papers are written in Mandarin and not accessible in English. So we were suggested to include a link to the common literature on causation.

References

  • Advisory Committee to the Surgeon General of the Public Health Service. (1964). Smoking and health: Report of the advisory committee to the surgeon general. Atlanta: Public Health Service, US Department of Health, Education and Welfare.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bortolus, A. (2012). Running like Alice and losing good ideas: On the quasi-compulsive use of English by non-native English speaking scientists. Ambio, 41(7), 769–772.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broadbent, A. (2009a). Causation and models of disease in epidemiology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 40, 302–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broadbent, A. (2009b). Fact and law in the causal inquiry. Legal Theory, 15, 173–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broadbent, A. (2012). Causes of causes. Philosophical Studies, 158(3), 457–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broadbent, A. (2013). Philosophy of epidemiology. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Braodbent, A. (2014). Disease as a theoretical concept: The case of “HPV-it is”. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 48, 250–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cancer Research UK (CRUK). (2016). Smoking facts and evidence. Web. Retrieved from http://www.cancerresearchuk.org/about-cancer/causes-of-cancer/smoking-and-cancer/smoking-facts-and-evidence. Accessed 21 Feb 2018.

  • Chen, R.-L. (2013). Constructing a causal reasoning for the RCA event—an approach based on structural causation and abduction. SOCIETAS: A Journal for Philosophical Study of Public Affairs, 46, 81–130. (in Mandarin).

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, R.-L. (2014). Flying out from the cage: Reflections on causation in Taiwan’s public health cases. Academia Sinica Law Journal, 15, 283–329. (in Mandarin).

    Google Scholar 

  • Clavero, M. (2011). Language bias in ecological journals. Frontiers in Ecology and the Environment, 9(2), 93–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corcoran, J. N. (2015). English as the international language of science: A case study of Mexican scientists’ writing for publication (Doctoral dissertation, University of Toronto).

  • Daniel, H.-D. (1993). Guardians of science: Fairness and reliability of peer review. Weinheim, Germany: Wiley-VCH.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Schutter, H. (2014). Testing for linguistic injustice: Territoriality and pluralism. Nationalities Papers, 42(6), 1034–1052.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Schutter, H. (2017a). Global, interlinguistic and intralinguistic linguistic justice. Workshop on Language, Nationalism, Nations: Multilingualism Beyond Europe, Princeton University, 29–30 September 2017.

  • De Schutter, H. (2017b). Two principles of equal language recognition. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 20(1), 75–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Schutter, H., & Robichaud, D. (2015). Van Parijsian linguistic justice–context, analysis, and critiques. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 18(2), 87–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Bitetti, M. S., & Ferreras, J. A. (2017). Publish (in English) or perish: The effect on citation rate of using languages other than English in scientific publications. Ambio, 46(1), 121–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ernst, E., & Kienbacher, T. (1991). Chauvinism. Nature, 352, 560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferguson, G. (2007). The global spread of English, scientific communication and ESP: Questions of equity, access and domain loss. Ibérica, 13, 7–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guariguata, M. R., Sheil, D., & Murdiyarso, D. (2011). ‘Linguistic injustice’ is not black and white. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 26(2), 58–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, A. B. (1965). The environment and disease: Association or causation. Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine, 58, 295–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holroyd, J. (2012). Responsibility for implicit bias. Journal of Social Philosophy, 43(3), 274–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hyland, K. (2016a). Academic publishing and the myth of linguistic injustice. Journal of Second Language Writing, 31, 58–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hyland, K. (2016b). Language myths and publishing mysteries: A response to Politzer-Ahles et al. Journal of Second Language Writing, 34, 9–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jost, J. T., Rudman, L. A., Blair, I. V., Carney, D. R., Dasgupta, N., Glaser, J., et al. (2009). The existence of implicit bias is beyond reasonable doubt: A refutation of ideological and methodological objections and executive summary of ten studies that no manager should ignore. Research in Organizational Behavior, 29, 39–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langum, V., & Sullivan, K. P. (2017). Writing academic english as a doctoral student in sweden: Narrative perspectives. Journal of Second Language Writing, 35, 20–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, C. (2010). Information structure in PA/SN or descriptive/metalinguistic negation: with reference to scalar implicatures. In Dingfang Shu & Ken Turner (Eds.), Contrasting meanings in languages of the east and west (pp. 33–73). New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, C. J., Sugimoto, C. R., Zhang, G., & Cronin, B. (2012). Bias in peer review. Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology, 64(1), 2–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Li, C. I. (1997). Logical entailment and conversational implication: A discourse-pragmatic account of Taiwanese toh (就) and ciah (才). Journal of Taiwan Normal University: Humanities & Social Science, 42, 55–70. https://doi.org/10.6210/JNTNULL.1997.42.05.

    Google Scholar 

  • Link, A. M. (1998). US and non-US submissions. Journal of the American Medical Association, 280(3), 246–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacMahon, B., & Pugh, T. F. (1970). Epidemiology: Principles and methods. Boston: Little, Brown & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, S. (2015). The problem with English (es) and linguistic (in) justice. Addressing the limits of liberal egalitarian accounts of language. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 18(2), 131–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mori, A. S., Qian, S., & Tatsumi, S. (2015). Academic inequality through the lens of community ecology: A meta-analysis. PeerJ, 3, e1457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Politzer-Ahles, S., Holliday, J. J., Girolamo, T., Spychalska, M., & Berkson, K. H. (2016). Is linguistic injustice a myth? A response to Hyland (2016). Journal of Second Language Writing, 34, 3–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Primack, R. B., Ellwood, E., Miller-Rushing, A. J., Marrs, R., & Mulligan, A. (2009). Do gender, nationality, or academic age affect review decisions? An analysis of submissions to the journal Biological Conservation. Biological Conservation, 142(11), 2415–2418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. (2015). How inclusive is European philosophy of science? International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(2), 149–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, D., & Elmore, S. (2016). Ensuring the quality, fairness, and integrity of journal peer review: A possible role of editors. Science and Engineering Ethics, 22(1), 169–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2005). Contrastive causation. Philosophical Review, 114, 327–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2010). Contrastive causation in the law. Legal Theory, 16, 259–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Subtirelu, N. (2016). Denying language privilege in academic publishing. [Web log post]. Retrieved from https://linguisticpulse.com/2016/03/28/denying-language-privilege-in-academic-publishing/. Accessed 21 Feb 2018.

  • Suhler, C., & Churchland, P. (2009). Control: Conscious and otherwise”. Trends in cognitive sciences, 13(8), 341–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Susser, M. W. (1991). What is a cause and how do we know one? A grammar for pragmatic epidemiology. American Journal of Epidemiology, 133, 635–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Parijs, P. (2011). Linguistic justice for Europe and for the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press on Demand.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Parijs, P. (2015). Lingua franca and linguistic territoriality. Why they both matter to justice and why justice matters for both. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 18(2), 224–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weihelm, I., Conklin, S. L., & Hassoun, N. (2017). New data on the representation of women in philosophy journals: 2004–2015. Philosophical Studies, 1–27. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0919-0.

  • Wellmon, C., & Piper, A. (2017). Publication, power, and patronage: On inequality and academic publishing. Critical Inquiry. https://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/publication_power_and_patronage_on_inequality_and_academic_publishing/. Accessed 21 Feb 2018

  • Wolters, G. (2015). Globalized parochialism: Consequences of english as Lingua Franca in philosophy of science. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(2), 189–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • World Bank. (2012). Annual report. World Bank. Retrieved from http://siteresources.worldbank.org/EXTANNREP2012/Resources/8784408-1346247445238/AnnualReport2012_En.pdfi.

  • Wright, S. (2015). What is language? A response to Philippe van Parijs. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 18(2), 113–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tzu-Wei Hung.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Yen, CP., Hung, TW. New Data on the Linguistic Diversity of Authorship in Philosophy Journals. Erkenn 84, 953–974 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-9989-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-9989-4

Navigation