Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemic Responsibility in Business: An Integrative Framework for an Epistemic Ethics

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

How can we make businesspeople more concerned about the truth of the information they spread or allow to circulate? In this age of ‘fake news’, ‘business bullshit’ and ‘post-truth,’ the issue is of the utmost importance, especially for business trustworthiness in the internet economy. The issue is related to a kind of epistemic responsibility, that consists in accounting for one’s own epistemic wrongdoings, such as making a third party believe something false. Despite growing interest in epistemic misbehavior in the literature of business ethics, the question of epistemic responsibility has been neglected. The aim of this paper is therefore to address this gap, by proposing a notion of epistemic responsibility for business, that may help regulate undesirable epistemic behavior, such as the spreading of false information. To define this notion of epistemic responsibility, I have introduced the concept of epistemic fault. Being epistemically responsible consists in being disposed to account for alleged epistemic faults. This notion of epistemic fault relies on a theoretical framework which combines a typology of eight ‘epistemic values’, a normative stance regarding these values, and a dispositional approach to epistemic virtues and vices. I use this theoretical framework to integrate the various accounts of epistemic virtues and vices found in the literature into a single explanatory scheme. Combined with the notion of epistemic responsibility itself, such an integrative framework should facilitate the practical application of an operational epistemic ethics in business, i.e., the development of virtuous epistemic practices.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. These two expressions are often used interchangeably in the literature. I have chosen to use the term epistemic, for reasons which will become clear later.

  2. This model is inspired by Koppl (2006), who outlines a mathematical theory of epistemic systems. According to Koppl (2006), epistemic systems are “social processes viewed from the perspective of their tendency to help or frustrate the production of true judgements” (Koppl, 2006, p. 91). Mathematically, Koppl (2006) models an epistemic system as a set of senders, S, a set of receivers, R, and a set of messages.

  3. Epistemologists make the distinction between "trait virtues" and "faculty virtues". Faculty virtues are truth-conducive cognitive faculties. Here, however, I consider only trait virtues.

  4. It is also a contribution to the debate on the unity of epistemic virtues (Goldman, 2001).

  5. Technically, this means that the locution “epistemic vice” must be ‘predicative’ (Ridge, 2013, p. 188), since “is epistemic vice” entails both ‘is epistemic’ and ‘is a vice’.

  6. Like Battaly (2017), I do not think that this last kind of epistemic justice, called “hermeneutical epistemic injustice” by Fricker (2007), is a vice, since the deviation is not clearly avoidable, and therefore does not clearly constitute a fault. However, I will not elaborate on this point in this paper.

  7. This is why I have chosen the term epistemic ethics, not intellectual ethics.

References

  • Alston, W. P. (2005). Beyond “justification”: Dimensions of epistemic evaluation. Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baird, C., & Calvard, T. S. (2018). Epistemic vices in organizations: Knowledge, truth, and unethical conduct. Journal of Business Ethics, 160(1), 263–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Battaly, H. (2017). Testimonial injustice, epistemic vice, and vice epistemology. In I. J. Kidd, J. Medina, & J. G. Pohlhaus (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of epistemic injustice (pp. 223–231). Taylor and Francis.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Booth, A., & de Bruin, B. (2019). Stakes sensitivity and credit rating: A new challenge for regulators. Journal of Business Ethics, 169(1), 169–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borg, E., & Hooker, B. (2019). Epistemic virtues versus ethical values in the financial services sector. Journal of Business Ethics, 155(1), 17–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouilloud, J.-P., Deslandes, G., & Mercier, G. (2019). The leader as chief truth officer: The ethical responsibility of “managing the truth” in organizations. Journal of Business Ethics, 157(1), 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A. (2002). Social moral epistemology. Social Philosophy & Policy, 19(2), 126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carreyrou, J. (2018). Bad blood: Secrets and lies in a silicon valley startup. Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cederblom, J., & Paulsen, D. W. (2005). Critical reasoning. Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chase, J., & Coady, D. (2018). The return of applied epistemology. In D. Coady & J. Chase (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of applied epistemology (pp. 3–12). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chignell, A. (2018). The ethics of belief. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Choo, C. W. (2016). The inquiring organization: How organizations acquire knowledge and seek information. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crossman, J., & Doshi, V. (2015). When not knowing is a virtue: A business ethics perspective. Journal of Business Ethics, 131(1), 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Bruin, B. (2013). Epistemic virtues in business. Journal of Business Ethics, 113(4), 583–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Bruin, B. (2015). Ethics and the global financial crisis. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Duong, C., Pescetto, G., & Santamaria, D. (2014). How value–glamour investors use financial information: UK evidence of investors’ confirmation bias. The European Journal of Finance, 20(6), 524–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. Z. (2017). True enough. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Engel, P. (2019). Les vices du savoir: Essai d’éthique intellectuelle. Agone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Facebook. (2019, October 17). Mark Zuckerberg stands for voice and free expression. About Facebook. Retrieved from https://about.fb.com/news/2019/10/mark-zuckerberg-stands-for-voice-and-free-expression/.

  • Fassio, D. (2016). Une explication instrumentale de la relation entre assertion et connaissance. In J.-M. Chevalier & B. Gaultier (Eds.), La connaissance et ses raisons. Collège de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frostenson, M. (2016). Humility in business: A contextual approach. Journal of Business Ethics, 138(1), 91–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • García-Carpintero, M. (2004). Assertion and the semantics of force-markers. In C. Bianchi (Ed.), The semantics/pragmatics distinction (pp. 133–166). CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1999). Knowledge in a Social World. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2001). The unity of the epistemic virtues. In A. Fairweather & L. Zagzebski (Eds.), Virtue epistemology: Essays on epistemic virtue and responsibility (pp. 30–48). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J., & Turri, J. (2016). Virtue epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grey, C., & Garsten, C. (2001). Trust, control and post-bureaucracy. Organization Studies, 22(2), 229–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1991). Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. M. (2006). Can we teach character? An Aristotelian answer. Academy of Management Learning & Education, 5(1), 68–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa, J. J., & Steup, M. (2018). The analysis of knowledge. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford University, Metaphysics Research Lab.

    Google Scholar 

  • Intezari, A., & Pauleen, D. J. (2014). Management wisdom in perspective: Are you virtuous enough to succeed in volatile times? Journal of Business Ethics, 120(3), 393–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Intezari, A., Pauleen, D., & Rooney, D. (2016). Rediscovering philosophia: The PhD as a path to enhancing knowledge, wisdom and creating a better world. Journal of Business Ethics Education, 13, 147–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jena, G. B., & Chavan, S. (2017). Implementation of Good Laboratory Practices (GLP) in basic scientific research: Translating the concept beyond regulatory compliance. Regulatory Toxicology and Pharmacology, 89, 20–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kang, C., Isaac, M., & Popper, N. (2019). Facebook’s Zuckerberg, Accused of Lying, Withstands a Washington ‘Beating.’ The New York Times (online). Retrieved from https://www.nytimes.com/2019/10/23/technology/facebook-zuckerberg-libra-congress.html.

  • Koppl, R. (2006). Epistemic systems. Episteme, 2(02), 91–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (1983). Justified belief and epistemically responsible action. The Philosophical Review, 92(1), 33–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, R. (2012). Aristotle on becoming good: Habituation, reflection, and perception. In C. Shields (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of Aristotle (pp. 529–558). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. L. (2011). Norms of assertion. In J. Brown & H. Cappelen (Eds.), Assertion: New philosophical essays (pp. 233–251). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Laroche, H., Steyer, V., & Théron, C. (2019). How could you be so gullible? Scams and over-trust in organizations. Journal of Business Ethics, 160(3), 641–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, C. B. (2013). Moral character: An empirical theory. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mintz, S. M. (1996). Aristotelian virtue and business ethics education. Journal of Business Ethics, 15(8), 827–838.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mozur, P. (2020). TikTok to Withdraw From Hong Kong as Tech Giants Halt Data Requests. The New York Times (online). Retrieved 29 August, 2020, from https://www.nytimes.com/2020/07/06/technology/tiktok-google-facebook-twitter-hong-kong.html.

  • Mumford, S. (2016). Dispositions. In T. Crane (Ed.), Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pagin, P. (2016). Assertion. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pouivet, R. (2020). L’éthique intellectuelle: Une épistémologie des vertus. Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Powell, T. C., Lovallo, D., & Fox, C. R. (2011). Behavioral strategy. Strategic Management Journal, 32(13), 1369–1386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2021). Intellectual virtues and the epistemic value of truth. Synthese, 198(6), 5515–5528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radoilska, L. (2008). Truthfulness and business. Journal of Business Ethics, 79(1–2), 21–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawwas, M. Y., Arjoon, S., & Sidani, Y. (2013). An introduction of epistemology to business ethics: A study of marketing middle-managers. Journal of Business Ethics, 117(3), 525–539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ridge, M. (2013). Getting lost on the road to Larissa. Noûs, 47(1), 181–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Romm, T. (2020). Zuckerberg: Standing for voice and free expression. Washington Post (online). Retrieved from https://www.washingtonpost.com/technology/2019/10/17/zuckerberg-standing-voice-free-expression/.

  • Spicer, A. (2017). Business bullshit. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Standard & Poor’s. (2007). Ratings Structured Finance. Retrieved 28 June, 2018, from https://web.archive.org/web/20070818142212/http://www2.standardandpoors.com:80/portal/site/sp/en/us/page.family/ratings_sf/2,1,9,0,0,0,0,0,0,0,0,0,0,0,0,0.html.

  • Thomson, J. J. (2015). Normativity. Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turriago-Hoyos, A., Thoene, U., & Arjoon, S. (2016). Knowledge workers and virtues in Peter Drucker’s management theory. SAGE Open. https://doi.org/10.1177/2158244016639631

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • United States Congress. (2008). Credit Rating Agencies and the Financial Crisis., Pub. L. No. Y 4.G 74/7 § Committee on Oversight and Government Reform, House of Representatives. U.S. Government Printing Office, Washington. Retrieved 27 June, 2018, from https://www.gpo.gov/fdsys/pkg/CHRG-110hhrg51103/pdf/CHRG-110hhrg51103.pdf.

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (2018). Argumentation theory: A pragma-dialectical perspective. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walter, C. (2016). The financial Logos: The framing of financial decision-making by mathematical modelling. Research in International Business and Finance, 37, 597–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warenski, L. (2018). Banking and finance. Disentangling the epistemic failings of the 2008 financial crisis. In D. Coady & J. Chase (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of applied epistemology (pp. 196–210). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. (2006). Responsibility. In Internet Encylopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from http://www.iep.utm.edu/r/responsi.htm.

  • Williams, G. (2008). Responsibility as a virtue. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 11(4), 455–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. T. (1996). Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Boudewijn de Bruin (section editor) and the four anonymous reviewers for their very helpful comments, which greatly improved this paper. I would also like to thank Pascal Engel for his insightful remarks on an earlier version. This paper also benefited from the feedbacks received at the 2020 workshop on epistemic responsibility, organized by Christian Walter's and Emmanuel Picavet's Ethics and Finance Chair at the fondation Maison des sciences de l'homme (FMSH), in Paris. I am also thankful for the insightful discussions with Isabelle Beyneix, Jean-Philippe Bouilloud, Véronique Coq, Leonardo Augusto de Vasconcelos Gomes, Hervé Laroche, Sara Mandray, Emmanuel Picavet, Roger Pouivet, Louis Vuarin and Christian Walter. And last but not least, I am particularly grateful to Linda El-Dash for her help in clarifying the text, and making my English more understandable.

Funding

This study received no funding.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Erwan Lamy.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

There are no conflicts of interest to declare.

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lamy, E. Epistemic Responsibility in Business: An Integrative Framework for an Epistemic Ethics. J Bus Ethics 183, 1–14 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-022-05078-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-022-05078-1

Keywords

Navigation