Skip to main content
Log in

The ‘niche’ in niche-based theorizing: much ado about nothing

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The niche is allegedly the conceptual bedrock underpinning the most prominent, and some would say most important, theorizing in ecology. We argue this point of view is more aspirational than veridical. Rather than critically dissect existing definitions of the concept, the supposedly significant work it is thought to have done in ecology is our evaluative target. There is no denying the impressive mathematical sophistication and theoretical ingenuity of the ecological modeling that invokes ‘niche’ terminology. But despite the pervasive labeling, we demonstrate that niche talk is nothing more than a gloss on theory developed without it, that doesn’t need it, and that doesn’t benefit from it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Chase and Leibold (2003, 2), for instance, claim the niche “can help to solidify the conceptual synthesis that ecology so desperately needs.” And other champions of the concept claim its role in niche construction is on a par with natural selection (Scott-Phillips et al. 2014, 1232). Laland et al. (2009, 195) similarly assert that neglecting the niche would pose a “major conceptual barrier” to evolutionary and ecological theory, and Vandermeer (2004, 474) states that “niche-based” theorizing may constitute “a major breakthrough.”

  2. Although Schoener (1989) lauded Hutchinson’s niche definition as “revolutionary,” he also detailed many of its serious empirical shortcomings. Contra his positive evaluation, but prefiguring the critical line in the next section, he also observed that the “concept of the niche nearly always used in the body of concepts known as ‘niche theory’ … is not Hutchinson's” (Schoener 1989, 91).

  3. On the latter in philosophy of science, see Wilson (2006), Thagard (2012), and Sohlberg and Leiulfsrud (2016). Within the literature on concepts and conceptual engineering, see Burgess et al. (2020).

  4. According to Worster (1994, 374), MacArthur was “an ecologist who had the kind of ‘superbrain’ charisma commonly enjoyed by celebrities in physics.”

  5. The history of the niche in ecology is vast, intricate, and very difficult to address comprehensively. Our objective is supplying compelling evidence for a strong inductive argument against the scientific utility of the niche concept. Careful examination of the text and key equations from the first and most influential publications propelling the development of niche-theorizing therefore yields a weighty evidentiary basis for our induction. Other works adopt a wider scope of analysis, and although we don’t have the space to present it here, what those works uncover complements and enhances, rather than diminishes, the strong evidence driving our critical induction (see Schoener 1989, 2009; Pocheville 2015).

  6. See especially Kingsland’s (1995, 203–204) discussion of the work of Nelson Hairston among other critics.

  7. The fifth occurs in the last sentence: “The failure of Hypotheses II and III suggests that, at least as a rough approximation, niches do not overlap much and are more continuous than discrete.” As with its role labeling hypotheses, ‘niche’ was given no independent sense.

  8. See https://library.cshl.edu/symposia/1957/participants.html, accessed January 3, 2021.

  9. And in 1960 MacArthur thanked Hutchinson for providing “a continuous stream of good ideas on the subject for 7 years since he first drew the author's attention to it” (1960, 33).

  10. The scale of the independent variable R can represent any properties of resources that affect their utilization, such as location or size.

  11. This is a specific Gaussian function centered at R = 0 and peaking at U = 1.

  12. There are, moreover, many other measures of variation displaying similarly appealing statistical properties, such as the interquartile range and mean absolute deviation measures. But if resource use is more accurately represented with curves other than Gaussian functions, even these closely related measures can diverge. We thank an anonymous reviewer for highlighting this important fact.

  13. Even some niche loyalists seem to concede this priority. Schoener (2009, 5), for example, says, “Indeed, the resource-utilization niche is nothing more than a precisely formulated description of the natural history of a species: its habitat, food types, and activity times, among other things … Thus, we have a niche concept that precisely encapsulates what ecologists measure anyway” (italics added). The superfluous supervience couldn’t be clearer.

  14. For example, Tilman’s (1982) impressive manuscript, which integrated and expanded on several prior papers, contains exactly four instances of ‘niche’ and in each case the word is simply being used to refer to labels chosen by others. We thank an anonymous reviewer for stressing this point.

  15. Alternative explanations have been promulgated and Hubbell’s remark above about getting “closer to the truth” indicates there are philosophical undercurrents to the debate. Beyond his speculation that deterministic dispositions might underwrite ecologists’ “resistance” towards neutral theorizing, the last quote broaches another potential philosophical divide: realism versus instrumentalism. Wennekes et al. (2012, 259), for instance, argue that the “niche-based” vs. neutral theory feud ultimately boils down to fundamental disagreements between realists and instrumentalists, respectively, which they strangely claim correspond to “philosophical preference[s] for either general but vague versus specific and detailed models.” Scientific judgments are obviously shaped by folk metaphysical beliefs and tacit assumptions about the limits of epistemic inquiry, but Wennekes et al.’s specific assessment squares poorly with Hubbell’s own words. As the previous quotes manifest, he explicitly endorses the truth-seeking aim of realism. And it’s plausible Hubbell’s predilection for realism prompted his prediction that the two approaches would be “reconciled” and eventually integrated (2001, 26), a prediction born out by the vast majority of research done on the issue in the last 2 decades (Haegman and Loreau 2011; Fisher and Mehta 2014).

  16. “Niche construction should be regarded, after natural selection, as a second major participant in evolution” (Odling-Smee et al. 2003, 2), and others claim its role is “equal in explanatory importance to natural selection” (see Scott-Phillips et al. 2014, 1232, our italics).

  17. Ecological inheritance is defined as “any case in which organisms encounter a modified feature-factor relationship between themselves and their environment where the change in the selective pressures is a consequence of the prior niche construction by parents or other ancestral organisms” (2003, 42).

  18. In fact, NCT advocates are quite explicit about the narrow focus on causality. Despite the proclaimed centrality of the concepts of “environmental niche” and “ecological inheritance” for NCT, in an unobtrusive footnote of Niche Construction within the section “A Definition of Niche Construction” Odling-Smee et al. (2003, 41) disclose, “[o]ur use of the term construction refers to a physical modification of the selective environment or actual movement in physical space.” Intricate conceptual machinery is conspicuously absent.

  19. Moreover, if our critical line is correct, it’s implausible there is such a role even when evaluating higher-order ways concepts can influence scientific practice, but we’re not making that case here. See footnote 3 above.

  20. Prominent examples can probably be counted on two hands: e.g. absolute simultaneity, entelechy, ether, and phlogiston.

  21. Darwinian (and relative) fitnesses of genotypes can also be derived from Eq. (7).

  22. See Justus (2012) for another example of this kind of pluralistic fruitfulness in theoretical ecology, and Wakil (2020) for an example in evolutionary biology.

  23. It’s worth stressing that this critical judgment carries with it no reductionistic pretensions. As the fitness concept indicates, the utility of a concept in science doesn’t depend upon it being reducible to something more fundamental, such as causal relations. A concept may be fruitful because it can be so reduced, or its utility might be clearly ascertainable independent of any reductionistic commitments, such as for fitness or the concept of force in physics, at least since Newton (see Smith 2002).

  24. Chase and Leibold (2003, 19), for example, claim their niche concept successfully combines various definitions into “a single organized conceptual framework” that is “probably valid for almost any situation of ecological interest” (ibid, 2).

References

  • Ariew A, Lewontin RC (2004) The confusions of fitness. Br J Philos Sci 55:347–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bausman W (2019) The aims and structures of ecological research programs. Philos Top 47(1):1–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess A, Cappelen H, Plunkett D (2020) Conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. Oxford University Press

  • Cappelen H (2018) Fixing language: an essay on conceptual engineering. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chase J, Leibold M (2003) Ecological niches. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Colwell RK, Futuyma DJ (1971) On the measurement of niche breadth and overlap. Ecology 52:567–576

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edmondson YH (1971) Some components of the Hutchinson legend. Limnol Oceanogr 16:157–163

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elton C (1927) Animal ecology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher CK, Mehta P (2014) Niche-to-neutral transition in ecology. Proc Natl Acad Sci 111(36):13111–13116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillespie J (1998) Population GENETICS: a concise guide. John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik A (1998) Explanation as orgasm. Mind Mach 8:101–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gotelli NJ, Graves GR (1996) Null models in ecology. Smithsonian Institution Press, Washington, DC

    Google Scholar 

  • Grinnell J (1917) The niche-relationships of the california thrasher. Auk 34:427–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haegman B, Loreau M (2011) A mathematical synthesis of niche and neutral theories in community ecology. J Theor Biol 269:150–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubbell S (2001) The unified neutral theory of biodiversity and biogeography. Princeton University Press, Princeton Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurlbert SH (1981) A gentle depilation of the niche: Dicean resource sets in resource hyperspace. Evol Theory 5:177–184

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson GE (1944) Limnological studies in connecticut. Part 7. A critical examination of the supposed relationship between phytoplankton periodicity and chemical changes in lake waters. Ecology 25:3–26

  • Hutchinson GE (1957) Concluding remarks. Cold Spring Harb Symp Quant Biol 22:415–427

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James W (1879) Are we automata? Mind 4:1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Justus J (2012) Carnap on concept determination: methodology for philosophy of science. Eur J Philos Sci 2:161–179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Justus J (2019) Ecological theory and the superfluous niche. Philos Top 47(1):105–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalyuzhny M, Seri E, Chocron R, Flather C, Kadmon R, Shnerb N (2014) Niche versus neutrality: a dynamical analysis. Am Nat 184:439–446

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingsland SE (1995) Modeling nature: episodes in the history of population ecology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kon E, Lombrozo T (2019) Scientific discovery and the human drive to explain. In: Wilkenfeld DA, Samuels R (eds) Advances in experimental philosophy of science. Bloomsbury Academic, London, pp 15–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Kylafis G, Loreau M (2011) Niche construction in the light of niche theory. Ecol Lett 14:82–90

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN, Odling-Smee FJ, Feldman MW, Kendal JR (2009) Conceptual barriers to progress within evolutionary biology. Found Sci 4:195–216

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland K, Matthews B, Feldman MW (2016) An introduction to niche construction theory. Evol Ecol 30:191–202

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1968) Evolution in changing environments. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1983) Gene, organism, and environment. In: Bendall DS (ed) Evolution from molecules to men. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 273–285

    Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur R (1957) On the relative abundance of bird species. Proc Natl Acad Sci 43:293–295

  • MacArthur R (1960) On the relative abundance of species. Am Nat 94:25–36

  • MacArthur R, Levins R (1964) Competition, habitat selection, and character displacement in a patchy environment. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 51(6):1207–1210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur R, Pianka E (1966) On optimal use of a patchy environment. Am Nat 100:603–609

  • Macarthur R, Levins R (1967) The limiting similarity, convergence, and divergence of coexisting species. Am Nat 101(921):377–385

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur R (1968) The theory of the niche. In: Population biology and evolution. Syracuse University Press, Syracuse, NY

  • Machery E (2009) Doing without concepts. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McInerny G, Etienne R (2012) Ditch the niche—is the niche a useful concept in ecology or species distribution modelling? J Biogeogr 39:2096–2102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh R (1985) The background of ecology: concept and theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy G (2004) The big book of concepts. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh J (Forthcoming) Neutrality, niche, and nulls: causal relevance in ecology. In: Waters C, Woodward J (eds) Philosophical perspectives on causal reasoning in biology. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, MN

  • Odling-Smee FJ (1988) Niche-constructing phenotypes. In: Plotkin HC (ed) The role of behavior in evolution. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 73–132

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee FJ, Laland KN, Feldman MW (2003) Niche construction: the neglected process in evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee J, Erwin DH, Palkovacs EP, Feldman MW, Laland KN (2013) Niche construction theory: a practical guide for ecologists. Q Rev Biol 88(1):4–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patten B, Auble G (1981) System theory of the ecological niche. Am Nat 117(6):893–922

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pedruski MT, Fussmann GF, Gonzalez A (2016) A network approach reveals surprises about the history of the niche. Ecosphere 7:e01266. https://doi.org/10.1002/ecs2.1266

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pence C, Ramsey G (2013) A new foundation for the propensity definition of fitness. Br J Philos Sci 64:851–881

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peters RH (1991) A critique for ecology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Pianka ER, Vitt LJ, Pelegrin N, Fitzgerald DB, Winemiller KO (2017) Toward a periodic table of niches, or exploring the lizard niche hypervolume. Am Nat 190(5):601–616

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plunkett D, Cappelen H (2020) A guided tour of conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. In: Cappelen H, Plunkett D, Burgess A (eds) Conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 1–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Pocheville A (2015) The ecological niche: history and recent controversies. In: Heams T, Huneman P, Lecointre G, Silberstein M (eds) Handbook of evolutionary thinking in the sciences. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9014-7_26

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Prinzing M (2018) The revisionist’s rubric: conceptual engineering and the discontinuity objection. Inquiry: Interdiscip J Philos 61(8):854–880

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Real L, Levin S (1991) The role of theory in the rise of modern ecology. In: Real L, Brown J (eds) Foundations of ecology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 177–191

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schoener T (1989) The ecological niche. In: Cherrett J (ed) Ecological concepts: the contribution of ecology to an understanding of the natural world. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 79–113

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoener T (2009) Ecological niche. In: Levin SA, Carpenter SR, Godfray HCJ, Kinzig AP, Loreau M, Losos JB, Walker B, Wilcove DS (eds) The Princeton guide to ecology. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, pp 3–13

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scott-Phillips TC, Laland KN, Shuker DM, Dickins TE, West SA (2014) The niche construction perspective: a critical appraisal. Evolution 68(5):1231–1243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scudo M, Ziegler J (1978) The golden age of theoretical ecology: 1923–1940. New York, Springer

  • Slack N (2010) G. Evelyn Hutchinson and the invention of modern ecology. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith GE (2002) The methodology of the principia. In: Cohen IB, Smith GE (eds) The Cambridge companion to Newton. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 138–173

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (2001) The two faces of fitness. In: Singh RS, Krimbas CB, Paul DB, Beatty J (eds) Thinking about evolution: historical, philosophical, and political perspectives. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sohlberg P, Leiulfsrud H (eds) (2016) Theory in action. Brill Press, Leiden

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugihara G (1980) Minimal community structure: an explanation of species abundance patterns. Am Nat 116(6):770–787

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard P (2012) The cognitive science of science. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tilman D (1982) Resource competition and community structure. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Trout JD (2017) Motivation and the sense of understanding in theory construction. Motiv Sci 3(3):304–317

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vandermeer J (2004) The importance of a constructivist view. Science 303:472–474

  • Vergnon R, Dulvy NK, Freckleton RP (2009) Niches versus neutrality: uncovering the drivers of diversity in a species-rich community. Ecol Lett 12(10):1079–1090

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakil S (2020) Objectivity and orgasm: the perils of imprecise definitions. Synthese 199(1):2315–2333

    Google Scholar 

  • Wennekes PL, Rosindell J, Etienne RS (2012) The neutral-niche debate: a philosophical perspective. Acta Biotheor 60(3):257–271

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittaker RH, Levin SA (1975) Niche: theory and application. Dowden, Hutchinson & Ross, Stroudsburg, PA

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson M (2006) Wandering significance: an essay on conceptual behavior. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Worster D (1994) Nature’s economy: a history of ecological ideas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to audiences at the University of Minnesota, Pittsburgh Center for Philosophy of Science, conferences Concept Formation in the Natural and Social Sciences (Zurich) and Philosophical Perspectives on the Niche Concept (Münster), and Philosophy of Science Association Meeting (2018) for helpful feedback. In particular, comments from Ulrich Gädhe, Karen Kovaka, Alan Love, Sandy Mitchell, Rose Trappes, and Armin Schulz were especially valuable.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Samantha Wakil.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wakil, S., Justus, J. The ‘niche’ in niche-based theorizing: much ado about nothing. Biol Philos 37, 10 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-022-09839-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-022-09839-0

Keywords

Navigation