Skip to main content
Log in

Are Conductive Arguments Possible?

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Conductive Arguments are held to be defeasible, non-conclusive, and neither inductive nor deductive (Blair and Johnson in Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning. College, London, 2011). Of the different kinds of Conductive Arguments, I am concerned only with those for which it is claimed that countervailing considerations detract from the support for the conclusion, complimentary to the positive reasons increasing that support. Here’s an example from Wellman (Challenge and response: justification in ethics. Southern Illinois University Press, Chicago, 1971):

Although your lawn needs cutting, you ought to take your son to the movies because the picture is ideal for children and will be gone by tomorrow. (1971: 57)

I argue that Conductive Arguments are not possible—the “ought” conclusion only holds if countervailing considerations are nullified.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Johnson (2011) draws an analogy: “The dynamic in a pro/con argument seems very much like what occurs in what I have called an argument with a dialectical tier (2000a). This is an argument in which the arguer, after laying out the grounds for the conclusion (what I called the illative core), then attempts to anticipate and diffuse objections that might be raised against the argument (the dialectical tier)” (53). But no requirement for “attempts to anticipate” the counter-considerations is essential to conductive arguments. Johnson’s requirement imposes a strong burden on arguers. The topic is conductive arguments, not arguing conductively, which introduces demands of give and take (dialectic) and focuses on opinionated or controversial issues. But conductive arguments are far more general. See, for example the conductive argument in the text for the conclusion that Yale is a better buy. The goal is to learn or discover.

  2. The New York Times 2.18.2012 reported that the World Health Organization has decided to lift the ban.

  3. ‘Conclusive’ and ‘inconclusive’ are pervasive in the text, but they are not even listed in the index.

  4. A problem with the test is that even though Jim may assert the conclusion without qualification, it may be mutual that such predictions about delicate social relations are to be implicitly qualified. I assume that there is enough data and argument in the text to make my point even if this particular example is somewhat tricky.

  5. These possibilities would not be in the nearest possible worlds (Lewis 1973).

  6. This raises a difficulty: Other organisms will be able to more easily detect the strategy than if the organisms occasionally went to Area B. But this is a problem of evolutionary strategy, not germane to our topic.

References

  • Bach, K. 1999. The myth of conventional implicature. Linguistics and Philosophy 22: 327–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Battersby, M., and S. Bailin. 2011. Guidelines for reaching a reasoned judgment. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 145–157. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, J.A. 2011. Conductive reasoning/arguments: A map of the issues. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 1–9. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, J.A., and R.H. Johnson (eds.). 2011. Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, studies in logic and argumentation, vol. 33. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 1982. How is weakness of will possible? In Essays on actions and events, ed. D. Davidson, 21–42. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. 2000. Conclusive reasons. In Perception, knowledge and belief, ed. F. Dretske, 3–29. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro, M. 2011. Conductive arguments: A meta-argumentation approach. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 224–261. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, T. 2011. Weighing considerations in conductive pro and con arguments. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 86–103. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. 2010. A practical study of argument, 7th ed. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, J.B. 2011. Evaluating conductive arguments in light of the Toulmin model. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 127–144. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. 1986. Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. 2011. Conductive arguments: Overview of the symposium. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 262–276. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, H.V. 2011. Notes on balance-of-considerations arguments. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 31–51. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 1986. Change of view. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. 1965. Inductive inconsistencies. In Aspects of scientific explanation, ed. C. Hempel, 53–80. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, D. 1983. Critical thinking: A Guide to evaluating information. Toronto: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, D. 2007. Informal logic and the concept of argument. In Philosophy of logic, ed. D. Jacquette, 101–131. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jin, R. 2011. The structure of pro and con arguments: A survey of the theories. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 10–30. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R.H. 2011. The relationship between pro/con and dialectical tier arguments. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 52–61. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.K. 1973. Counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G.E. 1942. A reply to my critics. In The philosophy of G. E. Moore, ed. P.A. Schilpp. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, R.C. 2011. Weighing evidence in the context of conductive reasoning. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 104–126. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. 1975. Ignorance: A case for scepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, C. 1971. Challenge and response: Justification in ethics. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B.A.O. 1973. Ethical consistency. In Problems of the self, ed. B.A.O. Williams, 166–186. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wohlrapp, H. 2011. A misleading model for the analysis of pro- and contra- argumentation. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 210–223. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zenker, F. 2011. An attempt at unifying natural language argument structures. In Conductive argument: An overlooked type of defeasible reasoning, ed. J.A. Blair, and R.H. Johnson, 74–85. London: College.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper was submitted for publication to the journal Argumentation, but the author passed away during the review process. The editors of the journal Argumentation thought it worthwile to make an effort to get the paper published all the same. Professor J. Anthony Blair, one of the reviewers, kindly offered to prepare the final version of the paper, taking as much as he could account of the reviews. The editors appreciate Professor Blair’s assistance in getting the paper published very much and want to express their thanks.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan Adler.

Additional information

Jonathan Adler: Deceased.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Adler, J. Are Conductive Arguments Possible?. Argumentation 27, 245–257 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-012-9286-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-012-9286-3

Keywords

Navigation