Skip to main content
Log in

One-way monotonicity as a form of strategy-proofness

  • Published:
International Journal of Game Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Suppose that a vote consists of a linear ranking of alternatives, and that in a certain profile some single pivotal voter v is able to change the outcome of an election from s alone to t alone, by changing her vote from P v to \({P^\prime_{v}}\) . A voting rule \({\mathcal{F}}\) is two-way monotonic if such an effect is only possible when v moves t from below s (according to P v to above s (according to \({P^\prime_{v}}\) . One-way monotonicity is the strictly weaker requirement forbidding this effect when v makes the opposite switch, by moving s from below t to above t. Two-way monotonicity is very strong—equivalent over any domain to strategy proofness. One-way monotonicity holds for all sensible voting rules, a broad class including the scoring rules, but no Condorcet extension for four or more alternatives is one-way monotonic. These monotonicities have interpretations in terms of strategy-proofness. For a one-way monotonic rule \({\mathcal{F}}\) , each manipulation is paired with a positive response, in which \({\mathcal{F}}\) offers the pivotal voter a strictly better result when she votes sincerely.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Aleskerov F, Kurbanov E (1999) A degree of manipulability of known social choice procedures. In: Aliprantis S, Alkan A, Yannelis N (eds) Studies in Economic Theory, vol 8, Current Trends in Economics: Theory and Applications. Springer Verlag, Berlin, pp 13–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Black D (1958) The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ, Fishburn PC (1983) Paradoxes of preferential voting. Math Mag 56: 207–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ, Fishburn PC (2002) Voting procedures, Chap 4. In: Arrow JA, Sen AJ, Suzumura K (eds) Handbook of social choice and welfare, vol 1. Handbooks in economics 19. Elsevier, Amsterdam

  • Campbell DE, Kelly JS (2002) Non-monotonicity does not imply the no-show paradox. Soc Choice Welf 19: 513–515

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danilov V (1992) Implementation via Nash equilibria. Econometrica 60: 43–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doğan O, Giritligil AE (2007) Existence of anonymous, neutral, Pareto-optimal, single-valued and monotonic social choice functions—a characterization (preprint)

  • Erdem O, Sanver MR (2005) Minimal monotonic extensions of scoring rules. Soc Choice Welf 25: 31–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Favardin P, Lepelley D, Serais J (2002) Borda rule, Copeland method, and strategic manipulation. Rev Econ Design 7: 213–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Favardin P, Lepelley D (2006) Some further results on the manipulability of social choice rules. Soc Choice Welf 26: 485–509

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1977) Condorcet social choice functions. SIAM J Appl Math 33: 469–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1982) Monotonicity paradoxes in the theory of elections. Discrete Appl Math 4: 119–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors P (1979) On definitions of manipulation of social choice functions, Chap 2. In: Lafont J (ed) Aggregation and revelation of preferences. North Holland, Amsterdam

  • Gibbard A (1973) Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result. Econometrica 41: 587–601

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maskin E (1977) Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality. mimeo

  • Maskin E (1999) Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality. Rev Econ Stud 66: 23–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merlin VR, Saari DG (1997) Copeland method II: manipulation, monotonicity, and paradoxes. J Econ Theory 72: 148–172

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin H (1988a) Axioms of cooperative decision making. Econometric Soc Monograph #15. Cambridge University Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulin H (1988b) Condorcet’s principle implies the no-show paradox. J Econ Theory 45: 53–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller E, Satterthwaite M (1977) The equivalence of strong positive association and incentive compatibility. J Econ Theory 14: 412–418

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saari D (1990) Consistency of decision processes. Ann Oper Res 23: 103–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saari D (1994) Geometry of voting. Aliprantis C, Yannellis NC (eds) Studies in economics 3. Springer, Berlin

  • Saari D (1999) Explaining all three-alternative voting outcomes. J Econ Theory 87: 313–355

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saari D, Barney S (2003) Consequences of reversing preferences. Math Intell 25: 17–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanver MR, Zwicker WS (2009) Monotonicity properties for irresolute voting rules (working paper)

  • Satterthwaite M (1975) Strategy-proofness and Arrow’s conditions: existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. J Econ Theory 10: 187–217

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith D (1999) Manipulability measures of common social choice functions. Soc Choice Welf 16: 639–661

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith JH (1973) Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate. Econometrica 41: 1027–1041

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor AD (2005) Social choice and the mathematics of manipulation. Cambridge University Press and Mathematical Association of America, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwicker WS (1991) The voters’ paradox, spin, and the Borda count. Math Soc Sci 22: 187–227

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to M. Remzi Sanver.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sanver, M.R., Zwicker, W.S. One-way monotonicity as a form of strategy-proofness. Int J Game Theory 38, 553–574 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-009-0170-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-009-0170-9

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation