Skip to main content
Log in

A time to kill: Ronald Dworkin and the ethics of euthanasia

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

References

  1. SeeRodriguez v.British Columbia (Attorney General) (1993) 107 D.L.R. (4th) 342;Airedale NHS Trust v.Bland [1993] 2 W.L.R. 316; andCruzan v.Director Missouri Department of Health (1990) 110 Supreme Court Reports 2841.

  2. Increasingly, especially in the lower courts, our judges lack any significant education in moral philosophy. The leading Canadian political philosopher, the late George Grant, cautioned that “When society puts power into the hands of the courts, they had better be educated ... The more the justices quote philosophy or religious tradition the less they give the sense they understand what they are dealing with.” (“The Triumph of the Will”, inA Time to Choose Life: Women, Abortion and Human Rights, ed. Ian Gentles (Stoddart: Toronto, 1990), 9-18, endnote 3 at p.213, as cited in Iain Benson, “Medical and Legal Ethics: Objective Truth and Subjective Schooling”,Focus 15/1 (1994), 12–23).

  3. Rodriguez, supra n.1, SeeRodriguez v.British Columbia (Attorney General) (1993) 107 D.L.R. (4th) 342;Airedale NHS Trust v.Bland [1993] 2 W.L.R. 316; andCruzan v.Director Missouri Department of Health (1990) 110 Supreme Court Reports 2841. at 389.

  4. R. Dworkin,Life's Dominion (London: Harper Collins, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Edward Keyserlingk,Sanctity of Life or Quality of Life (Study Paper, Law Reform Commission of Canada, Ottawa, DSS, 1979).

  6. R.P. George,Making Men Moral: Civil Liberties and Public Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 19.

    Google Scholar 

  7. On the role of tradition in general, see A. MacIntyre,Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  8. I do not provide any defence of natural law theory here, and I will attempt only a brief summary of some key concepts. By “natural law theory” I mean the particular restatement developed largely by John Finnis and Germain Grisez. References to works by Finnis, Grisez, Robert George and others should point the reader towards a satisfactory exposition and defence of this tradition.

  9. Linacre Centre for Health Care Ethics, “Submission to the Select Committee of the House of Lords on Medical Ethics”, inEuthanasia, Clinical Practice and the Law, ed. Luke Gormally (London: The Linacre Centre, 1994), 111–65, at 119.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Supra n.9..

    Google Scholar 

  11. In John Finnis' account these include life, knowledge, play, aesthetic experience, sociability (friendship), practical reasonableness, and “religion”; J.M. Finnis,Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), ch. IV.

    Google Scholar 

  12. J.M. Finnis, “Natural Law and Legal Reasoning,” inNatural Law Theory, ed. R. George (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 134–57, at 136.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Finnis argues for nine basic principles of practical reasonableness. They are: (1) have a harmonious set of orientations, purposes, and commitments; (2) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, any of the basic human goods; (3) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, the goodness of other people's participation in human goods (i.e. have no arbitrary preferences among persons); (4) do not give any particular project the significance which belongs only to a basic good; (5) do not abandon your commitments lightly; (6) do not waste opportunities through unnecessary inefficiency; (7) do not choose directly against a basic human good; (8) promote the common good of your communities; and (9) follow your conscience. See J.M. Finnis,Fundamentals of Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983), 75;supra n. 11, In John Finnis's account these include life, knowledge, play, asthetic experience, sociability (friendship), practical reasonableness, and “religion”; J.M. Finnis,Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), at ch. V.

    Google Scholar 

  14. “Natural Law and Legal Reasoning”,supra n. 12,, at 147.

    Google Scholar 

  15. This is to be distinguished from F.A. Hayek's epistemological point that it is not within our cognitive capacity to know and choose good, and therefore we can only refrain from doing wrong (see Z. Bankowski, “Ambiguities of the Rule of Law”, inIssues of Law and Morality, ed. H. Jung (Berlin: Forum Verlag, 1991), 101–12, at 105). The point from practical reasonableness is that even if we do know how to do good, some possible instantiations of good will be mutually exclusive, and we must choose among them. Therefore some possible good will not be pursued. Given finite human ability, we cannot have moral absolutes requiring that all good be done. See J.M. Finnis, “Intention and side-effects”, inLiability and Responsibility, ed. R.G. Frey and C.W. Morris (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 32–64, at 63.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Finnis,supra n. 12..

    Google Scholar 

  17. Supra n.6., at 8–9; also J.M. Finnis,Moral Absolutes (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 1991), 43–44.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Finnis,supra n. 15,, at 62.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Supra n. 18,, at 62–4. Alsosupra n.6, R.P. George,Making Men Moral: Civil Liberties and Public Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 19. at 17.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Finnis,supra n.15,, at 61.

    Google Scholar 

  21. The Linacre Centre, Report of a Working Party, “Euthanasia and Clinical Practice,” in Gormallysupra n.9.

    Google Scholar 

  22. “Act so that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of another, always as an end and never as a means only”, cited in Finnis,supra n.13, Finnis argues for nine basic principles of practical reasonableness. They are: (1) have a harmonious set of orientations, purposes, and commitments; (2) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, any of the basic human goods; (3) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, the goodness of other people's participation in human goods (i.e. have no arbitrary preferences among persons); (4) do not give any particular project the significance which belongs only to a basic good; (5) do not abandon your commitments lightly; (6) do not waste opportunities through unnecessary inefficiency; (7) do not choose directly against a basic human good; (8) promote the common good of your communities; and (9) follow your conscience. See, at 121.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Finnis,supra n.15.. Also,supra n.9, Linacre Centre for Health Care Ethics, “Submission to the Select Committe of the House of Lords on Medical Ethics”, inEuthanasia, Clinical Practice and the Law, ed. Luke Gormally (London: The Linacre Centre, 1994), 111–65, at 48–50.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Supra n.9,, at 39.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Supra n.9, at 39–41. Also Finnis,Fundamentals of Ethics, supra n. 13, Finnis argues for nine basic principles of practical reasonableness. They are: (1) have a harmonious set of orientations, purposes, and commitments; (2) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, any of the basic human goods; (3) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, the goodness of other people's participation in human goods (i.e. have no arbitrary preferences among persons); (4) do not give any particular project the significance which belongs only to a basic good; (5) do not abandon your commitments lightly; (6) do not waste opportunities through unnecessary inefficiency; (7) do not choose directly against a basic human good; (8) promote the common good of your communities; and (9) follow your conscience. See J.M. Finnis,Fundamentals of Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983), 75;supra n. 11, In John Finnis' account these include life, knowledge, play, aesthetic experience, sociability (friendship), practical reasonableness and “religion”; J.M. Finnis,Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), ch. IV. at ch. V. at 124–33.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Bland, supra n.1, SeeRodriguez v.British Columbia (Attorney General) (1993) 107 D.L.R. (4th) 342;Airedale NHS Trust v.Bland [1993] 2 W.L.R. 316; andCruzan v.Director Missouri Department of Health (1990) 110 Supreme Court Reports 2841, at 367.

  27. Rodriguez, supra n.1, SeeRodriguez v.British Columbia (Attorney General) (1993) 107 D.L.R. (4th) 342;Airedale NHS Trust v.Bland [1993] 2 W.L.R. 316; andCruzan v.Director Missouri Department of Health (1990) 110 Supreme Court Reports 2841, and the Law Reform Commission of Canada,Euthanasia, Aiding Suicide and Cessation of Treatment, Working Paper 28 (Ottawa: DSS, 1982), at 33.

  28. J.M. Finnis, “Bland: Crossing the Rubicon?”,Law Quarterly Review 109 (1993), 329–37, at 333.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See N. Pace, “A Practitioner's Overview”, an unpublished manuscript presented at the University of Glasgow, Conference on “Death, Dying and the Law”, 3 September 1994, at p.3.

  30. Supra n.9,, at 63–64.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Supra n.4,, at 101.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Supra n.4,, at 68–69.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Supra n.4,, at ch. III.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Supra n.4,, at 69.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Supra n.4,, at 92.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Supra n.4,, at 84.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Supra n.4,, at 84–89.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Supra n.9,, at 84–89.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Supra n.4,, at 89–94.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Supra n.4,, at 93.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Supra n.4,, at 215–216.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Supra n.4,, at 28.

    Google Scholar 

  43. See Z. Bankowski, “Don't think about it?: Legalism and Legality”,Rechtstheorie Beiheft 15 (1993), 45–54.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Supra n.43.. Also, St. Thomas Aquinas,Summa Theologiae I–II q.96, a.2; George,supra n.6.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Although Dworkin's liberalism also allows for limited paternalism: see R. Dworkin, “The Right to Death”,New York Review of Books, 31 st January 1991, 14–17 at 17 n.6; and R. Dworkin, “Foundations of Liberal Equality”, in1989 Tanner Lectures on Human Values (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1989), vol. II, cited in George,supra n.6, at 102.

  46. Supra n. 6,, at 28–35.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Supra n. 6,, at 43.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Supra n.43, at 8.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Supra n.13Finnis argues for nine basic principles of practical reasonableness. They are: (1) have a harmonious set of orientations, purposes, and commitments; (2) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, any of the basic human goods; (3) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, the goodness of other people's participation in human goods (i.e. have no arbitrary preferences among persons); (4) do not give any particular project the significance which belongs only to a basic good; (5) do not abandon your commitments lightly; (6) do not waste opportunities through unnecessary inefficiency; (7) do not choose directly against a basic human good; (8) promote the common good of your communities; and (9) follow your conscience. See, at 124.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Supra n.12, at 145–48.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Supra n.12, at 148–50.

    Google Scholar 

  52. J.M. Finnis, “The ‘Value of Human Life’ and ‘The Right to Death’: Some Reflections on Cruzan and Ronald Dworking”,Southern Illinois University Law Journal 17 (1993), 559–571, at 567–70. This is not to suggest that emotions form no part of rational deliberation; seesupra n.12, J.M. Finnis, “Natural Law and Legal Reasoning”, inNatural Law Theory, ed. R. George (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 134–57, 39–41 andsupra n.6,R. P. George,Making Men Moral: Civil Liberties and Public Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 19. at 9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Supra n.4, at 213.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Supra n.9,, at 121–23.

    Google Scholar 

  55. C.S. Lewis,Abolition of Man (New York: Macmillan, 1947), 60.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Supra n.55,. at 59.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Supra n.9,, at 122, note 8(2).

    Google Scholar 

  58. Supra n.4,, at 80.

    Google Scholar 

  59. While Dworkin's contention that life can have no value is placed in the context of an autonomous request for death, the concept of the valueless life has necessary implications for involuntary euthanasia, as well as the creation of a moral climate which encourages people to make life terminating decisions (either in advance directives or contemporaneously) based on a vision which encourages them to feel worthless in themselves and a burden on society.

  60. Supra n.4,, at 230.

    Google Scholar 

  61. L. Gormally, “The Aged: non-persons, human dignity and justice”, inThe Dependent Elderly, ed. L. Gormally (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 181–88, at 184.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Supra n.9,, at 123.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Supra n.9,.

    Google Scholar 

  64. J.M. Finnis, “Economics, justice and the value of life: concluding remarks”, inGormally,supra n.61,, 189–98, at 193–96.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Supra n.61, 189–98, at 193–6.

    Google Scholar 

  66. G.V. Bradley, “Life's Dominion: A Review Essay”,Notre Dame Law Review 69 (1993), 329–91, at 374.

    Google Scholar 

  67. G. Grisez, “Should Nutrition and Hydration Be Provided to Permanently Unconscious and Other Mentally Disabled Persons?”,Issues in Law and Medicine 5/2 (1989), 165–79, at 173.

    Google Scholar 

  68. “The Right to Death”,supra n.45,Although Dworkin's liberalism also allows for limited paternalism: see R. Dworkin, “The Right to Death”,New York Review of Books, 31st January 1991, 14–17 at 17 n.6; and R. Dworkin, “Foundations of Liberal Equality”, in1989 Tanner Lectures on Human Values (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1989), vol. II, cited in George,supra n.6, at 102. at 17.

  69. Supra n.67,, at 174.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Supra n.67,, at 174.

    Google Scholar 

  71. J.M. Finnis,supra n.64,“, at 192–94.

    Google Scholar 

  72. J.M. Finnis,supra n.64,“, at 192–94.

    Google Scholar 

  73. On the distinction between emotional reactions and the rational requirements of justice: “Neither solidarity nor justice can be maintained by reliance on sentiments of affection uninformed by recognition of duties of care to those who in the course of nature (because of immaturity and decline) are necessarily dependent and without a sense of responsibility for their own lives. The lives of many of us have depended at some stage on others recognising duties of care towards us, a recognition overriding any strong inclination to abandon care for us” (supra n.9.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Supra n.4,, at ch. VII and VIII.

    Google Scholar 

  75. J. Boyle, “The American debate about artificial nutrition and hydration”, in Gormally,supra n.61,, at 28–46.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Supra n.11,In John Finnis' account these include life, knowledge, play, aesthetic experience, sociability (friendship), practical reasonableness, and “religion”;, at 106–107.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Supra n.67,, at 169.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Supra n.9,, at 122.

    Google Scholar 

  79. And this is not simply to make the epistemological complaint that it is impossible to foresee the benefits and burdens that would occur as a result of each option. On incommensurability, see J. Raz,The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), ch. XIII; also J.M. Finnis, J. Boyle, and G. Grisez,Nuclear Deterrence, Morality and Realism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987), ch. IX.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Finnis, Grisez and Boyle,supra n.79,, at 252.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Supra n.4,, at 205.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Supra n.4,, at 29.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Raz,supra n.79

    Google Scholar 

  84. Supra n.4, at 224.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Supra n.4, at 224.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Supra n.6, at 129.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Supra n.4, at 202—206.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Supra n.4, at 202–206.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Supra n.4, at 228–29.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Fundamentals of Ethics, supra n.13 Finnis argues for nine basic principles of practical reasonableness. The are: (1) have a harmonious set of orientations, purposes, and commitments; (2) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, any of the basic human goods; (3) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, the goodness of other people's participation in human goods (i.e. have no arbitrary preferences among persons); (4) do not give any particular project the significance which belongs only to a basic good; (5) do not abandon your commitments lightly; (6) do not waster opportunities throughunnecessary inefficiency; (7) do not choose directly against a basic human good; (8) promote the common good of your communities; and (9) follow your conscience. See, at 70–74.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Supra n. 12, at 100.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Supra n.6, at 178.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Supra n.9, at 131.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Supra n.13 Finnis argues for nine basic principles of pracrical reasonableness. They are: (1) have a harmonious set of orientations purposes, and commitments; (2) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, any of the basic human goods: (3) do not leave out of account, or arbitrarily discount or exaggerate, the goodness of other people's participation in human goods (i.e. have no arbitrary preferences among persons); (4) do not give any particular project the significance which belongs only to a basic good; (5) do not abandon your commitments lightly; (6) do not waste opportunities through unnecessary inefficiency; (7) do not choose directly against a basic human good; (8) promote the common good of your communities; and (9) follow your conscience. See, at 124.

    Google Scholar 

  95. J. Boyle, “The Americabn debate about artificial nutrition and hydration”, in Gormally,Supra n.61, 28–46, at 42.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Supra n.9, at 131-132.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Supra n.6, at 32.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Raz,supra n.79, at ch. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Supra n.6, at 163–4.

    Google Scholar 

  100. J. Keown, “Some reflections on euthanasia in The Netherlands”, in Gormally,supra n.61,, 70–100, at 79.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Finnis,supra n.12, See Kennedy's comments on Myra Hindley's treatment by the courts, the media and the public,post, text accompanying n.17.

  102. Supra n.6, at 99.

    Google Scholar 

  103. For a fuller discussion of policy considerations, see Y. Kamisar, “Some Non-Religious Views Against Proposed ‘Mercy-Killing’ Legislation”,Minnesota Law Review 42 (1958), 970–1039.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Supra n.100,, 70–101, at 82.

    Google Scholar 

  105. B. Logue, “Physician-Assisted Suicide: A Social Science Perspective on International Trends (Summary)”, unpublished manuscript presented at University of Glasgow Symposium on “Death, Dying and the Law”, 3 September 1994, at 3–4.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Miller, B.W. A time to kill: Ronald Dworkin and the ethics of euthanasia. Res Publica 2, 31–61 (1996). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02335709

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02335709

Navigation