Skip to main content
Log in

Positional Voting Systems Generated by Cumulative Standings Functions

  • Published:
Group Decision and Negotiation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Positional voting systems are a class of voting systems where voters rank order the candidates from best to worst and a set of winners is selected using the positions of the candidates in the voters’ preference orders. Although scoring rules are the best known positional voting systems, this class includes other voting systems proposed in the literature as, for example, the Majoritarian Compromise or the \(q\)-Approval Fallback Bargaining. In this paper we show that some of these positional voting systems can be integrated in a model based on cumulative standings functions. The proposed model allows us to establish a general framework for the analysis of these voting systems, to extend to them some results in the literature for the particular case of the scoring rules, and also facilitates the study of the social choice properties considered in the paper: monotonicity, Pareto-optimality, immunity to the absolute winner paradox, Condorcet consistency, immunity to the absolute loser paradox and immunity to the Condorcet loser paradox.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As far as we know this term first appears in Gärdenfors (1973).

  2. It is worth noting that there exist other PVSs based on mathematical programming techniques that have an important drawback from the point of view of social choice theory: The relative order between two candidates may be altered when the number of first, second, ..., \(m\)th ranks obtained by other candidates changes, although there are not any variations in the number of first, second, ..., \(m\)th ranks obtained by both candidates (see Llamazares and Peña 2009). The PVSs with this drawback are not considered in this paper.

  3. Although the cumulative standings of each candidate depend on the profile \(\varvec{p}\), in order to avoid cumbersome notation we shall omit \(\varvec{p}\) in the notation of these values when there is no possible confusion. When it will be necessary, we will use the notation \(V_{k}^{i}\) for the profile \(\varvec{p}\), \(V_{k}^{\prime i}\) for the profile \(\varvec{p}'\) and so on.

  4. Nevertheless, for convenience we continue to use the notation \(V_{m}^{i}\) instead of \(n\) when appropriate.

  5. Taking into account that the score of each candidate only depends on the number of first, second, ..., \(m\)th ranks obtained by him/her, the use of CSFs excludes the PVSs that have the drawback mentioned in the introduction.

  6. It is easy to check that the functions considered in this section are monotonic and, therefore, are CSFs.

  7. Notice that, although the majoritarian Compromise historically precedes \(q\)-approval fallback bargaining, we first show this PVS for the sake of simplicity of the CSF.

  8. The best known special cases of \(k\)-approval voting are plurality (\(k=1\)) and antiplurality (\(k=m-1\)).

  9. This corollary extends to all PVSs generated by CSFs the result obtained for the scoring rules by Saari (1992, 1994) (see also Merlin et al. 2000).

  10. It is worth noting that the same set of winning candidates can be also obtained through a model proposed by Llamazares and Peña (2013).

  11. Excepting the scoring rules because the results relative to these voting systems are already known (see Llamazares and Peña 2014).

  12. It is worth noting that Condorcet-consistency is a controversial property: Although some authors such as Felsenthal (2012) hold that a Condorcet winner, if one exists, ought always to be elected, others, such as Fishburn (1974), question the importance of this property.

  13. In this case the cumulative standing function will be denoted by \(F_n\) instead of \(F_q\).

  14. Notice that, when \(m=3\), the third column of Table 2 is \(V_{2}^{i}\) and not \(V_{m-1}^{i}\).

  15. It is worth noting that, when \(m=3\), the third column of Table 3 is \(V_{2}^{i}\) and not \(V_{m-1}^{i}\).

  16. It is worth noting that Brams and Kilgour (2001) and Sertel and Yilmaz (1999) use examples with four and five candidates, respectively, to show that their methods are not Condorcet consistent. Our examples show this result independently of the number of the candidates. In this respect, for \(m\ge 3\), the no-Condorcet consistency of the Condorcet’s practical method and the Majoritarian Compromise has been noted by Merlin et al. (2006) using the geometry of voting.

  17. According to Fishburn (1974), the forward cyclic list of orders generated by \(A_{1}\,A_{2}\cdots A_{m}\) is the \(m\)-tuple of orders \((A_{1}\,A_{2}\cdots A_{m-1}\,A_{m},\; A_{2}\,A_{3}\cdots A_{m}\,A_{1},\; A_{3}\,A_{4}\cdots A_{1}\,A_{2},\; \dots ,\; A_{m}\,A_{1}\cdots A_{m-2}\,A_{m-1})\).

References

  • Bassett GW, Persky J (1999) Robust voting. Public Choice 99(3–4):299–310

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ, Kilgour DM (2001) Fallback bargaining. Group Decis Negot 10(4):287–316

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Congar R, Merlin V (2012) A characterization of the maximin rule in the context of voting. Theory Decis 72(1):131–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Contreras I, Hinojosa MA, Mármol AM (2005) A class of flexible weight indices for ranking alternatives. IMA J Manag Math 16(1):71–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cook WD, Kress M (1990) A data envelopment model for aggregating preference rankings. Manag Sci 36(11):1302–1310

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felsenthal DS (2012) Review of paradoxes afflicting procedures for electing a single candidate, studies in choice and welfare. In: Felsenthal DS, Machover M (eds) Electoral systems: paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures, chap 3. Springer, Berlin, pp 19–91

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1974) Paradoxes of voting. Am Polit Sci Rev 68(2):537–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1982) Monotonicity paradoxes in the theory of elections. Discret Appl Math 4(2):119–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foroughi AA, Jones DF, Tamiz M (2005) A selection method for a preferential election. Appl Math Comput 163(1):107–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors P (1973) Positionalist voting functions. Theory Decis 4(1):1–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein WV, Lepelley D (2003) On some limitations of the median voting rule. Public Choice 117(1–2):177–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green RH, Doyle JR, Cook WD (1996) Preference voting and project ranking using DEA and cross-evaluation. Eur J Oper Res 90(3):461–472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurwicz L, Sertel MR (1999) Designing mechanisms, in particular for electoral systems: the majoritarian compromise. In: Sertel MR (ed) Econ Des Behav. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Llamazares B, Peña T (2009) Preference aggregation and DEA: an analysis of the methods proposed to discriminate efficient candidates. Eur J Oper Res 197(2):714–721

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Llamazares B, Peña T (2013) Aggregating preferences rankings with variable weights. Eur J Oper Res 230(2):348–355

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Llamazares B, Peña T (2014) Scoring rules and social choice properties: some characterizations. Theory Decis (in press)

  • Merlin V, Tataru M, Valognes F (2000) On the probability that all decision rules select the same winner. J Math Econ 33(2):183–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merlin V, Özkal-Sanver I, Sanver MR (2006) Properties of majoritarian compromise, efficient compromise, and related compromise rules. Paper presented in the 8th international meeting of the society for social choice and welfare, Istanbul

  • Moulin H (1988) Axioms of cooperative decision making, econometric society monographs, vol 15. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi H (1999) Voting paradoxes and how to deal with them. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Obata T, Ishii H (2003) A method for discriminating efficient candidates with ranked voting data. Eur J Oper Res 151(1):233–237

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saari DG (1992) Millions of election outcomes from a single profile. Soc Choice Welf 9(4):277–306

    Google Scholar 

  • Saari DG (1994) Geometry of voting, studies in economic theory, vol 3. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sertel MR, Yilmaz B (1999) The majoritarian compromise is majoritarian-optimal and subgame-perfect implementable. Soc Choice Welf 16(4):615–627

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheikhmohammady M, Kilgour DM, Hipel KW (2010) Modeling the Caspian Sea negotiations. Group Decis Negot 19(2):149–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein WE, Mizzi PJ, Pfaffenberger RC (1994) A stochastic dominance analysis of ranked voting systems with scoring. Eur J Oper Res 74(1):78–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors are very grateful to two anonymous referees for valuable suggestions, comments and references. This work is partially supported by the Spanish Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness (Projects ECO2011-24200 and ECO2012-32178) and the Junta de Castilla y León (Consejería de Educación, Project VA066U13).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bonifacio Llamazares.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Theorem 2

Let \(F\) be a CSF, let \(\varvec{p}\) be a profile and let \(A_{i}\) be a winning candidate for this profile. Suppose that some voters raise \(A_{i}\) in their rankings without changing the orders of the remaining candidates. Let \(\varvec{p}^{\prime }\) be this new profile. It is straightforward to check that \(\varvec{V}^{\prime i}\ge \varvec{V}^i\) and \(\varvec{V}^{\prime j}\le \varvec{V}^j\) for all \(j\ne i\). Since \(A_{i}\) is a winning candidate and \(F\) is monotonic we have

$$\begin{aligned} F(\varvec{V}^{\prime i})\ge F(\varvec{V}^i)\ge F(\varvec{V}^j)\ge F(\varvec{V}^{\prime j}) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(j\ne i\). Therefore, \(A_{i}\) continues to be a winning candidate for the new profile \(\varvec{p}^{\prime }\). \(\square \)

Before proving Theorem 3, we give the following lemma.

Lemma 1

If the candidate \(A_i\) is not Pareto-optimal, then \(V_{1}^{i}=0\) and there exists another candidate \(A_j\) with \(V_{k}^{i} \le V_{k-1}^{j}\) for all \(k \in \{2,\dots ,m\}\).

Proof

If \(A_i\) is not Pareto-optimal, there exists another candidate \(A_j\) that is preferred to \(A_i\) by all voters, so \(V_{1}^{i}=0\). On the other hand, when a voter places candidate \(A_i\) in the \(k\)th position, that voter will have ranked \(A_j\) higher. Therefore, \(V_{k}^{i} \le V_{k-1}^{j}\) for all \(k \in \{2,\dots ,m\}\). \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 3

In all cases we are going to prove that, given a profile \(\varvec{p}\), if a candidate \(A_i\) is not Pareto-optimal, then \(A_i\) cannot be a winning candidate.

  1. 1.

    Lexicographic Rule If \(A_i\) is not Pareto-optimal, then, by Lemma 1, \(V_{1}^{i}=0\) and, consequently, \(A_i\) is not a winning candidate.

  2. 2.

    Condorcet’s Practical Method Consider \(m=3\). If \(A_i\) is not Pareto-optimal, then he/she is dominated by a candidate \(A_{j}\). We distinguish two cases:

    1. (a)

      If \(V_{1}^{j} > \lfloor n/2\rfloor \), then \(A_{j}\) is the only winner.

    2. (b)

      If \(V_{1}^{j} \le \lfloor n/2\rfloor \), then, by Lemma 1, \(V_{1}^{i} = 0\), \(V_{2}^{j} \ge V_{3}^{i} = n\) and \(V_{2}^{i} \le V_{1}^{j}< n\). So, \(F_{C}(\varvec{V}^{j}) = 1\) and \(F_{C}(\varvec{V}^{i}) < 1\). Therefore, \(A_i\) cannot be a winning candidate.

  3. 3.

    Obata and Ishii’s Method If \(A_i\) is not Pareto-optimal, then, by Lemma 1, \(V_{1}^{i}=0\) and there exists another candidate \(A_j\) with \(V_{k}^{i} \le V_{k-1}^{j}\) for all \(k \in \{2,\dots ,m\}\). Let \(l\in \{2,\dots ,m\}\) such that

    $$\begin{aligned} F_{OI}(\varvec{V}^{i}) = \max \left\{ V_{1}^{i}, \frac{V_{2}^{i}}{2}, \dots , \frac{V_{m-1}^{i}}{m-1}, \frac{V_{m}^{i}}{m}\right\} = \frac{V_{l}^{i}}{l}. \end{aligned}$$

    Since \(V_{l}^{i} > 0\) and \(V_{l}^{i} \le V_{l-1}^{j}\), we have

    $$\begin{aligned} F_{OI}(\varvec{V}^{i}) = \frac{V_{l}^{i}}{l} < \frac{V_{l-1}^{j}}{l-1} \le F_{OI}(\varvec{V}^{j}). \end{aligned}$$

    Therefore, \(A_i\) is not a winning candidate.

  4. 4.

    Contreras, Hinojosa and Mármol’s Method If \(A_i\) is not Pareto-optimal, then, by Lemma 1, \(V_{1}^{i}=0\) and there exists another candidate \(A_j\) with \(V_{k}^{i} \le V_{k-1}^{j}\) for all \(k \in \{2,\dots ,m\}\). Let \(l\in \{2,\dots ,m\}\) such that

    $$\begin{aligned} F_{CHM}(\varvec{V}^{i}) = \max \left\{ V_{1}^{i}, \frac{V_{1}^{i} + V_{2}^{i}}{3}, \dots , \frac{2}{m(m+1)}\sum _{k=1}^{m} V_{k}^{i}\right\} = \frac{2}{l(l+1)}\sum _{k=1}^{l} V_{k}^{i}. \end{aligned}$$

    Since \(\sum _{k=1}^{l} V_{k}^{i} > 0\,\) and \(\sum _{k=1}^{l} V_{k}^{i} \le \sum _{k=1}^{l-1} V_{k}^{j}\), we have

    $$\begin{aligned} F_{CHM}(\varvec{V}^{i}) = \frac{2}{l(l+1)}\sum _{k=1}^{l} V_{k}^{i} < \frac{2}{(l-1)l}\sum _{k=1}^{l-1} V_{k}^{j} \le F_{CHM}(\varvec{V}^{j}). \end{aligned}$$

    Therefore, \(A_i\) is not a winning candidate.

  5. 5.

    Geometric rule If \(A_i\) is not Pareto-optimal, then, by Lemma 1, \(V_{1}^{i}=0\) and, consequently, \(F_{G}(\varvec{V}^{i})=0\). So, \(A_{i}\) is not a winning candidate. \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 4

  1. 1.

    Obata and Ishii’s Method Let \(A_i\) be the absolute winner of a profile \(\varvec{p}\). In this case, \(V_{1}^{i}\ge \lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1\); so, \(F_{OI}(\varvec{V}^i)\ge \lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1\). Now, consider \(j\ne i\). Then \(V_{k}^{j}/k \le n/2\) for all \(k \in \{1,\dots ,m\}\). Therefore, \(F_{OI}(\varvec{V}^j)\le n/2 < \lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1 \le F_{OI}(\varvec{V}^i)\), for all \(j\ne i\). Consequently, \(A_i\) is the only winner.

  2. 2.

    Contreras, Hinojosa and Mármol’s Method Let \(A_i\) be the absolute winner of a profile \(\varvec{p}\). In this case, \(V_{1}^{i}\ge \lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1\); so, \(F_{CHM}(\varvec{V}^i)\ge \lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1\). Now, consider \(j\ne i\). Note that

    $$\begin{aligned} F_{CHM}(\varvec{V}^j) = \max _{l=1,\dots ,m}\left\{ \frac{2}{l(l+1)}\sum _{k=1}^{l} V_{k}^{j} \right\} \end{aligned}$$

    and that \(V_{1}^{j} \le n-\big (\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1 \big )\). Then, for all \(l \in \{1,\dots ,m\}\), we have

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{2}{l(l+1)}\sum _{k=1}^{l} V_{k}^{j}&\le \frac{2}{l(l+1)}\Big (n - \big (\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1 \big ) + (l-1)n\Big ) \\&= \frac{2}{l(l+1)}\Big (ln - \big (\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1 \big )\Big ) = 2\left( \frac{n}{l+1}-\frac{\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1}{l(l+1)}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

    We are going to prove that the maximum value of the last expression is achieved when \(l=2\). We distinguish two cases:

    1. (a)

      If \(l=1\), then

      $$\begin{aligned} \frac{n}{2}-\frac{\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1}{2}&\le \frac{n}{3}-\frac{\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1}{6} \\&\Leftrightarrow \frac{n}{6} \le \frac{\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1}{3}\\&\Leftrightarrow n \le 2\big (\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1\big ), \end{aligned}$$

      which is true.

    2. (b)

      If \(l \in \{3,\dots ,m\}\), then

      $$\begin{aligned} \frac{n}{l+1}-\frac{\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1}{l(l+1)}&\le \frac{n}{3}-\frac{\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1}{6} \\&\Leftrightarrow \; \big (\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1\big ) \frac{l(l+1)-6}{6l(l+1)} \le n \frac{l-2}{3(l+1)}\\&\Leftrightarrow \; \big (\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1\big ) \frac{(l+3)(l-2)}{l} \le 2n(l-2)\\&\Leftrightarrow \; \big (\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1\big )(l+3) \le 2ln, \end{aligned}$$

      which is true.

    Therefore,

    $$\begin{aligned} F_{CHM}(\varvec{V}^j)&\le 2\left( \frac{n}{3}-\frac{\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1}{6}\right) \\&< 2\left( \frac{2\big (\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1\big )}{3}-\frac{\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1}{6}\right) = \lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1 \le F_{CHM}(\varvec{V}^i), \end{aligned}$$

    for all \(j\ne i\). Consequently, \(A_i\) is the only winner. \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 5

First, we are going to prove that the Lexicographic rule, the Condorcet’s practical method (with \(m > 4\)), Fallback Bargaining, the Obata and Ishii’s method, the Contreras, Hinojosa and Mármol’s method and the Geometric rule are vulnerable to the absolute loser paradox. Consider twice the forward cyclic list of orders generated by \(A_{2}\,A_{3}\cdots A_{m}\). In the first forward cyclic list we place candidate \(A_{1}\) in the first position and in the second forward cyclic list we place \(A_{1}\) in the last position. Now we consider a profile \(\varvec{p}\) of \(8m-9\) voters where each order is considered \(4\) times but the first one, which is considered \(3\) times:

  • \(3\) voters: \(A_{1}\,A_{2}\,A_{3}\cdots A_{m-1}\,A_{m}\)

  • \(4\) voters: \(A_{1}\,A_{3}\,A_{4}\cdots A_{m}\,A_{2}\)

  • \(4\) voters: \(A_{1}\,A_{4}\,A_{5}\cdots A_{2}\,A_{3}\)

  • \(\ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \)

  • \(4\) voters: \(A_{1}\,A_{m}\,A_{2}\cdots A_{m-2}\,A_{m-1}\)

  • \(4\) voters: \(A_{2}\,A_{3}\cdots A_{m-1}\,A_{m}\,A_{1}\)

  • \(4\) voters: \(A_{3}\,A_{4}\cdots A_{m}\,A_{2}\,A_{1}\)

  • \(4\) voters: \(A_{4}\,A_{5}\cdots A_{2}\,A_{3}\,A_{1}\)

  • \(\ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \ldots \)

  • \(4\) voters: \(A_{m}\,A_{2}\cdots A_{m-2}\,A_{m-1}\,A_{1}.\)

Notice that \(A_{1}\) is the absolute loser in the profile \(\varvec{p}\). In Table 8 we show the cumulative standings of the candidates according to this profile. It is worth noting that \(V_{k}^{m} = 4(2k-1)\) for all \(k\in \{1,\dots ,m-1\}\).

Table 8 Cumulative standings of profile \(\varvec{p}\) (Absolute loser paradox)

We are going to show that \(A_{1}\) is a winning candidate for the PVSs listed in the statement of Theorem 5 and, consequently, these PVSs are vulnerable to the absolute loser paradox. Given that \(\varvec{V}^{m}\ge \varvec{V}^{i}\) for all \(i\in \{2,\dots ,m-1\}\), for any CSF \(F\) we have \(F(\varvec{V}^{m}) \ge F(\varvec{V}^{i})\) (and, therefore, \(A_{m}\succcurlyeq A_{i}\)) for all \(i\in \{2,\dots ,m-1\}\). Let us see that \(A_{1}\succcurlyeq A_{m}\) for the PVSs considered:

  1. 1.

    Lexicographic Rule Since \(4m-5 > 4\) for all \(m\ge 3\), we have that \(A_{1}\succ A_{m}\).

  2. 2.

    Condorcet’s Practical Method Since neither \(A_{1}\) nor \(A_{m}\) have a majority of first ranks and \(4m-5 > 12\) for all \(m\ge 5\), we have that \(A_{1}\succ A_{m}\).

  3. 3.

    Fallback Bargaining Since \(V_{m-1}^{i} < 8m-9 = n\) when \(i\in \{1,m\}\), we have that \(F_{n}(\varvec{V}^{1}) = F_{n}(\varvec{V}^{m}) = 0\) and, consequently, \(A_{1}\succcurlyeq A_{m}\).

  4. 4.

    Obata and Ishii’s Method Since \(V_{k}^{m} = 4(2k-1)\) for all \(k\in \{1,\dots ,m-1\}\), the scores of candidates \(A_{1}\) and \(A_{m}\) are

    $$\begin{aligned} F_{OI}(\varvec{V}^{1})&= \max \left\{ 4m-5,\frac{4m-5}{2}, \dots ,\frac{4m-5}{m-1},\frac{8m-9}{m}\right\} ,\\ F_{OI}(\varvec{V}^{m})&= \max \left\{ 4, 6,\dots , \frac{4(2m-3)}{m-1},\frac{8m-9}{m}\right\} . \end{aligned}$$

    It is straightforward to check the following inequalities:

    $$\begin{aligned} 4m-5&> \frac{8m-9}{m} \quad (\text {for all } m\ge 3),\\ \frac{4(2m-3)}{m-1}&> \frac{8m-9}{m} \quad (\text {for all } m\ge 3), \end{aligned}$$

    and

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{V_{k+1}^{m}}{k+1} = \frac{4(2(k+1)-1)}{k+1}&> \frac{4(2k-1)}{k} = \frac{V_{k}^{m}}{k} \quad (\text {for all } k\in \{1,\dots ,m-2\}). \end{aligned}$$

    Therefore, we get

    $$\begin{aligned} F_{OI}(\varvec{V}^{1}) = 4m-5,\qquad F_{OI}(\varvec{V}^{m}) = \frac{4(2m-3)}{m-1}. \end{aligned}$$

    Given that

    $$\begin{aligned} 4m-5 > \frac{4(2m-3)}{m-1} \quad (\text {for all } m\ge 3), \end{aligned}$$

    we have \(A_{1}\succ A_{m}\).

  5. 5.

    Contreras, Hinojosa and Mármol’s Method The score obtained by candidates \(A_{1}\) is

    $$\begin{aligned} F_{CHM}(\varvec{V}^{1}) =&\max \Bigg \{ 4m-5, \frac{2}{3}(4m-5), \dots ,\frac{2}{m}(4m-5),\\&\qquad \quad \frac{2}{m(m+1)}\big ((m-1)(4m-5)+(8m-9)\big )\Bigg \}. \end{aligned}$$

    It is straightforward to check that the inequality

    $$\begin{aligned} 4m-5 > \frac{2}{m(m+1)}\big ((m-1)(4m-5)+(8m-9)\big ) \end{aligned}$$

    is satisfied for all \(m\ge 3\). Therefore, \(F_{CHM}(\varvec{V}^{1}) = 4m-5\). To calculate the score of candidate \(A_{m}\) we take into account that

    $$\begin{aligned} \sum _{l=1}^{k} V_{l}^m = 4 \sum _{l=1}^{k} (2l-1) = 4 k^2, \end{aligned}$$

    for all \(k\in \{1,\dots ,m-1\}\). Therefore

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{2}{k(k+1)}\sum _{l=1}^{k} V_{l}^m&= \frac{8k}{k+1} \quad (\text {for all } k\in \{1,\dots ,m-1\}),\\ \frac{2}{m(m+1)}\sum _{l=1}^{m} V_{l}^m&= \frac{2}{m(m+1)} \left( 4(m-1)^2 + (8m-9)\right) . \end{aligned}$$

    It is easy to check the following inequalities:

    $$\begin{aligned}&\frac{8k}{k+1} < \frac{8(k+1)}{k+2} \quad (\text {for all } k\in \{1,\dots ,m-2\}),\\&\frac{2}{m(m+1)} \left( 4(m-1)^2 + (8m-9)\right) < \frac{8(m-1)}{m}. \end{aligned}$$

    Therefore

    $$\begin{aligned} F_{CHM}(\varvec{V}^{m})=\frac{8(m-1)}{m}. \end{aligned}$$

    Given that

    $$\begin{aligned} 4m-5 > \frac{8(m-1)}{m}\quad (\text {for all } m\ge 3), \end{aligned}$$

    we have \(A_{1}\succ A_{m}\).

  6. 6.

    Geometric Rule The scores of candidates \(A_{1}\) and \(A_{m}\) are

    $$\begin{aligned} F_{G}(\varvec{V}^{1})&= (4m-5)^{m-1},\\ F_{G}(\varvec{V}^{m})&= 4^{m-1}\prod _{k=1}^{m-1} (2k-1) = \frac{4^{m-1}(2m-2)!}{2^{m-1}(m-1)!} = 2^{m-1}\frac{(2m-2)!}{(m-1)!}. \end{aligned}$$

    We are going to prove that, for all \(m\ge 3\),

    $$\begin{aligned} 2^{m-1}\frac{(2m-2)!}{(m-1)!} < (4m-5)^{m-1}. \end{aligned}$$

    The proof is by induction on \(m\). If \(m=3\), then \(48 < 49\). Suppose now the result is true for \(m=k\), and let us see that the claim holds for \(m=k+1\). By hypothesis of induction we have

    $$\begin{aligned} 2^{k}\frac{(2k)!}{k!} = 2\frac{(2k-1)2k}{k}\cdot 2^{k-1}\frac{(2k-2)!}{(k-1)!} < 4(2k-1)(4k-5)^{k-1}. \end{aligned}$$

    Since

    $$\begin{aligned} (4k-1)^k&= (4k-1)\Big ((4k-5)+4\Big )^{k-1}\\&> (4k-2)\left( (4k-5)^{k-1}+(k-1)4(4k-5)^{k-2}\right) \\&> (4k-2)\left( (4k-5)^{k-1}+(4k-5)^{k-1}\right) \\&= 4(2k-1)(4k-5)^{k-1}, \end{aligned}$$

    we get

    $$\begin{aligned} 2^{k}\frac{(2k)!}{k!} < (4k-1)^k. \end{aligned}$$

    Therefore \(A_{1}\succ A_{m}\).

Next we are going to prove that the Condorcet’s practical method is immune to the absolute loser paradox when \(m \le 4\). Let \(A_i\) be the absolute loser of a profile \(\varvec{p}\). Then \(V_{1}^{i} < \lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1\). We are going to prove that there exists \(j\ne i\) such that \(V_{2}^{j}\ge V_{2}^{i}\) and, consequently, \(A_{i}\) cannot be a winning candidate.

Given that \(V_{2}^{i}\le n - (\lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1) = \lfloor (n-1)/2 \rfloor \) and \(\displaystyle \sum _{j=1}^{m} V_{2}^{j} = 2n\), then we have \(\displaystyle \sum _{j\ne i} V_{2}^{j} \ge 2n - \lfloor (n-1)/2 \rfloor \). Therefore, there exists \(j\ne i\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} V_{2}^{j} \ge \frac{2n - \lfloor (n-1)/2 \rfloor }{m-1}. \end{aligned}$$

Since

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{2n - \lfloor (n-1)/2 \rfloor }{m-1} > \lfloor (n-1)/2 \rfloor&\Leftrightarrow 2n > m \lfloor (n-1)/2 \rfloor \Leftrightarrow \frac{2}{m} n > \lfloor (n-1)/2 \rfloor , \end{aligned}$$

which is true when \(m\le 4\), we get

$$\begin{aligned} V_{2}^{j} \ge \frac{2n - \lfloor (n-1)/2 \rfloor }{m-1} > \lfloor (n-1)/2 \rfloor \ge V_{2}^{i}. \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Llamazares, B., Peña, T. Positional Voting Systems Generated by Cumulative Standings Functions. Group Decis Negot 24, 777–801 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10726-014-9412-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10726-014-9412-8

Keywords

Navigation