Skip to main content
Log in

An empirical, purely spatial criterion for the planes ofF-simultaneity

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The claim that distant simultaneity with respect to an inertial observer is conventional arose in the context of a space-and-time rather than a spacetime ontology. Reformulating this problem in terms of a spacetime ontology merely trivializes it. In the context of flat space, flat time, and a linear inertial structure (a purely space-and-time formalism), we prove that the hyperplanes of space for a given inertial observer are determined by a purely spatial criterion that depends for its validity only on the two-way light principle, which is universally regarded as empirically verified. All (empirically determined) “spacetime” entities, such as the conformal structure or light surface equation, are used in a purely mathematical manner that is independent of and hence isneutral with respect to the ontological status that is ascribed to them. In this regard, our criterion is significantly stronger than thespacetime criterion recently advanced by D. Malament, which appeals explicitly to the conformal orthogonality of spacetime vectors and to the invariance of the conformal-orthogonal structure of spacetime under the causal automorphisms of spacetime. Once the hyperplanes of space for a given inertial observer have been determined by our empirical and purely spatial criterion, the following holds: there exists one and only one\(\vec \varepsilon \)-synchronization procedure, namely the standard procedure proposed by Einstein, such that the planes of common time are thesame as the nonconventional hyperplanes of space for the inertial observer. It follows that our criterion provides an empirical even if indirect method for determining that the one-way speed of light is the same as the average two-way speed of light. In addition, two inertial observers that are not at rest with respect to each other necessarily havedifferent hyperplanes of space, and consequently their respective spatial views cannot be encompassed in a single three-dimensional space. Hence, our purely spatial criterion provides an empirical motivation for adopting the more comprehensive spacetime ontology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. M. Castagnino, “Some remarks on the Marzke-Wheeler method of measurement,”Nuovo Cimento B 54, 149–150 (1968).

    Google Scholar 

  2. M. Castagnino, “The Riemannian structure of space-time as a consequence of a measurement method,”J. Math. Phys. 12, 2203–2211 (1971).

    Google Scholar 

  3. R. K. Clifton, “Some recent controversy over the possibility of experimentally determining isotropy in the speed of light,”Philos. Sci. 56, 688–696 (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  4. E. Crapo, “The tetrahedral-octahedral truss,”Struct. Topol. 7, 51–60 (1982).

    Google Scholar 

  5. R. A. Coleman and H. Korte, “Jet bundles and path structures,”J. Math. Phys. 21, 1340–1351 (1980); erratum,23, 345 (1982).

    Google Scholar 

  6. R. A. Coleman and H. Korte, “Spacetime G-structures and their prolongations,”J. Math. Phys. 22, 2598–2611 (1981).

    Google Scholar 

  7. R. A. Coleman and H. Korte, “The status and meaning of the laws of inertia,” inProceedings of the 1982 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. I, P. D. Asquith and T. Nickles, eds. (Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, Michigan, 1982), pp. 257–274.

    Google Scholar 

  8. R. A. Coleman and H. Korte, “A realist field ontology of the causal-inertial structure (the refutation of geometric conventionalism),” University of Regina preprint (1981), extended version (1984), 192 pp. Final version forthcoming as a volume inSynthese Library.

  9. R. A. Coleman and H. Korte, “Constraints on the nature of inertial motion arising from the universality of free fall and the conformal causal structure of spacetime,”J. Math. Phys. 25, 3513–3526 (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  10. R. A. Coleman and H. Korte, “Any physical, monopole equation-of-motion structure uniquely determines a projective inertial structure and an (n−1) force,”J. Math. Phys. 28, 1492–1498 (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  11. R. A. Coleman and H. Korte, “Harmonic analysis of directing fields,”J. Math. Phys. 31, 127–130 (1990).

    Google Scholar 

  12. R. De Ritis and S. Guccione, “Can Einstein's definition of simultaneity be considered a convention?”Gen. Relativ. Gravit. 17, 595–598 (1985).

    Google Scholar 

  13. J. Ehlers, R. A. E. Pirani, and A. Schild, “The geometry of free fall and light propagation,” inGeneral Relativity, Papers in Honour of J. L. Synge, L. O' Raifeartaigh, ed. (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1972), pp. 63–84.

    Google Scholar 

  14. A. Einstein, “On the electrodynamics of moving bodies,” inThe Principle of Relativity, (Dover, New York, 1952), pp. 36–65; translated by W. Perret and G. B. Jeffery from “Zur Elektrodynamik bewegter Körper,”Ann. Phys. (Leipzig) 17, 891–921 (1905).

    Google Scholar 

  15. A. Einstein, “Reply to criticisms,” inAlbert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, P. A. Schilpp, ed. (Open Court, La Salle, Illinois, 1969), pp. 665–688.

    Google Scholar 

  16. E. Feenberg, “Conventionality in distant simultaneity,”Found. Phys. 4, 177–203 (1971).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Shing-Fai Fung and K. C. Hsieh, “Is the isotropy of the speed of light a convention?”Am. J. Phys. 48, 654–657 (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  18. C. Giannoni, “Relativistic mechanics and electrodynamics without one-way velocity assumptions,”Philos. Sci. 45, 17–46 (1978).

    Google Scholar 

  19. A. Grünbaum, Philosophical Problems of Space and Time, 2nd ed. (Reidel, Dordrecht, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  20. P. Havas, “Simultaneity, conventionalism, general covariance, and the special theory of relativity,”Gen. Relativ. Gravit. 19, 435–453 (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  21. M. Jammer, “Some Fundamental Problems in the Special Theory of Relativity,” inProblems in the Foundations of Physics, Proceedings of the International School of Physics, Enrico Fermi, Course LXXII, G. Toraldo di Francia, ed. (North Holland, New York, 1979), pp. 202–236.

    Google Scholar 

  22. L. Karlov, “Clocks in Nonstandard Synchrony,”Gen. Relativ. Gravit. 19, 455–464 (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  23. P. Kolen and D. G. Torr, “An experiment to measure the one-way velocity of propagation of electromagnetic radiation,”Found. Phys. 12, 401–411 (1982).

    Google Scholar 

  24. W. Kundt and B. Hoffmann, “Determination of gravitational standard time,” inRecent Developments in General Relativity (Pergamon, New York, 1962), pp. 303–336.

    Google Scholar 

  25. D. Malament, “Causal theories of time and the conventionality of simultaneity,”Nous 11, 293–300 (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  26. R. Mansouri and R. U. Sexl, “A test theory of special relativity: I. simultaneity and clock synchronisation,”Gen. Relativ. Gravit. 8, 497–513 (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  27. R. Mansouri and R. U. Sexl, “A test theory of special relativity: II. first-order tests,”Gen. Relativ. Gravit. 8, 515–524 (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  28. R. Mansouri and R. U. Sexl, “A test theory of special relativity: III. second-order tests,”Gen. Relativ. Gravit. 8, 809–814 (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  29. R. F. Marzke and J. A. Wheeler, “Gravitation as geometry, I: the geometry of space-time and the geometrical standard meter,” inGravitation and Relativity, Hong-Yee Chiu and W. F. Hoffmann, eds. (Benjamin, Amsterdam, 1964), pp. 40–64.

    Google Scholar 

  30. P. Mittelstaedt,Der Zeitbegriff in der Physik (B. I.-Wissenschaftsverlag, Zürich, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  31. C. Nissim-Sabat, “A gedankenexperiment to measure the one-way velocity of light,”Br. J. Philos. Sci. 35, 62–64 (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  32. P. Ohrstrom, “Conventionality in distant simultaneity,”Found. Phys. 10, 333–343 (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  33. H. Reichenbach,The Philosophy of Space and Time (Dover, New York, 1958).

    Google Scholar 

  34. H. Reichenbach,Axiomatization of the Theory of Relativity (University of California Press, Los Angeles, 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  35. H. Reichenbach, “The philosophical significance of the theory of relativity,” inAlbert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, P. A. Schilpp, ed. (Open Court, La Salle, Illinois, 1969), pp. 289–311.

    Google Scholar 

  36. W. C. Salmon, “The conventionality of simultaneity,”Philos. Sci. 36, 44–63 (1969).

    Google Scholar 

  37. W. C. Salmon, “The philosophical significance of the one-way velocity of light,”Noûs 11, 253–292 (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  38. G. Stolakis, “Against conventionalism in physics,”Br. J. Philos. Sci. 37, 229–232 (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  39. H. Weyl, “Zur Infinitesimalgeometrie: Einordnung der projektiven und konformen Auffassung,”Nachr. Königl. Ges. Wiss. Göttingen, Math.-phys. Kl., 99–112 (1921) (reprinted in Ref. 40, Vol. II, 195–207).

  40. H. Weyl,Gesammelte Abhandlungen, 4 Vols., K. Chandrasekharan, ed. (Springer, Berlin, 1968).

    Google Scholar 

  41. H. Weyl, “Mathematische Analyse des Raumproblems,” inDas Kontinuum, H. Weyl, ed. (Chelsea, New York, no date).

  42. W. Whiteley, “Motions of trusses and bipartite frameworks,”Struct. Topol. 7, 61–68 (1982).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Coleman, R.A., Korte, H. An empirical, purely spatial criterion for the planes ofF-simultaneity. Found Phys 21, 417–437 (1991). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00733356

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00733356

Keywords

Navigation