Skip to main content

Empathy at War: The Distinction Between Reasonableness and the Reasonable Military Commander Standard

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Honest Errors? Combat Decision-Making 75 Years After the Hostage Case
  • 71 Accesses

Abstract

There is a distinction between asking whether a military commander’s act was reasonable and asking whether a military commander acted in the manner in which a reasonable military commander would have acted. The difference is that only the second question compels a person assessing a given state of affairs to engage in empathetic perspective-taking. Accordingly, this chapter argues that the reasonable military commander test is a legal device which invites those who apply it to engage in empathetic perspective-taking. Construing the reasonable military commander test as a perspective-taking device brings into focus the crucial question of whose views and whose interests influence the legal evaluation of a commander’s behaviour. Understanding the reasonable military commander test in this way also directs attention to the role of empathy in the battlefield. It is important to be clear about this rationale of the reasonable military commander test in the battlefield in order to ensure that the conduct of military commanders is assessed accurately.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a comprehensive account of Hammerfest’s destruction, see the report “The Devastation of Hammerfest after the Compulsory Evacuation of the Population at the Beginning of the Month of November 1944” dated 20 April 1945 by the city’s engineer, Johannes Kummeneje. Excerpts of the report were cited by the prosecution during the Hostage case, see US Nuremberg Tribunal, “Transcript for NMT7: Hostage Case” 2761–2769 (27 August 1947), http://nuremberg.law.harvard.edu/transcripts/4-transcript-for-nmt-7-hostage-case [accessed 1 April 2023].

  2. 2.

    United States Military Tribunal at Nuremberg, United States v. Wilhelm List et al. (“Hostage Case”), Judgment, 19 February 1948, (1950) Trials of War Criminals Before the Nuernberg Military Tribunals under Control Council Law No. 10, p 1296.

  3. 3.

    Jodl A (1944) Teletype, dated 28 October 1944, from Chief of the Operations Staff of the German Armed Forces High Command to Armed Forces Commander in Chief, Norway Concerning the Evacuation of Northern Norway. Reproduced as document 754-PS by United States Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (1950) Hostage Case, p 836.

  4. 4.

    Rendulic L (1944) Teletype from 20th (Mountain) Army to Subordinate Units Concerning the Evacuation of Northern Norway. Reproduced as document NOKW-086 by United States Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (1950) Hostage Case, pp 1114–1117.

  5. 5.

    Rendulic L (1944) Teletype from 20th (Mountain) Army to Subordinate Units Concerning the Evacuation of Northern Norway. Reproduced as document NOKW-086 by United States Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (1950) Hostage Case, p 1117.

  6. 6.

    Rendulic’s testimony reproduced by US Nuremberg Tribunal, p 5542 (31 October 1947).

  7. 7.

    According to the tribunal’s own law report, the case was so called since “the greater part of the trial was concerned with alleged hostage or reprisal actions of one kind or another”, United States Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (1950) Hostage Case, p 759. The official designation of the case is, however, United States of America vs. Wilhelm List et al. (Case No. 7).

  8. 8.

    Ibid., p 1295.

  9. 9.

    Hague Convention (IV) respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land and its Annex: Regulations concerning the Laws and Customs of War on Land, opened for signature 18 October 1907, (1907) 3 Martens (3d) 504, entered into force 26 January 1910.

  10. 10.

    Ibid., Article 23(g).

  11. 11.

    United States Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (1950) Hostage Case, p 1295. See also Rendulic’s testimony reproduced by US Nuremberg Tribunal, p 5536 (30 October 1947).

  12. 12.

    United States Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (1950) Hostage Case, p 1296.

  13. 13.

    Ibid.

  14. 14.

    US Nuremberg Tribunal, p 5345 (31 October 1947). See also Rendulic 1965, p 374.

  15. 15.

    United States Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (1950) Hostage Case, p 1296.

  16. 16.

    Ibid., p 1297.

  17. 17.

    Ibid., p 1296.

  18. 18.

    Ibid., p 1297.

  19. 19.

    Rendulic was convicted, however, on counts one, three and four relating respectively to the “murder of hundreds of thousands of civilians”, to the “drafting, distribution, and execution of illegal orders”, and to the “murder, torture, and systematic terrorization, imprisonment in concentration camps, forced labor” of civilians, ibid., pp 1233–1234.

  20. 20.

    Clarke 2012, p 78; Merriam 2016, pp 111–112; Johansen 2019, p 77.

  21. 21.

    See Chap. 8.

  22. 22.

    USAF JAG Department 2014, p 19; Ministry of Foreign Affairs (Israel) 2009, para 125; Office of the Judge Advocate General (Canada) 2001, para 418(3). For an overview of the state practice in this area, see the International Humanitarian Law Database of the International Committee of the Red Cross, available at: https://ihl-databases.icrc.org [accessed 1 April 2023].

  23. 23.

    Montgomery 2002, p 189.

  24. 24.

    Human Rights Council 2009, paras 42, 700, 1922.

  25. 25.

    International Law Association’s Study Group on the Conduct of Hostilities in the 21st Century 2017, p 369.

  26. 26.

    Human Rights Watch 2016, p 7.

  27. 27.

    Supreme Court of Israel Sitting as a High Court of Justice, Hassan Khalaf Ali el Hamri v. Commander of the Judea and Samaria Region, Merits, 10 August 1982, [1982] HCJ No. 361/82, 1984 (1) Palestine Yearbook of International Law 129 (1982), p 133; The Supreme Court of Israel Sitting as the High Court of Justice, Beit Sourik Village Council v. The Government of Israel and the Commander of the IDF Forces in the West Bank, Merits, 30 June 2004, [2004] HCJ 2056/04, para 46. See also Supreme Court of Israel Sitting as High Court, Public Committee against Torture in Israel and Palestinian Society for the Protection of Human Rights and the Environment v Israel, Merits, 13 December 2006, [2006] HCJ 769/02, para 57.

  28. 28.

    International Criminal Court (Office of the Prosecutor) (2014), paras 26, 75, 81; International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) (Trial Chamber 1), Prosecutor v. Stanislav Galić, Judgment and Opinion, 5 December 2003, IT-98-29-T (2003), paras 55, 58, 719.

  29. 29.

    ICTY Review Committee 2000. The authors of this report are at times credited with having created the standard of the “reasonable military commander”, see Henderson and Reece 2018, p 840. In fact, the expression dates back at least to the 1970s. See, for instance, Mallison and Mallison 1977, p 56.

  30. 30.

    ICTY Review Committee 2000, paras 49–50.

  31. 31.

    Jeutner forthcoming.

  32. 32.

    Notably, Immanuel Kant rejected the ideas of the sentimental enlightenment only in the last quarter of his life. See Frazer 2010, p 112.

  33. 33.

    Ibid., p 8.

  34. 34.

    Ibid., p 34.

  35. 35.

    Bourke 1951, p 263.

  36. 36.

    Moyn 2006, p 399.

  37. 37.

    Or “moral taste”, as David Hume calls it. See Hume 1896, p 581.

  38. 38.

    Frazer 2010, p 4.

  39. 39.

    Hume 1896, p 365.

  40. 40.

    Ibid., p 576 (emphasis in original).

  41. 41.

    Ibid., p 581.

  42. 42.

    Hume 2006, p 75.

  43. 43.

    Hume 1896, pp 581–582 (emphasis in original).

  44. 44.

    Hunt 2007, p 65.

  45. 45.

    On the etymology and the relationship between the terms sympathy and empathy, see Moyn 2006, pp 399–400. See also Stueber 2019.

  46. 46.

    Hume 1889, p 158.

  47. 47.

    Smith 1976.

  48. 48.

    At times, Smith focusses on self-assessment, at times he focusses on passing judgment on others. But he maintains that both types of assessment are governed by the same principle, ibid., p 109.

  49. 49.

    Ibid., p 110.

  50. 50.

    See, generally, Del Mar 2018.

  51. 51.

    Raphael 2007, p 35.

  52. 52.

    Stueber 2019.

  53. 53.

    Del Mar 2018, p 64.

  54. 54.

    Raphael 2007, p 10.

  55. 55.

    Ibid., p 49.

  56. 56.

    See also, generally, ibid., Chapter 12.

  57. 57.

    Smith 1978, p 17.

  58. 58.

    Ibid., pp 16–17.

  59. 59.

    Raphael 2007, p 110.

  60. 60.

    Smith 1978, p 17.

  61. 61.

    Ibid., p 104.

  62. 62.

    Ibid., p 87.

  63. 63.

    While it might be presumed that civilians are less likely to commit war crimes, Noel Trew points out that the opposite can also be the case: Trew 2017, pp 124–125.

  64. 64.

    This account by an anonymous military lawyer is related by Luban 2013, p 315. The lawyer in question described the difference between the perspective of civilians and of military officers. Luban himself distinguishes the two camps by reference to their starting point: one “begins with armed conflict” assigning “military necessity […] axiomatic status” while the other “begins with humanitarianism” assigning “human dignity […] primary status”. Ibid., p 316. See also Benvenisti 2010, p 348.

  65. 65.

    United States Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (1950) Hostage Case, pp 1245–1246.

  66. 66.

    Notably, Rendulic himself observed that he found it particularly irritating that he was asked to justify his conduct during wartime before people who “by their own admission” had not “the slightest idea of war”, Rendulic 1965, p 444.

  67. 67.

    Henderson and Reece 2018, p 841. For similar interpretations of the report, see Holland 2004, pp 48–49; Groeben 2010, p 480.

  68. 68.

    ICTY Review Committee 2000, para 50.

  69. 69.

    Ibid.

  70. 70.

    Johansen 2019, p 86.

  71. 71.

    Dinstein 2011, p 488.

  72. 72.

    Ibid.

  73. 73.

    Ibid., p 484.

  74. 74.

    Ibid., p 488.

  75. 75.

    Ibid. See also Sloane 2015, p 319.

  76. 76.

    Dinstein 2011, p 488.

  77. 77.

    Ibid., p 486.

  78. 78.

    Ibid.

  79. 79.

    Ibid., p 484. For a sceptical view of such a portrayal of the enemy, see Noll 2012, pp 223, 225.

  80. 80.

    Dinstein 2011, p 485.

  81. 81.

    Ibid., p 488.

  82. 82.

    Ibid., p 489.

  83. 83.

    Ibid., p 493.

  84. 84.

    Newton 2007, p 900.

  85. 85.

    McLaughlin 2010, p 237. McLaughlin contrasts this understanding of the reasonable person’s identity with a narrower construction of the reasonable person as the reasonable military commander to which the “common law ‘reasonable person’ […] is irrelevant”, ibid., p 232.

  86. 86.

    O’Brien 1972, p 629. See also O’Brien 1957, p 55. Both times O’Brien attributes the term “reasonable colonel” to Ernst Feilchenfeld. Attempts to verify this attribution were unsuccessful. Paul Ramsey used the same expression (and also attributes it to Feilchenfeld), Johnson and Smith 1974, p 192.

  87. 87.

    Franck 2008, pp 737, 765.

  88. 88.

    Sloane 2015, pp 317–318.

  89. 89.

    Blank 2011, p 717.

  90. 90.

    Boothby 2012, p 190.

  91. 91.

    ICTY (Trial Chamber 1), Prosecutor v. Stanislav Galić, Judgment and Opinion, 5 December 2003, IT-98-29-T (2003), para 58.

  92. 92.

    Luban 2013, p 338.

  93. 93.

    Ibid.

  94. 94.

    Ibid.

  95. 95.

    Bothe 2002, p 184.

  96. 96.

    Bothe 2001, p 535.

  97. 97.

    Ibid.

  98. 98.

    Ibid.

  99. 99.

    Wall 2002b.

  100. 100.

    Wall 2002a, p 211.

  101. 101.

    Ibid.

  102. 102.

    Ibid., p 212.

  103. 103.

    Ibid.

  104. 104.

    Ibid.

  105. 105.

    Trew 2017, pp 122–123, 125–126. See also Olásolo 2008, pp 229–230.

  106. 106.

    Adams 2019, p 178.

  107. 107.

    See also Frazer 2010, p 142.

  108. 108.

    Sloane 2015, p 330.

  109. 109.

    Ibid., pp 328–329.

  110. 110.

    Noll 2012, pp 225–226. See also Traven 2021, p 274.

  111. 111.

    Noll 2012, pp 227–228.

  112. 112.

    Ibid., p 228. See also Chap. 11.

  113. 113.

    For the question of common sense in the context of war, see, for example, Lieblich and Benvenisti 2016, pp 253–254; Johansen 2019, pp 403–404.

  114. 114.

    Herrmann K (1944) Report from Evacuation Staff to 20th Mountain Army Concerning Evacuation of Northern Norway. Reproduced as document NOKW-090 by United States Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (1950) Hostage Case, pp 1118–1123.

  115. 115.

    Ibid.

  116. 116.

    Galinsky et al. 2006, p 1069.

  117. 117.

    Hogeveen et al. 2014, p 759; Adams 2019, pp 168, 169.

  118. 118.

    Galinsky et al. 2006, p 1068.

  119. 119.

    Ibid., p 1072.

  120. 120.

    Ibid. The authors note that the lack of perspective-taking is not necessarily the result of a conscious decision but rather that power “makes perspective-taking less likely”.

  121. 121.

    Galinsky et al. 2006, pp 1069, 1072.

  122. 122.

    Hogeveen et al. 2014, p 760.

  123. 123.

    Galinsky et al. 2006, p 1072; Gruenfeld et al. 2008, p 124.

  124. 124.

    Robertson 2013, p 187.

  125. 125.

    Gruenfeld et al. 2008, p 127; Robertson 2013, p 187.

  126. 126.

    Galinsky et al. 2006, p 1070.

  127. 127.

    Ibid., p 1072; Robertson 2013, p 187. See also Adams 2019, p 152.

  128. 128.

    Keltner 2016, p 101.

  129. 129.

    Adams 2019, p 172.

  130. 130.

    Galinsky et al. 2016, p 92.

  131. 131.

    Frazer 2010, pp 53–54.

  132. 132.

    Hume 1889, p 383.

  133. 133.

    Keltner et al. 2003, p 265. The exact definition of the concept of power is disputed. For a similar though slightly different definition, see Galinsky et al. 2016, p 91.

  134. 134.

    Galinsky et al. 2006, p 1073. A similar argument had been advanced earlier by Marshall 1978, pp 160–161.

  135. 135.

    Adams 2019, p 170.

  136. 136.

    Ardant du Picq 1921, pp 45–46.

  137. 137.

    Marshall 1978.

  138. 138.

    Ibid., p 57.

  139. 139.

    Ibid., p 56.

  140. 140.

    Grossman 1996, pp 3–4.

  141. 141.

    Ibid., p 27.

  142. 142.

    Adams 2019, p 176.

  143. 143.

    Ardant du Picq 1921, p 110.

  144. 144.

    Gray 1999, p 178. See also Adams 2019, p 176.

  145. 145.

    Ardant du Picq 1921, p 112.

  146. 146.

    Strozzi-Heckler 2003, p 127. See also Grossman 1996, p 97.

  147. 147.

    Grossman 1996, p 121.

  148. 148.

    Ibid., pp 100–101.

  149. 149.

    Ibid.

  150. 150.

    Fromm 1973, p 123.

  151. 151.

    Ibid., p 121; Grossman 1996, pp 160, 161.

  152. 152.

    Fromm 1973, p 123.

  153. 153.

    For more examples, see Holmes 1989, p 364; Grossman 1996, p 92.

  154. 154.

    Ardant du Picq 1921, p 99.

  155. 155.

    Holmes 1989, p 364; Grossman 1996, p 92.

  156. 156.

    Holmes 1989, p 364; Grossman 1996, p 92.

  157. 157.

    Tōge 2012, pp 38–39.

  158. 158.

    Grossman 1996, p 20.

  159. 159.

    Marshall 1978, p 79.

  160. 160.

    Dyer 1985, p 118.

  161. 161.

    Ardant du Picq 1921, pp 111, 110.

  162. 162.

    Ibid., p 112.

  163. 163.

    Great General Staff of the German Army 1915, pp 71–72.

  164. 164.

    Ibid.

  165. 165.

    For a general overview of the manner in which Marshall’s studies influenced the US Army and of the most important criticisms of his theories, see Williams 1999, Chapters 4–5.

  166. 166.

    Grossman 1996, p 132.

  167. 167.

    Ibid., p 253.

  168. 168.

    Ibid., p 132.

  169. 169.

    Great General Staff of the German Army 1915, pp 71–72. See also Adams 2019, pp 175–176.

References

  • Adams RS (2019) Power and proportionality: The role of empathy and ethics on valuing excessive harm. AF L Rev 80:149–182

    Google Scholar 

  • Ardant du Picq CJJJ (1921) Battle Studies: Ancient and Modern Battle. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Benvenisti E (2010) The legal battle to define the law on transnational asymmetric warfare symposium: war bound by law: non-state actors and the law of armed conflict in the twenty-first century. Duke Journal of Comparative and International Law 20:339–360

    Google Scholar 

  • Blank LR (2011) A new twist on an old story: lawfare and the mixing of proportionalities AGORA: classic international legal maxims in a modern world. Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law 43:707–738

    Google Scholar 

  • Boothby WH (2012) The Law of Targeting. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bothe M (2001) The protection of the civilian population and NATO bombing on Yugoslavia: comments on a Report to the Prosecutor of the ICTY. European Journal of International Law 12:531–535

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bothe M (2002) Targeting. In: Wall AE (ed) Legal and Ethical Lessons of NATO’s Kosovo Campaign. Naval War College, Newport, Rhode Island, pp 173–188

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourke VJ (1951) Rationalism. In: Runes DD (ed) The Dictionary of Philosophy. Philosophical Library, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke B (2012) Proportionality in armed conflicts: a principle in need of clarification? Journal of International Humanitarian Legal Studies 3:73–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Del Mar M (2018) Common virtue and the perspectival imagination: Adam Smith and common law reasoning. Jurisprudence 9:58–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dinstein Y (2011) Concluding remarks: LOAC and attempts to abuse or subvert it. In: Pedrozo RA, Wollschlaeger DP (eds) International law and the Changing Character of War. Naval War College, Newport, Rhode Island, pp 483–496

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyer G (1985) War. Crown, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Franck TM (2008) On proportionality of countermeasures in international law. American Journal of International Law 102:715–767

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frazer ML (2010) The Enlightenment of Sympathy: Justice and the Moral Sentiments in the Eighteenth Century and Today. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fromm E (1973) The Anatomy of Human Destructiveness. Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Galinsky AD, Magee JC, Inesi ME, Gruenfeld DH (2006) Power and perspectives not taken. Psychological Science 17:1068–1074

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galinsky AD, Rucker DD, Magee JC (2016) Power and perspective-taking: a critical examination. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 67:91–92

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gray JG (1999) The Warriors: Reflections on Men in Battle. University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln

    Google Scholar 

  • Great General Staff of the German Army (1915) The War Book of the German General Staff. McBridge, Nast & Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Grossman D (1996) On Killing: The Psychological Cost of Learning to Kill in War and Society. Little, Brown and Co., New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruenfeld DH, Inesi ME, Magee JC, Galinsky AD (2008) Power and the objectification of social targets. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 95:111–127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henderson I, Reece K (2018) Proportionality under international humanitarian law: the “reasonable military commander” standard and reverberating effects. Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law 51:835–855

    Google Scholar 

  • Hogeveen J, Inzlicht M, Obhi SS (2014) Power changes how the brain responds to others. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 143:755–762

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland J (2004) Military objective and collateral damage: their relationship and dynamics. Yearbook of International Humanitarian Law 7:35–78

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmes R (1989) Acts of War: The Behaviour of Men in Battle. Simon & Schuster, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Human Rights Council (2009) Human Rights in Palestine and Other Occupied Arab Territories: Report of the United Nations Fact-Finding Mission on the Gaza Conflict, UN DOC A/HRC/12/48

    Google Scholar 

  • Human Rights Watch (2016) Making the Case: The Dangers of Killer Robots and the Need for a Preemptive Ban. Available at https://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/report_pdf/arms1216_web.pdf

  • Hume D (1889) Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary. Lewis, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1896) A Treatise of Human Nature (Selby-Bigge LA (ed)). Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (2006) An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals: A Critical Edition (Beauchamp TL (ed)). Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunt L (2007) Inventing Human Rights: A History. W. W. Norton & Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • ICTY Review Committee (2000) Final Report to the Prosecutor by the Committee Established to Review the NATO Bombing Campaign Against the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia, ICTY, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • International Criminal Court (Office of the Prosecutor) (2014) Situation in the Republic of Korea (Article 5 Report), ICC, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • International Law Association’s Study Group on the Conduct of Hostilities in the 21st Century (2017) The Conduct of Hostilities and International Humanitarian Law: Challenges of 21st Century Warfare. International Law Studies 93:322–388

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeutner V (forthcoming) The Reasonable Person: A Legal Biography. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Johansen SR (2019) The Military Commander’s Necessity: The Law of Armed Conflict and Its Limits. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson J, Smith D (1974) Love and Society: Essays in the Ethics of Paul Ramsey. Scholars’ Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Keltner D (2016) The Power Paradox: How We Gain and Lose Influence. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Keltner D, Gruenfeld DH, Anderson C (2003) Power, approach, and inhibition. Psychological Review 110:265–284

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lieblich E, Benvenisti E (2016) The obligation to exercise discretion in warfare: why autonomous weapon systems are unlawful. In: Bhuta N, Beck S, Geiß R, Liu H-Y, Creß C (eds) Autonomous Weapons Systems: Law, Ethics, Policy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 245–283

    Google Scholar 

  • Luban D (2013) Military necessity and the cultures of military law. Leiden Journal of International Law 26:315–349

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallison WT, Mallison SV (1977) The juridical status of irregular combatants under the international humanitarian law of armed conflict. Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law 9:39–78

    Google Scholar 

  • Marshall SLA (1978) Men Against Fire: The Problem of Battle Command in Future War. Peter Smith, Gloucester, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin R (2010) The law of armed conflict and international human rights law: some paradigmatic differences and operational implications. Yearbook of International Humanitarian Law 13:213–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merriam JJ (2016) Affirmative target identification: operationalizing the principle of distinction for US warfighters. Virginia Journal of International Law 56:83–146

    Google Scholar 

  • Ministry of Foreign Affairs (Israel) (2009) The Operation in Gaza: Factual and Legal Aspects. Ministry of Foreign Affairs, Jerusalem

    Google Scholar 

  • Montgomery T (2002) Legal perspective from the EUCOM targeting cell. In: Wall AE (ed) Legal and Ethical Lessons of NATO’s Kosovo campaign. Naval War College, Newport, Rhode Island, pp 189–197

    Google Scholar 

  • Moyn S (2006) Empathy in history, empathizing with humanity. History and Theory 45:397–415

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newton MA (2007) Modern military necessity: the role and relevance of military lawyers symposium. Roger Williams U L Rev 12:877–903

    Google Scholar 

  • Noll G (2012) Analogy at war: proportionality, equality and the law of targeting. Netherlands Yearbook of International Law 43:205–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien WV (1957) The Yearbook of World Polity. Praeger, Westport

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien WV (1972) Law of war, command responsibility and Vietnam, The. Geo L J 60:605–664

    Google Scholar 

  • Office of the Judge Advocate General (Canada) (2001) Joint Doctrine Manual, Law of Armed Conflict at the Tactical and Operational Levels, B-GJ-005-104/FP-021

    Google Scholar 

  • Olásolo H (2008) Unlawful Attacks in Combat Situations: From the ICTY’s Case Law to the Rome Statute. Brill Nijhoff, Leiden

    Google Scholar 

  • Raphael DD (2007) The Impartial Spectator: Adam Smith’s Moral Philosophy. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rendulic L (1965) Soldat in stürzenden Reichen. Damm Verlag, Munich

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson IH (2013) How power affects the brain. The Psychologist 26:186–189

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloane RD (2015) Puzzles of proportion and the “reasonable military commander”: reflections on the law, ethics, and geopolitics of proportionality. Harvard National Security Journal 6:299–343

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith A (1976) The Theory of Moral Sentiments (Raphael DD, Macfie AL (eds)). Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith A (1978) Lectures on Jurisprudence (Meek RL, Raphael DD, Stein PG (eds)). Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Strozzi-Heckler R (2003) In Search of the Warrior Spirit: Teaching Awareness Disciplines to the Green Berets. North Atlantic Books, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Stueber K (2019) Empathy. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tōge S (2012) Little Child. In: Tōge S (author) Poems of the Atomic Bomb. University of Chicago, Chicago, pp 38–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Traven D (2021) Law and Sentiment in International Politics: Ethics, Emotions, and the Evolution of the Laws of War. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Trew N (2017) Dead Letter Law Arising from Strategic Choices: The Difficulty of Achieving Accountability for the Jus in Bello Rules on Proportionality and Precautions in Attack. University of Exeter, Exeter

    Google Scholar 

  • USAF JAG Department (2014) Air Force Operations and the Law, 3rd edn. United States Air Force, Maxwell AFB

    Google Scholar 

  • von der Groeben C (2010) Criminal responsibility of German soldiers in Afghanistan: the case of Colonel Klein. German Law Journal 11:469–491

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wall AE (ed) (2002a) Discussion: Reasonable Military Commanders and Reasonable Civilians. Legal and Ethical Lessons of NATO’s Kosovo Campaign. International Law Studies. Naval War College, Newport, Rhode Island, pp 211–212

    Google Scholar 

  • Wall AE (2002b) Legal and Ethical Lessons of NATO’s Kosovo campaign. Naval War College, Newport, Rhode Island

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams FDG (1999) SLAM - The Influence of S.L.A. Marshall on the United States Army. In: Canedy S (ed) Office of the Command Historian, United States Army Training and Doctrine Command, Washington, D.C.

    Google Scholar 

Other Documents

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Valentin Jeutner .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2024 T.M.C. Asser Press and the authors

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Jeutner, V. (2024). Empathy at War: The Distinction Between Reasonableness and the Reasonable Military Commander Standard. In: Hayashi, N., Lingaas, C. (eds) Honest Errors? Combat Decision-Making 75 Years After the Hostage Case. T.M.C. Asser Press, The Hague. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-6265-611-6_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-6265-611-6_10

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: T.M.C. Asser Press, The Hague

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-6265-610-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-6265-611-6

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics