Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 195))

  • 231 Accesses

Abstract

The thesis of this essay is that there is a primordial apprehension of the contingency of nature in civilized experience.1 The expressions of this apprehension of contingency have taken many forms, from the mythic to the philosophical and theological. The expressions have different motifs in different cultures, and there is no preferred cultural starting point. My intent here is to explore the truth about this apprehension of contigency, however, and so I shall be arguing for a preferable contemporary way of understanding it, framed in the discourse of Western intellectual traditions as informed by the East and South Asian. In particular, I shall argue that there are two dimensions to the contingency of nature, namely the contingency of natural things within nature, and the contingency of nature as such, and that the apprehension of both is one of the founding definitions of human culture. The first can be called cosmological contingency, characteristic of cosmological processes, and the second ontological contingency, the contingency of being as such, from ontos, one of the Greek words for being. These two senses of contingency are closely related. From a cross-cultural perspective, the notions of both nature and its apprehension are problematic, and some of the discussion to follow treats these problems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Indeed perhaps in all human experience although the discussion here is limited to its civilized expressions.

    Google Scholar 

  2. The extended defense of this thesis is complicated, but I have attempted it in print. Part of the defense is to show how symbolic representation is itself a part of nature. For this we need not only a theory of signs, such as that provided by Peirce, but a theory of nature as well. Then we need an analysis of some important kinds of symbols, such as religious ones, that purport to engage “ontological” dimensions of reality as well as garden variety things. My trilogy, Axiology of Thinking, attempts the theory of signs and nature; it consists in Reconstruction of Thinking (Albany: SUNY Press, 1981 ), Recovery of the Measure (Albany: SUNY Press, 1987), and Normative Cultures (Albany: SUNY Press, 1995). For a theory of religious symbols and their ontological reach, see my The Truth of Broken Symbols ( Albany: SUNY Press, 1996 ).

    Google Scholar 

  3. By “West” here I mean Western Asia with its European appendage and American colonies, and include the religious traditions of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam, each of which has been called a civilization in its own right.

    Google Scholar 

  4. The criticism of the idea of totality in nature in Kant’s Antinomies (Critique of Pure Reason,B 455–462). I have discussed it at some length regarding Hegel and Whitehead’s approach to nature in The Highroad around Modernism (Albany: SUNY Press, 1992), chapter 5.

    Google Scholar 

  5. This was the nub of Kant’s argument about totality.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Many of the elements of nature discussed here, in the ancient conceptions, are discussed compendiously by Richard Sorabji in Time, Creation, and the Continuum: Theories in Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages ( Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993 ).

    Google Scholar 

  7. See the book of Judges in the Bible.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See 1 Samuel in the Bible.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See Isaiah 40–66; Ezekiel; Job.

    Google Scholar 

  10. On the secularizing of God’s creation, see Tikva Frymer-Kensky’s In the Wake of the Goddesses: Women, Culture, and the Biblical Transformation of Pagan Myth (New York: Free Press, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  11. See Karl Jaspers’ Way to Wisdom,translated by Ralph Manheim (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1954).

    Google Scholar 

  12. The ideal of early modern science was to quantify measurement, as in Descartes’ analytical geometry. See my discussion in Reconstruction of Thinking,chapter 1.

    Google Scholar 

  13. The discussion to follow summarizes in part my analysis of determinateness in God the Creator (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968; reprint with a new preface, Albany: SUNY Press, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Bradley’s Appearance and Reality (Second edition; Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1897).

    Google Scholar 

  15. There might be many things with respect to which it is only partially determinate, or indeterminate. It might be, for instance, that the determinate character of the present is such that several different responses to future possibilities can be made; with respect to the future, the present is somewhat open or indeterminate, awaiting subsequent deciding events.

    Google Scholar 

  16. This analysis summarizes that in Recovery of the Measure,chapters 9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Our late modern age has more difficulty than the ancient Western world in imagining dynamic eternity as the context for emersion in the temporality of life. But that is because of an impoverishment in the conception of time as much as it is a collapse of eternalistic religious sensibilities.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See the analysis of perception and appearance in Reconstruction of Thinking,part 2.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Stephen Hawking, A Brief History of Time ( New York: Bantam, 1988 ), p. 174.

    Google Scholar 

  20. The argument above urged that things are determinate only by being related to other things, and that they and the other things must have essential features that are together on a more basic level than their conditioning relations. Thus even the laws of logic and mathematics are ontologically contingent even if we cannot imagine alternatives — indeed, imagination itself is contingent.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Translated by Wing-tsit Chan in his edited Source Book in Chinese Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1963), p. 139.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Chan, p. 463.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Translated by A.A. Macdonell in A Source Book in Indian Philosophy edited by Sarvepalli Radhakrishna and Charles A. Moore ( Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957 ), pp. 23–24.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Neville, R.C. (1998). The Contingency of Nature. In: Cohen, R.S., Tauber, A.I. (eds) Philosophies of Nature: The Human Dimension. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 195. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2614-6_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2614-6_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4859-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2614-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics