Skip to main content

The Universalization of Responsibility as a Passage from Ethics to a Politics of Questioning: Simon Critchley’s Reading of Levinas

  • Chapter
Levinas between Ethics and Politics

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 152))

  • 166 Accesses

Abstract

Interpretations of the passage from the ethical to the political domains in Levinas move between the two perspectives sketched in the previous chapter. The interpretations of the universalization of ethics range from a demand for de facto justice to a highly individualized aesthetic expression, which ultimately has little to do with politics. The first position is exemplified by Simon Critchley who proposes a formal theory of political activity inspired by Levinas’ ethics.1 The second position is that of Gillian Rose, who perceives in Levinas’ political writings the incompatibility of his formal ethics and a pragmatic secular politics.2 Neither commentator addresses prophecy at length as the generalization of ethical responsibility. However, they draw very different conclusions about the political implications of ethical enactment in Levinas. At the heart of their disagreement stands a specific understanding of ethical witness, or prophetism, in its relation to society and politics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Simon Critchley, op. cit.,pp. 220 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Gillian Rose, “New Political Theology—Out of Holocaust and Liberation” in The Broken Middle: Out of our Ancient Past (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1992), pp. 247–307.ín this chapter, Rose argues above all that Levinas is one of a number of contemporary thinkers who have eliminated the possibility of the dialectisation, or the mediation, of necessity, or nature, and freedom. Such a mediation is, in her view, unavoidable for there to be a viable transition between the `domains’ of ethics, and social existence and political practice. This work is principally critical of post-modern thought, and although the spirit of the thinking herein comes from Hegelian thought, it does not attempt a positive, neo-Hegelian solution.

    Google Scholar 

  3. In regard to Levinas, Rose argues that the former manifests a blindness to one of the major debates in present day Judaism: viz., whether and how to supplement halakah (= “the way to go”; Judaism’s combined Law of the ‘oral’ law, codified in the Mishna [=“Repetition”] and the written law, i.e., of the Babylonian Talmud, principally). The question of a supplement to the prescriptions of halakah turns upon the relation of the holy law of the Tradition, which itself concerns Jews’ ethical behavior in every day life, and another, more secular ethics. As Rose writes, “[The ethics of] Levinas obscures a difficulty which modern Judaism—across the range from cultural orthodoxy to liberalism—admits: that the clash of Judaic law (halakah) and non-Judaic law raises issues concerning the relation of law and ethics within Judaism and between Judaic and non-Judaic judgement and institutions. This obscuring may be traced to the implication that the… `orders’ of `being’ are not themselves ethical when the idea of `order’ implies that they are ethical—normative, general and imperative, immanent and transcendent, actual and ideal, even when dirempted.” pp. 260–261 (my emphasis).

    Google Scholar 

  4. This work of Derrida, entitled in the original, “En ce moment même dans cet ouvrage me voici” appears in the French in François Lamelle, ed. Textes Pour Emmanuel Levinas,(Paris: Editions Jean-Michel Place, 1980), pp. 21–60.The English translation is found in R. Bernasconi and S. Critchley, eds. Re-reading Levinas,pp.11–49.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Critchley throws light upon the term “deconstruction” early in his text with five negative definitions or qualifications. These are so useful to the understanding of Derrida’s (non) method that I want to reproduce them here. Firstly, Critchley writes, “deconstruction is not something negative; it is not a process of demolition (which does not automatically entail that it is positive).”Secondly, “deconstruction needs to be sharply distinguished from analysis,which presupposes a reduction of entities to their simple… elements which themselves would stand in need of deconstruction.” In the third place, “deconstruction is not critique,either in the general or the Kantian sense.” Instead, according to Derrida, the possibility of transcendental critique and the manner in which it is effected can be an interest or object of deconstruction. Fourthly, “deconstruction is not a method… that can be utilized in the activity of interpretation.” Hence it is not one, writes Critchley following Derrida, of a number of methods in competition in various domains of knowledge. Finally, “deconstruction is not an act produced or controlled by a subject; nor is it an operation that sets to work on a text or an institution.” See Critchley, loc. cit.,pp. 21–22 (all but last two emphases mine).On the other hand, the term “deconstruction” does concern the reading of a text. A deconstructive reading, per Critchley who follows Derrida’s own remarks faithfully, entails two `moments’ which are not necessarily successive. These moments must begin with the determination of a level of “minimal consensus concerning the intelligibility” of the text. (Critchley, p. 24, citing Limited Inc. p. 269 tr. p. 146). Such is achieved by a faithful reconstruction of the “dominant interpretation of a text in a layer of ‘commentary”’ (Critchley, p. 25). The second moment of a deconstructive reading—although, again, such a breakdown invariably makes deconstruction appear as if it could be presented qua mode d’emploi or as if in a user’s manual—lies in the much more precarious discernment, which remains within the limits set by the text itself, of those ambivalences and hesitations in the work that work against what the text intended to convey. (Critchley, p. 27) However, this second moment, as Critchley notes, must arise from the first; i.e., out of the words of the work itself. am here following Francis Guibal’s 1986 presentation of Derrida’s work in a colloquium to which the latter was invited, “The Alterity of the Other—Otherwise: On the Traces of Jacques Derrida” in Altérités: Jacques Derrida et Pierre-Jean Labarrière (Paris: Editions Osiris, March 1986), p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See Critchley, loc. cit.,pp. 25 ff. ‘Ibid.,p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Critchley, pp. 32–33. ‘Context’ appears analogous to linguistics’ notion of the paradigmatic axis of language, that indefinable reserve out of which speech, or the syntagmatic axis, arises as pure spontaneity. Critchley’s remarks here are very helpful. He writes, “For Derrida, this response has a double consequence: first, that the current concept of context is inadequate, and second, that a generalized concept of context would entail an enlargement… of the traditional concept of writing, which could not longer be seen simply as a means of communication for the transmission of meaning” (p. 33).This claim also rejoins Levinas when he denies that language is merely a system for passing on information or instruction. (Cf. Leçon talmudique,p. 99; Revelation in the Jewish Tradition,p. 208; OBBE,pp. 43–7, 193–4, 196–7 [Fr.]; 34–6, 151–2, 154–5 [Eng.]). In the different texts I have written on (against) apartheid, I have on several occasions spoken of ’unconditional’ affirmation or of ’uncondition’ ’appeal’ [appel].This has also happened to me in other ’contexts’ and each time that I speak of the link between deconstruction and the ’yes’. Now, the very least that can be said of unconditionality (a word that I use not by accident to recall the character of the categorical imperative in its Kantian form) is that it is independent of every determinate context,… It announces itself as such only in the opening of context. Not that it is simply present (existent) elsewhere, outside of all context; rather it intervenes in the determination of a context from its very opening, and from an injunction, a law, a responsibility that transcends this or that determination of a given context. Following this, what remains is to articulate this unconditionality with the determinate… conditions of this or that context; and this is the moment of strategies, of rhetorics, of ethics and of

    Google Scholar 

  8. politic…

    Google Scholar 

  9. Critchley, p. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Levinas, Leon talmudique sur la justice,p. 99.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Derrida, Limited Inc.,(Paris: Galilée, 1988), pp. 281–82.English translation Limited Inc. (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1990), pp. 152–53. Cited, with emphasis, by Simon Critchley, loc. cit.,pp. 31–32.The reference to “deconstruction and the ‘yesrecalls a certain affirmation in Derrida’s writings. Critchley writes, “it is Nietzsche’s ’vast and boundless Yes and Amen saying’,... It is the ’Yes, to the stranger’ that opens… Derrida’s text on Michel de Certeau“ (pp. 40–41).This is a ‘yes’ that affirms no thing; it is a movement that itself issues in no theory. For Critchley, this affirmation is the ”ethical moment that motivates deconstruction“ (p. 41).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Is not this ‘yes’ reminiscent of what Levinas calls the ’glory’ of the self-opening of the Saying? Such a question overflows the present ’context’.See Critchley, pp. 40 ff. He has written, “… and for Derrida the ethical moment is the interruption of the general context of conditioned hypothetical imperatives by an unconditional categorical imperative. Ethics arises in and as the undecidable yet determinate articulation of these two orders.”

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid., p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  14. From Levinas, “Signature” in Difficile liberté. Essais sur le Judaisme (Paris: Editions Albin Michel, 1975 edition), p. 409. Cited in part by Critchley, p. 4, who writes, “’Moral consciousness is not an experience of values’; it is rather the delineation of the essence of meaning of the ethical in a way that disrupts traditional moral thinking and all claims to good conscience.” (Statement is Critchley’s after the single quotations.) For the textual citation from Levinas, emphasis has been added.

    Google Scholar 

  15. SLevinas, Difficile liberté, p. 409.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See J. Derrida, “En ce moment même dans cet ouvrage me voici” in François Lamelle, ed., Textes pour Emmanuel Lévinas, (Paris: Jean-Michel Place, 1980), pp. 21–60. English translation by Ruben Berezdivin, “At This Very Moment in This Work Here I Am,” in Robert Bernasconi and Simon Critchley, eds., Re-Reading Levinas ( Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press, 1991 ) pp. 11–48.

    Google Scholar 

  17. OBBE, p. 179 (Fr.), 141(Eng.).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Derrida, “En ce moment même…,” p. 27

    Google Scholar 

  19. cited by Critchley, loc. cit.,p. 122. “ bid.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See for example, OBBE,pp. 145, 155 (Fr.), 113–14, 121 (Eng.).

    Google Scholar 

  21. See OBBE,pp. 138–9, 147 (Fr.), 109, 115–16 (Eng.).

    Google Scholar 

  22. See Critchley, loc. cit.,p. 124.

    Google Scholar 

  23. bid.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., p. 125.

    Google Scholar 

  25. bid., p. 126.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Critchley discerns a three-fold structure in OBBE. He points out that the “exposition begins at the level of the said, of entities exposed in their essence in… the domination of totality. The second moment [of the work] is the move from the Said to the Saying, by peeling off the layers of ethical subjectivity until the structure of substitution is delineated in chapter 4.”Finally, “in a third moment, chapter 5 moves from the Saying back to the Said…, in order to reopen the questions of justice, politics, community, ontology, and philosophy…” loc. cit.,p. 229.

    Google Scholar 

  27. OBBE, p. 182 (Fr.), 143 (Eng.), translation modified.

    Google Scholar 

  28. OBBE, p. 182, 143, translation modified.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Critchley, p. 128. One may see a similar mechanism at work in the verses of Ezekiel 1:1–2:10, for example.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Of the interruption of thematization that is prophecy, Levinas writes, “its signification has not let itself be betrayed in the logos except in order to translate itself before us—a word articulated already as kerygma in prayer or blasphemy, keeping thus in its enunciation the trace of the excession of transcendence, of the beyond.

    Google Scholar 

  31. By these ambiguities prophetism is not the least option [le pis-aller] of a hobbling revelation. The ambiguities belong to the glory of the Infinite. That prophetism might take on the appearances of information circulating among other [information] issued from the subject or from influences undergone by the subject… —there lies the enigma—the ambiguity—but also the regime of transcendence of the Infinite. The Infinite is belied in the proof that the finite should like to give of its transcendence, it [the Infinite] should enter into conjunction with the subject which should make it appear. There it would lose its glory. Transcendence owes

    Google Scholar 

  32. it to itself to interrupt its own demonstration. It voice must be stifled [se taire] or silenced from the moment one listens to its message.… It requires diachrony breaking the unity of transcendental apperception which does not arrive at assembling the time of modern humanity… because incapable of denying the fraternity of men…“ (OBBE,p. 194, 152).

    Google Scholar 

  33. See Critchley, pp. xii—xiii, 220 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Critchley, p. 221.

    Google Scholar 

  35. OBBE, pp. 202–3 (Fr.), 159–160 (Eng.). Cited in Critchley, loc. cit., p. 221.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Critchley, p. 222.

    Google Scholar 

  37. lbid., This is from Levinas’ “Politique après!” in Au-delà du verset (Paris: Éditions de Minuit, 1982), pp. 221–28.

    Google Scholar 

  38. bid., Indeed, Simon Critchley reminds us at this point that a quietistic politics is exactly that for which Levinas reproached Martin Buber’s I-thou relation.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid., p. 223.

    Google Scholar 

  40. lbid.

    Google Scholar 

  41. T1, p. 189 (Fr.), 214 (Eng.).

    Google Scholar 

  42. bid.

    Google Scholar 

  43. T1, p. 188, 213.

    Google Scholar 

  44. But should not the opening to the beyond of Essence, to the ‘otherwise than being’, signify thus the possibility of seeing,of knowing,of understanding and grasping [de comprendre et de prendre],which by all evidence should come back to thematizing,and thus, to… discover a field for knowledge, for the taking in hand, for movement or displacement [déplacement],for operation and possession? The opening should thus bring the subject, where these intentions were recognized as fundamental or as good, eventually to be otherwise, but not to `otherwise than be. 42

    Google Scholar 

  45. OBBE, p. 225 (Fr.),178 (Eng.), my translation and emphasis. ’OBBE,p. 210 (Fr.), 175 (Fr.).

    Google Scholar 

  46. OBBE,p. ix (Fr.), xli (Eng.). 45OBBE, p. 151, 118.

    Google Scholar 

  47. One might argue that Levinas’ use of the term `death’ in the context noted above is intended to bespeak the finitude and of conceptualism And this is supported by earlier remarks in that section. (“It is as though the Platonic Ideas themselves owed their eternity and their purity as universals only to the perishing of the perishable…”) But the discussion also turns to the ways in which a subject confronts and refuses its own, factical death. (“This refusal of death in fact measures the depth of its [the subject’s] inwardness in essence,or its interest” (OBBE,p. 221, 175).

    Google Scholar 

  48. Critchley, loc. cit.,p. 225. ‘Critchley, loc. cit.,p. 239.

    Google Scholar 

  49. OBBE, p. 156 (Fr.), 121 (Eng.).

    Google Scholar 

  50. Critchley interprets the `prophet’ to be “the person who puts the community under the word of God, who binds the community and makes it a commonality” p. 226 ff. This seems quite right to me. It further seems that this God—and this double community of ethics and politics which, he reminds us, is called `monotheism’ by Levinas—does not much enter his discussion of politics.`God’ and `monotheism’ are not, themselves, problematized by Critchley. What he does say is that “[tlhe patriarchal and seemingly onto-theo-logical implications of these lines should be neither reduced nor elided.” He does not thereafter return to these implications, however. On the other hand, I believe that Levinas’ notions of God and monotheism are not so much onto-theo-logical in the Heideggerian sense of the term, rather they remind us again of what I alluded to earlier. The spirit of Levinasian hermeneutic phenomenology is the Jewish experience as inscribed in the Talmud and, significantly, in recent history.What do I mean when I refer to `recent history’? I refer, among other things, to a discussion of Jewish identity offered by the sociologist, Zygmunt Bauman, whose work Modernity and the Holocaust shows both the uniqueness and the `normalcy’, for our civilization of bureaucracy and technology, of the Shoah. Recent history then shows us the planning and execution of genocide based upon the racism of the gardener’s ideology, viz., the design to weed out elements which by their nature are conceived as incapable of bringing health or beauty to the national garden. Further, there was something quite specific to Jewish `weeds’.Bauman writes, “Hardly any dimension of the endemic Jewish incongruence, however, has influenced the shape of modern anti-Semitism more strongly and in more durable fashion than the fact that the Jews were, to quote Arendt again, a ‘non-national element in a world of growing or existing nations’.… Everywhere [the Jews] served as a constant reminder of the relativity and limits of individual self-identity and communal interest, which the criterion of nationhood was meant to determine with absolute and final authority.” Yet this reminder was supplemented by a paradox, which itself fueled the hatred of anti-Semites.“The Jews, Bauman writes, “were not just unlike any nation; they were also unlike any other foreigners. In short, they undermined the very difference between hosts and guests, the native and the foreign…. Jews were flexible and adaptable; an empty vehicle, ready to be filled with whatever despicable load `they’ were charged of carrying. Thus Toussenel saw the Jews as the bearers of anti-French poison, while Liesching… accused the Jews of smuggling into Germany the pestilent Gallic spirit.”See Bauman, Modernity and the Holocaust (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991) p. 52 (Author’s emphasis). I will return to discuss Bauman shortly. For his gardening metaphor applied to modern society, see pp. 91 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Critchley, loc. cit.,p. 233.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Levinas, Difficile Liberté: Essais sur le judaïsme (Paris: Éditions Albin Michel, 1976, 3rd edition revised), pp. 24–42.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Critchley, loc. cit.,pp. 236–241.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ibid., p. 237.

    Google Scholar 

  55. To the initiators and the managers of modern genocide, society is a subject of planning and conscious design. One can and should do more about the society than change one or several of its many details… cure some of its troublesome ailments. One can and should set oneself goals more ambitious…: one can and should remake the society… One can create a society that is objectively better than the one `merely existing’—that is, existing without conscious intervention.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Bauman, Modernity and the Holocaust (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991). 5’Bauman, op. cit.,p. 91.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Critchley, loc. cit.,p. 238. It appears that this definition excludes most political orders having a direct or secondary position in a globalizing economy, in which North-South domination is anything but diminished today.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Bauman, op. cit.,p. 108.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil (New York: Viking Press, 1964), pp. 294–95, cited by Bauman, loc. cit.,p. 177.

    Google Scholar 

  60. BBE, p. 189 (Fr.), 148 (Eng.).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bergo, B. (1999). The Universalization of Responsibility as a Passage from Ethics to a Politics of Questioning: Simon Critchley’s Reading of Levinas. In: Levinas between Ethics and Politics. Phaenomenologica, vol 152. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2077-9_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2077-9_11

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5214-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2077-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics