Skip to main content

Abstract

It was not so long ago that it was regarded as importantly obvious that a major feature of the seventeenth century was a secularization of knowledge. Butterfield, for example, had written of the second half of the seventeenth century as “a colossal secularization of thought in every possible realm of ideas at the same time”1. This secular movement was all of a piece with the battle between the Ancients and the Moderns and was much associated with the rise of modern science, especially as manifested in the thought of such giants as Galileo, and Newton, and the empiricist philosophy of Locke.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Herbert Butterfield, The Origins of Modern Science (London, 1951) p.166.

    Google Scholar 

  2. De Augmentis Scientiarum, III, 1, The Philosophical Works of Francis Bacon, edited by John M. Robinson from the texts of Ellis and Speckling (London, 1905 ) pp. 453–4.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Letter to the Grand Duchess Christina (1615), Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo, edited by Stillman Drake (New York, 1957), p.182.

    Google Scholar 

  4. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding,edited by P.H. Nidditch (Oxford, 1975), p.10. All references to the Essay will be to this edition and normally cited by Book, Chapter and Section number, and by page.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See his Locke and the Compass of Human Understanding (Cambridge, 1970) especially Chapter 1.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Essay, IV, XXI, 1–4, pp. 720–21.

    Google Scholar 

  7. ECHU, II, XI, 23, p.520. Locke attended Willis’s Oxford lectures around 1663 and 1664. Cf. Kenneth Dewhurst: Willis’s Oxford Lectures (Sanford Publications, Oxford, 1980) which contains a transcript of Locke’s MS.

    Google Scholar 

  8. In this essay, somewhat anachronistically, I shall sometimes talk of the sciences or the natural sciences, often using the terms as synonymous with `natural philosophy’. I am well aware that they were not so used in the early modern period, any more than the term ‘philosophy’ always means the same today as it did then (though it sometimes does). For something on these changes see: Andrew Cunningham and Perry Williams: “De-centring the `Big Picture’: The Origins of Modern Science and the modern origins of science”, which also has some remarks about Butterfield’s work, and see the discussion in Robert Crocker’s Introduction,above.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See, for example, the following papers by Popkin: “The Third Force in Seventeenth-Century Thought: Scepticism, Science and Millenarianism”, “Newton’s Biblical Theology and his Theological Physics” and “The Religious Background of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy”, all now collected in his The Third Force in Seventeenth-Century Thought (Leiden, 1992). See also the papers in Philosophy, Science, and Religion in England, 1640–1700,edited by Richard Kroll, Richard Ashcraft, and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge, 1992) and Millenarianism and Messianism in English Literature and Thought 1650–1800,edited by Richard Popkin (Leiden, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Rorty claims that it is not until Kant that the modern science-philosophy distinction takes hold. If this is so then there was no such subject as epistemology in the seventeenth century. I have considerable sympathy with some of Rorty’s claim, but there can be no doubt that characteristically epistemic worries emerge in Descartes, Locke and other canonical philosophers of the seventeenth century, and in my understanding of these matters owe a great deal to the recovery of ancient sceptical arguments at the very same time as atomistic theories once again enter the arena of natural philosophy. See his Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP, 1979 ), Chapter 3.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Many in England were of course influenced by Descartes but the number of those who accepted his sharp dualism appears very small. The Franciscan, Antoine Le Grand was a Cartesian and long resident in Oxfordshire, but whether he counts as an English Cartesian is doubtful as he was a native of Douay. Admirers of Descartes, such as Walter Charleton, often found difficulty in his sharp dualism.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. Immortality of the Soul, passim, in A Collection of Several Philosophical Writings of Dr Henry More (London, 1712) hereafter CSPW.

    Google Scholar 

  13. CSPW, The Immortality of the Soul, Book 3, ch. 12, p. 212.

    Google Scholar 

  14. The secondary literature on the Cambridge Platonists is now enormous. For a bibliography see: G.A.J. Rogers: “Die Cambridger Platoniker” in Grunddriss der Geschichte der Philosophie, Die Philosophie des 17. Jahrhunderts 3 England,edited by Jean-Pierre (Basel: Schobinger, 1988), pp.285–290. For a relevant recent account of Henry More see Arlene Miller Guinsburg “Henry More, Thomas Vaughan and the Late Renaissance Magical Tradition” Ambix,27 (1980), pp. 36–58.

    Google Scholar 

  15. The True Intellectual System of the Universe,to which are added the Notes of Dr J.L. Mosheim (3 vols, London, 1845), Vol. I, `Preface to the Reader’, p.xxxiii.

    Google Scholar 

  16. B.J.T. Dobbs: The Foundations of Newton’s Alchemy ( Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1975 ) p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Quoted in Dobbs, ibid. from Barrow: In comitiis 1652. Cartesiana hypothesis de materia et motu haud satisfacit praecipuis naturae phaenomenis,Barrow, Theological Works,(Cambridge, 1859), Vol. 9, pp.89–90. Translation from Percy Osmond: Isaac Barrow. His Life and Times (London, 1944), p.31.

    Google Scholar 

  18. On Robert Boyle’s intellectual development and his place in seventeenth-century thought see the rather contrasting accounts of M.A. Hunter: Robert Boyle (1627–1691). Scrupulosity and Science (London: The Boydell Press, 2000) especially Chapter 2 and Antonio Clericuzio: Elements, Principles and Corpuscles. A Study of Atomism and Chemistry in the Seventeenth Century (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2001), especially Chapters 3 and 4.

    Google Scholar 

  19. For a recent treatment see Margaret Osier’s “The intellectual sources of Robert Boyle’s philosophy of nature: Gassendi’s voluntarism and Boyle’s physico-theological project” in Philosophy, Science and Religion in England,edited by Richard Kroll, Richard Ashcraft and Perez Zagorin (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1992), pp. 178–198.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Origin of Forms and Qualities According to the Corpuscular Philosophy. The Theoretical Part,in The Works of the Hon. Robert Boyle,edited by Thomas Birch (6 vols, London, 1672), Vol. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  21. For the dispute between More and Boyle see Robert A. Greene: “Henry More and Robert Boyle on the Spirit of Nature”, JHI, 32 (1962), pp. 451–474.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Works,Vol. 3, p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Works,Vol. 4, p.7.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Of the High Veneration Man’s Intellect Owes to God, Works, Vol. 5, p. 131.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Works,Vol. 4, p.410.

    Google Scholar 

  26. In Advice in Judging of Things said to Transcend Reason he argues that normally there is a sharp difference between essence and existence. However, in the case of God (an infinitely perfect being) actual existence being a perfection, must belong to him.. Works,Vol. 4, p.461.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Royal Society Boyle Papers, Vol. XXXV in M.A. Stewart (ed), Selected Philosophical Papers of Robert Boyle ( Manchester: Manchester UP, 1979 ) p. 119.

    Google Scholar 

  28. For a brief overview see my “Descartes and the Mind of Locke. The Cartesian Impact on Locke’s Philosophical Development”, Descartes: Il Metodo E I Saggi,a cura di Giulia Belgioioso, et. al. (2 vols, Roma, 1990), vol. 2, pp. 689–697.

    Google Scholar 

  29. IV, XI, 3, p.631.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Two Treatises of Government, edited by Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1960), Second Treatise, Section 26, p. 304.

    Google Scholar 

  31. IV, X, 6, p.621.

    Google Scholar 

  32. II, XXVIII, 5, p.351.

    Google Scholar 

  33. II, XXVIII, 8, p.352.

    Google Scholar 

  34. I here follow the William Popple translation of Epistola de Tolerantia,most recently available in A Letter Concerning Toleration in Focus,edited by John Horton and Susan Mendus (London, 1991), p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  35. On this see John Dunn, “The Claim to Freedom of Conscience: Freedom of Speech, Freedom of Thought, Freedom of Worship?”, in From Persecution to Toleration. The Glorious Revolution and Religion in England,edited by Ole Peter Grell, et al. (Oxford, 1991), pp. 171–193 and G.A.J. Rogers, “Locke and the Latitude-men: Ignorance as a ground of Toleration”, in Philosophy, Science and Religion in England,pp. 230–252.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Essay, IV, XII, 11, p. 646.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Some Thoughts Concerning Education, edited by John W. Yolton and Jean S. Yolton, ( Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989 ), pp. 247–8.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid.,p.248.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid.,p.246.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Mr Locke’s Reply to the Bishop of Worcester’s Answer to his Second Letter, The Works of John Locke (10 vols, London, 1823 ), vol. 4, pp. 467–8.

    Google Scholar 

  41. The Correspondence of Isaac Newton,edited by H. W. Turnbull et al. (Cambridge, 19591977) 7 Vols., Vol. 3, p. 233.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Opticks, Dover edition, based on the 4th, 1730 edition (New York, 1952), p.405.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Sir Isaac Newton’s Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy and his System of the World,translated by Andrew Motte and revised by Florian Cajori (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1962) p.398.

    Google Scholar 

  44. The text is published in Frank E. Manuel, The Religion of Isaac Newton (Oxford: Oxford UP, 1974), Appendix A. The passage quoted is on p. 120.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Opticks, ed. cit., p.404.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Principia, ed. cit., p.400.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Manuel, Appendix A, p.121.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Cf. Principles of Philosophy,Part II, Principles 37–39.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rogers, G.A.J. (2001). Nature, Man and God in the English Enlightenment. In: Crocker, R. (eds) Religion, Reason and Nature in Early Modern Europe. Archives Internationales d’histoire des Idées / International Archives of the History of Ideas, vol 180. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9777-7_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9777-7_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5833-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9777-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics