Skip to main content

Part of the book series: The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science ((WONS,volume 25))

Abstract

Professor Laudan’s strictures on the strong programme in the sociology of knowledge do not, I think, call for a defence of that programme so much as a thorough counter-attack. Nevertheless I am grateful to him for raising a range of objections and queries of a kind which are typical of philosophers. I shall therefore combine defence and attack. To ease the burden on the reader I shall discuss Laudan’s points in the order in which he raises them. The only departure from this procedure concerns some general points from the end of his paper that I shall take up immediately. These deal with what Laudan sees as the excessive emphasis on sociological approaches and the neglect of the pragmatic success of science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Arnold Thackray, ‘“The Business of Experimental Philosophy”. The Early Newtonian Group and the Royal Society’, Actes du XXIe Congres International d’Histoire des Sciences, 3, 1970–71, 153–59.

    Google Scholar 

  2. For a valuable analysis of the various responses to this dispute see S. Shapin, ‘Licking Leibniz’ (essay review of A.R. Hall, Philosophers at War), History of Science, Dec. 1981

    Google Scholar 

  3. See for example M.C. Jacob, The Newtonians and the English Revolution, 1689–1720, Ithaca 1976. S. Shapin, ‘Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes’, Isis, 72, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  4. S. Shaffer, Newtonian Cosmology and the Steady State, unpublished PhD thesis, Cambridge University, 1980, Chap. vii.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Mary Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science, Brighton 1980, p. 190. Mary Hesse, The Structure of Scientific Inference, London 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  6. P. Forman, ‘Weimar Culture, Causality and Quantum Theory, 1918–1927. Adaptation by German Physicists and Mathematics to a Hostile Intellectual Environment’, in R. McCormmach, ed., Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, vol. 3, 1971, 1–115.

    Google Scholar 

  7. P. Duhem, The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, trans. P.P. Wiener, Princeton 1954.

    Google Scholar 

  8. J. Farley and G.L. Geison, ‘Science, Politics and Spontaneous Generation in Nineteenth Century France: The Pasteur-Pouchet Debate’, Bulletin of the History of Medicine, 48, 1974, 161–98.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Dov Ospovat, ‘Perfect Adaptation and Teleological Explanation: Approaches to the Problem of the History of Life in the Mid-nineteenth Century’, Studies in the History of Biology, 2, 1978, 33–56.

    Google Scholar 

  10. J. Dean, ‘Controversy Over Classification: A Case Study from the History of Botany’, in B. Barnes and S. Shapin (eds.). Natural Order, Historical Studies of Scientific Culture, Beverly Hills and London 1979, Chap. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  11. For example see D. MacKenzie, ‘Statistical Theory and Social Interests: A Case Study’, Social Studies of Science, 8, 1978, 35–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. S. Shapin, ‘The Politics of Observation: Cerebral Anatomy and Social Interes in the Edinburgh Phrenology Disputes’, in R. Wallis (ed.). On the Margins ot Science: The Social Construction of Rejected Knowledge, Sociological Review Monographs, 27, 1979, pp. 139–78.

    Google Scholar 

  13. S. Shapin, ‘Phrenological Knowledge and the Social Structure of Early Nineteenth-century Edinburgh’, Annals of Science, 32, 1975, 219–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. E. Frankel, ‘Corpuscular Optics and the Wave Theory of Light: The Science and Politics of a Revolution in Physics’, Social Studies of Science, 6, 1976, 141–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. J. Harwood, ‘The Race-Intelligence Controversy: A Sociological Approach. I - Professional Factors; II -External Factors’, Social Studies of Science, 6, 1976, 369–94;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. J. Harwood, ‘The Race-Intelligence Controversy: A Sociological Approach. I - Professional Factors; II -External Factors’, Social Studies of Science 7, 1977, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. R.S. Turner, ‘The Growth of Professorial Research in Prussia, 1818–1848 — Causes and Contexts’, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 3, 1971, 137–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. R.S. Turner, ‘University Reformers and Professorial Scholarship in Germany, 1760–1806’, in L. Stone (ed.), The University in Society, Oxford 1975, vol. ii, 195–531.

    Google Scholar 

  19. G. Allen, ‘Naturalists and Experimentalists: The Genotype and the Phenotype’, Studies in the History of Biology, 3, 1979, 179–209.

    Google Scholar 

  20. T. Brown, ‘The College of Physicians and the Acceptance of Iatromechanism in England, 1665–1695’. Bulletin of the History of Medicine, 44, 1970, 12–30.

    Google Scholar 

  21. T. Brown, ‘From Mechanism to Vitalism in Eighteenth-Century English Physiology’, Journal of the History of Biology, 7, 1974, 179–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. D.W. Hamlyn, The Psychology of Perception, London 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  23. K. Koffka, Principles of Gestalt Psychology, London 1936, p. 76.

    Google Scholar 

  24. L. Laudan, Progress and Its Problems, Towards a Theory of Scientific Growth, London 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  25. For a fuller account of why I speak of a contrast between causal and teleological styles of explanation, and my reasons for imputing teleological theories to Lakatos and others who treat rationality as a self-propelling phenomenon, see D. Bloor, ‘Wittgenstein and Mannheim on the Sociology of Mathematics’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 4, 1973, 173–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. I have taken the term ‘natural rationality’ from S.B. Barnes, ‘Natural Rationality: A Neglected Concept in the Social Sciences’, Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 6, 1976,115–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. R.L. Gregory, Concepts and Mechanisms of Perception, London 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  28. E.E. Evans-Pritchard, Witchcraft, Oracles and Magic Among the Azande, Oxford, 1937.

    Google Scholar 

  29. As evidence that this confusion is endemic and does not merely represent a momentary lapse, see the following review of Laudan’s book: S.B. Barnes, ‘Vicissitudes of Belief’, Social Studies of Science, 9, 1979, 247–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. As well as the previous references to their work, see B. Barnes, Interests and the Growth of Knowledge, London 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  31. D. Mackenzie, Statistics in Britain, 1865–1930. The Social Construction of Scientific Knowledge, Edinburgh 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  32. S. Shapin, ‘Social Uses of Science’, in G. Rousseau and R. Porter (eds.). The Ferment of Knowledge: Studies in the Historiography of Eighteenth-century Science, Cambridge 1980. Also, the very valuable collection of papers in B. Barnes and S. Shapin (eds.), Natural Order: Historical Studies of Scientific Culture, op. cit., note 9, above.

    Google Scholar 

  33. M. Hesse, The Structure of Scientific Inference, op. cit., note 4, Chapters 1 and 2.

    Google Scholar 

  34. D. Bloor, ‘Polyhedra and the Abominations of Leviticus’, British Journal for the History of Science, 11, 1978, 245–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. This is a sociological reading of I. Lakatos’brilliant book Proofs and Refutations: The Logic of Mathematical Discovery, Cambridge 1976.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  36. Hesse’s network model was designed, in part, to attack the empiricist idea of an independent observation language. It explains why all predicates are ‘theory-laden’ by showing that they all depend on a negotiable ‘network’. But at the same time this explains why it is correct to equate the theoretical aspect of knowledge with its social aspect. This is because examination of the model shows that the network is a set of conventions.

    Google Scholar 

  37. D. Bloor, ‘Klassifikation und Wissenssoziologie: Durkheim and Mauss neu betrachtet’, in N. Stehr und V. Meja (Hrsg.), Wissenssoziologie-Studien und Materialen, Sonderheft 22 der Kolner Zeitschrift fur Sozioloqie und Sozialpsychologie, Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  38. An English version will, I hope, be published before too long. In this paper I develop the ideas first formulated in my review of Hesse’s Structure of Scientific Inference, D. Bloor, ‘Epistemology or Psychology?’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 6, 1975, 382–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. The slogan comes of course from E. Durkheim, and M. Mauss, Primitive Classification, trans. R. Needham, London 1963, p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  40. The materials from the history of science that I have used to illustrate the network model and, in particular, its capacity to provide a new theoretical underpinning for Durkheim and Mauss’s ideas, is taken from the growing literature on Boyle and Newton’s corpuscular philosophy. This work is one of the best sustained studies in the sociology of knowledge that is currently available. For a small sample see, for instance: P.M. Rattansi, ‘Paracelsus and the Puritan Revolution’, Ambix, 11, 1963, 24–32;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. P.M. Rattansi, ‘The Intellectual Origins of the Royal Society’, Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London, 23, 1968, 129–43;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. J.R. Jacob, ‘The Ideological Origins of Robert Boyle’s Natural Philosophy’, Journal of European Studies, 2, 1972, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. J. R. Jacob, ‘Robert Boyle and Subversive Religion in the Early Restoration’, Albior, 6, 1974, 175–93;

    Google Scholar 

  44. J.R. Jacob, ‘Boyle’s Atomism and the Restoration Assault on Pagan Naturalism’, Social Studies of Science, 8, 1978, 211–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. I realize, that my critic has shown that he is aware of some of this literature by his brief discussion of Forman, Shapin and Brown in his book. But instead of putting the cases that he considers in their proper context, he considers them in isolation and produces ad hoc responses to them. This is of course always possible, and is simply a technique for evading the cumulative significance of a growing body of work. This method of response is well illustrated by his reply to the valuable work that has been done on the reception of the mechanical philosophy. ‘It might just be that Walter Charleton accepted the mechanical philosophy because — as he explains in 400 turgid pages — that theory was rationally preferable to its alternatives’. Yes it might, especially if you make sure that you use an historically relevant criterion of rationality. But when you have found out what Charleton thought it was rational to take into account, and when you have explained why Charleton’s judgements differed from those of others around him — and his own earlier views — you will have engaged in the very exercise that Laudan is criticizing. If, on the other hand, there are ahistorical criteria that explain the changes, then why not give the rival account, rather than just say that it might exist?

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1984 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bloor, D. (1984). The Strengths of the Strong Programme. In: Scientific Rationality: The Sociological Turn. The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol 25. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7688-8_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7688-8_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-8403-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-7688-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics