Skip to main content

William James’s Concept of the Stream of Thought Phenomenologically Interpreted

  • Chapter
Collected Papers III

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 22))

Abstract

Future historians of philosophy will certainly agree that it was mainly the thought of three thinkers which helped to remodel the contemporary style of philosophizing: James, Bergson, and Husserl. Although from the beginning of their activity James and Bergson found themselves attracted to each other, entered into correspondence, and met personally several times, there is no reference in James’s books or in his correspondence to Husserl’s Logische Untersuchungen (1900–1901). On the other hand, we know Husserl’s admiration for James’s Principles of Psychology, which he studied carefully with the intention of writing a critical review for a German philosophical journal — a project never realized. Certainly such a document from Husserl’s pen would have opened for all friends of James’s psychology the best approach to Husserl’s own thought.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Reference

  1. Preface to the Italian translation of Principles, quoted by Ralph Barton Perry, The Thought and Character of William James, Boston, 1935, Vol. II, p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  2. The Principles of Psychology, New York, 1893, Vol. I, p. 185

    Google Scholar 

  3. Principles, Vol. I, p. 226.

    Google Scholar 

  4. As Professor John Dewey states in his impressive study, “ The Vanishing Subject in the Psychology of James” (Journal of Philosophy, Vol. XXXVII, 1940, pp. 589–599), “There is a double strain in the Principles of Psychology of William James. One strain is official acceptance of epistemological dualism. According to this view, the science of psychology centers about a subject which is ‘mental’ just as physics centers about an object which is material. But James’s analysis of special topics tends, on the contrary, to reduction of the subject to a vanishing point, save as ‘subject’ is identified with the organism, the latter, moreover, having no existence save in interaction with environing conditions. According to the latter strain, subject and object do not stand for separate orders or kinds of existence but at most for certain distinctions made for a definite purpose within experience” (op. cit., p. 589). Professor Dewey quotes different passages of James’s work, proving that both views can be found therein and that the equivocal account given by James of the nature of the self and our consciousness of it is, above all, the source of the controversy. It may be admitted that Professor Dewey’s interpretation leading to reduction of the subject to a vanishing point corresponds in a higher degree to James’s later philosophy than the dualistic view. But even Professor Dewey agrees that the important chapter on the “stream of consciousness” is verbally the most subjectivistic part of the whole book and he comments on this statement in a footnote as follows: “I say ‘verbally’ because it is quite possible to translate ‘stream of consciousness’ into [the ongoing], ‘course of experience’ [‘of experienced things’] and retain the substance of the chapter.” The present paper, limiting its topic to James’s concept of the stream of thought, neglects intentionally the second strain emphasized by Professor Dewey and deals exclusively with the first, the subjective one.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Principles, Vol. I, pp. 370, 400 f. Cf. footnote 4.

    Google Scholar 

  6. E. Husserl, “Phenomenology,” Encyclopaedia Britannica, 14th ed.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Vol. I, p. 184.

    Google Scholar 

  8. E. Husserl, Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology, translated by Boyce Gibson, § 36.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. for this problem, Husserl, Ideas, § 3 ff. (and see the author’s “Some Leading Concepts of Phenomenology,’’ Collected Papers, Vol. I.)

    Google Scholar 

  10. “Phenomenology,” op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ralph Barton Perry, The Thought and Character of William James, Vol. II, p. 75–13 Principles, Vol. I, p. 240. In a specific footnote James refers here to the Psychology (Vol. I, pp. 219–220) of Franz Brentano (the teacher of Edmund Husserl) and says: “Altogether this chapter of Brentano’s on the unity of consciousness is as good as anything with which I am acquainted.”

    Google Scholar 

  12. Principles, Vol. I, p. 245. It must be remembered that James uses the term “feeling” as synonymous with “thought” and consciousness. Cf. Vol. I, p. 186.

    Google Scholar 

  13. In Husserl’s Erfahrung und Urteil (Part I, Chapter III) it is even treated under the caption “Experience and Relation.”

    Google Scholar 

  14. Principles, Vol. I, p. 221.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Principles, Vol. I, p. 459.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cf. also Principles, Vol. I, p. 272: “Sameness in a multiplicity of objective appearances is thus the basis of our belief in realities outside of thought.”

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ideas, § 86.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. Ideas, § 82. Professor Boyce Gibson, the English translator, has chosen the term “fringe” here for Husserl’s term “Horizont” (horizon) and has by this translation alone anticipated our whole topic.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Principles, Vol. I, pp. 608 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Principles, Vol. I, pp. 259 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. R. B. Perry, op. cit., Vol. II, pp. 75 ff.; Principles, Vol. I, pp. 275 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  22. We have neglected entirely, e. g., the function of the “topic” as “grammatical subject” and the problem of a general grammar based on the concept of fringes. According to James, a feeling of “and,” of “if,” of “by,” also pertains to the fringe relation (Principles, Vol. I, pp. 245 f.). * See Collected Papers, Vol. I, pp. 112–113, 274 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Principles, Vol. I, p. 260.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., p. 271.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ideas, pp. 118 f.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Principles, Vol. I, p. 472.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

I. Schutz

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1970 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schutz, A. (1970). William James’s Concept of the Stream of Thought Phenomenologically Interpreted. In: Schutz, I. (eds) Collected Papers III. Phaenomenologica, vol 22. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-3456-7_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-3456-7_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-015-2220-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-3456-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics