Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Theory and Decision Library ((TDLA,volume 5))

  • 251 Accesses

Abstract

In the previous chapter I came to the point that the general distribution problem is considered an optimization problem, with a chosen or designed social welfare function as the objective function. An optimization problem necessarily has some constraint(s), which is a preset condition(s) that has to be satisfied. Philosophers sometimes do not emphasize these mathematical details. Since I incorporate the general distribution problem into the quantitative maximization problem of social utility, it seems essential to identify the constraint. In fact, welfare economists have already set a constraint on this distribution problem, although, as will be discussed later, I do not consider it satisfactory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. John Ralws, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 75–80.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Yew-Kwang Ng, Welfare Economics (New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1980), p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid., p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  4. The material in Section 11.3 has been presented in the following paper. C. L. Sheng, “Comments on Rawls’ Difference Principle As a Criterion for Distribution,” presented at the Third World Congress on Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, Kobe, Japan, August 20-26, 1987; also to be published in a volume of selected papers for the congress.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See Note 1. p. 75.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Robert Paul Wolf, “A Refutation of Rawl’s Theory of Justice,” The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 63, No. 7 (March 1966).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Dan W. Brock, “Contratualism, Utilitarianism, and Social Inequalities,” Social Theory and Practice, Vol. 1, No. 3 (Spring 1971), pp. 33–44.

    Google Scholar 

  8. J. E. J. Altham, “Rawls’s Difference Principle,” Philosophy, Vol. 48 (1973), pp. 75–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Scott Gordon, “John Rawls’s Difference Principle, Utilitarianism, and the Optimum Degree of Inequality,” The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 70 (May 1973), pp. 275–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. T. M. Scanlon, “Rawls’ Theory of Justice,” in Reading Rawls: Critical Studies of A theory of Justice, ed. Norman Daniels (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1975), p. 205.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Amartya K. Sen, “Rawls versus Bentham: An Axiomatic Examination of the Pure Distribution Problem,” in Reading Rawls: Critical Studies of A theory of Justice, pp. 284–291.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Benjamin B. Barber, “Justifying Justice: Problem of Psychology, Politics and Measurement in Rawls,” in Reading Rawls: Critical Studies of A Theory of Justice, pp. 292–318.

    Google Scholar 

  13. John C. Harsanyi, “Can the Maximin Principle Serve As a Basis for Morality? A critique of John Rawls’ Theory,” American Political Science Review, Vol. 59 (1975), pp. 594–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. See Note 1, p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See Note 9, p. 277.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid., p. 279.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See Note 1, p. 76.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Note 9, p. 278.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See Note 2, p. 148. Fig. 11.3-4 is reproduced from Yew-Kwang Ng’s Fig. 6.1 on p. 148.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., pp. 38, 147.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., p. 148.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See Note 13.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See Note 2, p. 151.

    Google Scholar 

  25. The maximization of utility coincides with the choice based on the maximin principle only when a very special welfare function is used. For instance, let where α < 1, α O. Then as α →-∞, SWF comes to depend solely on the income of the poorest person. See, for instance, P. R. G. Layard and A. A. Walters, Microeconomic Theory (New York: McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1978), p. 48.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Amartya K. Sen, On Economic Inequality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973), pp. 24–46.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  27. Nicholas Rescher, Distributive Justice: A Critique of the Utilitarian Theory of Distribution (Indianapolis, Indiana: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, 1966), p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  28. L. H. Powers, “A More Effective Average: A Note on Distributive Justice,” Philosophical Studies, Vol. 24 (1970), pp. 74–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. See Note 27, p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., p. 90.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid., pp. 40-41.

    Google Scholar 

  32. See Note 28.

    Google Scholar 

  33. See Note 27.

    Google Scholar 

  34. See Note 28.

    Google Scholar 

  35. The material in Section 11.6 has been presented in the following paper. C. L. Sheng, “Utilitarianism Is Not Indifferent to Distribution,” presented at the Fourth International Conference on Social Philosophy, Oxford, U.K., August 16-19, 1988; also to be published in Rights, Justice, and Community (The Edwin Meilen Press).

    Google Scholar 

  36. See Note 1, p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  37. J. L. Mackie, “Rights, Utility, and Universalization,” in Utility and Rights, ed., R. G. Frey (Minneaplis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, 1984), pp. 86–105.

    Google Scholar 

  38. H. J. McCloskey, “Respect for Human Moral Rights versus Maximizing Good,” in Utility and Rights, pp. 121–36.

    Google Scholar 

  39. John Gray, “Indirect Utility and Fundamental Rights,” Social Philosophy and Policy, Vol 1, Issue 2 (Spring 1985), pp. 73–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. For instance, David Gauthier writes, “Value, as understood here, is identical with utility.” See David Gauthier, “On the Refutation of Utilitarianism,” in The Limits of Utilitarianism, ed. Harlen B. Miller and William H. Williams (Minneapolis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), pp. 144-63.

    Google Scholar 

  41. See Note 1.

    Google Scholar 

  42. In Chapter 17 I shall show that, if two persons A and B have the same utility function U(V) but A deserves cA/B times as much as B deserves, then it is justified to adopt a social welfare function (for the society of two members A and B) of the form

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  44. R. G. Frey, “Introduction: Utilitarianism and Persons,” in Utility and Rights, pp. 3–19.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  46. D. G. Brown, “Mill’s Criterion of Wrong Conduct,” Dialogue, Vol. 21 (1982), pp. 27–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1991 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sheng, C.L. (1991). The Constraint. In: A New Approach to Utilitarianism. Theory and Decision Library, vol 5. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3192-6_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3192-6_11

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-5408-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-3192-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics