Skip to main content

The Measurement Problem in Physics, Computation, and Brain Theories

  • Chapter
Nature, Cognition and System II

Part of the book series: Theory and Decision Library ((TDLD,volume 10))

Abstract

Two types of brain model are currently the center of a fundamental controversy in cognitive science. Traditional artificial intelligence models are based on the discrete, programmable symbol systems normally associated with Turing/von Neumann computation, and for which language and logic are the essential tools. This type of model is now being challenged by the rebirth of concurrent, distributed networks that are based on analog models of physical systems, and that also claim some similarity to neural architecture. In the former, discrete symbols are local, sequential, and rewritten under total program control. In the latter, symbols are only the end result of coherent network dynamics that need little explicit program control. The behavior of these networks is determined by the constraints within the network and the initial conditions. In this respect, network behavior is functionally similar to a complex measurement process, since measurement in physics discriminates and classifies implicate dynamical patterns by mapping them to explicit symbols. But what determines when a measurement is completed is an unresolved problem in physics, especially in quantum theory. It involves complementary modes of description, one based on the rate-dependent, continuous, time-symmetric dynamics of inexorable physical laws, and the other based on the rate-independent, discrete, irreversible constraints of programmable symbol systems. In physics, these modes are both distinguished and related only by measurement, but when a measurement occurs appears to be a matter of arbitrary choice. The brain uses many complementary modes of description, and must constantly choose among them, but the ultimate nature of this choice remains a problem.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Bohr, N. (1934) Atomic Theory and the Description of Nature, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1949) Discussions with Einstein on epistemological problems in atomic physics, in Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, P. A. Schilpp, ed. Library of Living Philosophers, Evanston, Illinois.

    Google Scholar 

  • Born, M. (1964) Symbol and reality, in The Natural Philosophy of Cause and Chance, M. Born, Dover, New York, Appendix 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad, M. (1988) The brain-machine disanalogy, BioSystems 22 197–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowan, J. and Sharp, D. H. (1988) Neural nets and artificial intelligence, Dædalus 117, 85–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delbrück, M. (1986) Mind from Matter, Blackwell Scientific Publications, Palo Alto, California.

    Google Scholar 

  • d’Espagnat, B. (1983) In Search of Reality, Springer-Verlag, Berlin.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Witt, B. and Graham, R. B. (1973) The Many Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1985) Précis of Modularity of Mind, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8, 1–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. and Pylyshyn, Z. (1988) Connectionism and cognitive architecture, in Connections and Symbols, S. Pinker and J. Mehler eds., MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, pp. 3–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979) The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception, Houghton-Mifflin, Boston, Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herbert, N. (1985) Quantum Reality, Anchor/Doubleday, Garden City, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kugler, P. and Turvey, M. (1987) Information, Natural Law, and the Self-assembly of Rhythmic Movement, Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, New Jersey.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A. (1980) Physical Symbol Systems, Cognitive Science 4, 135–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. H. (1967) Quantum mechanics, heredity, and the origin of life, J. Theoretical Biology 17, 410–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. H. (1979) The complementarity principle and the origin of macromolecular information, BioSystems 11, 217–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. H. (1982) Cell psychology: an evolutionary approach to the symbol-matter problem, Cognition and Brain Theory 5, 325–341

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. H (1985) Universal principles of measurement and language function in evolving systems, in Complexity, Language and Life: Mathematical Approaches, J. Casti and A. Karlqvist, eds., Springer-Verlag, Berlin, pp. 268–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1989) The Emperor’s New Mind, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1984) Cognition and Computation, MIT Press, Cambridge Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolensky, P. (1988) On the proper treatment of connectionism, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11, 1–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skarda, C. A. and Freeman, W. J. (1987) How brains make chaos in in order to make sense of the world, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10, 161–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toffoli, T. (1982) Physics and Computation, International J. of Theoretical Physics 21, 165–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J. (1955) Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J. A. and Zurek, W. H. Quantum Theory and Measurement, Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J. A. (1982) Bohr, Einstein, and the strange lesson of the quantum, in Mind in Nature, R. Q. Elvee, ed., Harper & Row, San Francisco, California, pp. 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. (1960) The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences, Communications in Pure and Applied Mathematics 13, 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. (1964) Events, laws, and invariance principles, Science 145, 995–999.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. (1982) The limitations of the validity of present-day physics, in Mind in Nature, R. Q. Elvee, ed., Harper & Row, San Francisco, California, pp.118–133.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1992 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Pattee, H.H. (1992). The Measurement Problem in Physics, Computation, and Brain Theories. In: Carvallo, M.E. (eds) Nature, Cognition and System II. Theory and Decision Library, vol 10. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-2779-0_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-2779-0_10

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-5234-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-2779-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics